Skip to main content

Full text of "The science of mechanics; a critical and historical exposition of its principles"

See other formats


Google 


This  is  a  digital  copy  of  a  book  that  was  preserved  for  generations  on  library  shelves  before  it  was  carefully  scanned  by  Google  as  part  of  a  project 

to  make  the  world's  books  discoverable  online. 

It  has  survived  long  enough  for  the  copyright  to  expire  and  the  book  to  enter  the  public  domain.  A  public  domain  book  is  one  that  was  never  subject 

to  copyright  or  whose  legal  copyright  term  has  expired.  Whether  a  book  is  in  the  public  domain  may  vary  country  to  country.  Public  domain  books 

are  our  gateways  to  the  past,  representing  a  wealth  of  history,  culture  and  knowledge  that's  often  difficult  to  discover. 

Marks,  notations  and  other  maiginalia  present  in  the  original  volume  will  appear  in  this  file  -  a  reminder  of  this  book's  long  journey  from  the 

publisher  to  a  library  and  finally  to  you. 

Usage  guidelines 

Google  is  proud  to  partner  with  libraries  to  digitize  public  domain  materials  and  make  them  widely  accessible.  Public  domain  books  belong  to  the 
public  and  we  are  merely  their  custodians.  Nevertheless,  this  work  is  expensive,  so  in  order  to  keep  providing  tliis  resource,  we  liave  taken  steps  to 
prevent  abuse  by  commercial  parties,  including  placing  technical  restrictions  on  automated  querying. 
We  also  ask  that  you: 

+  Make  non-commercial  use  of  the  files  We  designed  Google  Book  Search  for  use  by  individuals,  and  we  request  that  you  use  these  files  for 
personal,  non-commercial  purposes. 

+  Refrain  fivm  automated  querying  Do  not  send  automated  queries  of  any  sort  to  Google's  system:  If  you  are  conducting  research  on  machine 
translation,  optical  character  recognition  or  other  areas  where  access  to  a  large  amount  of  text  is  helpful,  please  contact  us.  We  encourage  the 
use  of  public  domain  materials  for  these  purposes  and  may  be  able  to  help. 

+  Maintain  attributionTht  GoogXt  "watermark"  you  see  on  each  file  is  essential  for  in  forming  people  about  this  project  and  helping  them  find 
additional  materials  through  Google  Book  Search.  Please  do  not  remove  it. 

+  Keep  it  legal  Whatever  your  use,  remember  that  you  are  responsible  for  ensuring  that  what  you  are  doing  is  legal.  Do  not  assume  that  just 
because  we  believe  a  book  is  in  the  public  domain  for  users  in  the  United  States,  that  the  work  is  also  in  the  public  domain  for  users  in  other 
countries.  Whether  a  book  is  still  in  copyright  varies  from  country  to  country,  and  we  can't  offer  guidance  on  whether  any  specific  use  of 
any  specific  book  is  allowed.  Please  do  not  assume  that  a  book's  appearance  in  Google  Book  Search  means  it  can  be  used  in  any  manner 
anywhere  in  the  world.  Copyright  infringement  liabili^  can  be  quite  severe. 

About  Google  Book  Search 

Google's  mission  is  to  organize  the  world's  information  and  to  make  it  universally  accessible  and  useful.   Google  Book  Search  helps  readers 
discover  the  world's  books  while  helping  authors  and  publishers  reach  new  audiences.  You  can  search  through  the  full  text  of  this  book  on  the  web 

at|http: //books  .google  .com/I 


i 


Q/9 

H\s- 

/fT3 


l 


^t 


THE   SCIENCE   OF   MECHANICS 


THE 


SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS 


A    CRITICAL  AND   HISTORICAL   EXPOSITION 

OF   ITS   PRINCIPLES 


■  BY 

DR.    ERNST    MACH 
Propbssor  op  Physics  in  thb  Universitv  op  Pracub 


TRANSLATED  FROM  THE  SECOND  GERMAN  EDITION 

BY 

THOMAS    J.    McCORMACK 


%  BY 


Wrm  TWO   HUNDRBD   AND    PIPTY   CUTS   AND   ILLUSTRATIONS 


CHICAGO 
THE   OPEN   COURT   PUBLISHING   CO. 

1893 


Copyright  1893, 

BY 

Thb  Opkm  Coukt  Pubushinc  Ca 


•  •  • 


V\' 


fit'  Littcsific  ^irsf 

R.  R.  DONNELLEY  *  SONS  CO..  CHICAGO 


i 


TRANSLATOR'S  PREFACE. 


ERRATA. 

•      Page  140. — Lines  i  and  2  from  top,  for  its  perptndicular  read  the  vertical. 

Page  14a. — Last  line,  read  no  force  for  a  force. 

Page  277.— Between  the  third  and  fourth  lines  from  the  bottom  insert  the 
following:  "employed  as  the  anit  of  mass,  an  arbitrary  length  is." 

Page  283  — Line  13  from  bottom,  read  jr^^o/A  for  S26oth. 

Page  337. — Line  9  from  bottom,  for  perpendicular  read  vertical. 

Page  398.— Line  5  from  bottom,  read  Xdx  for  Xdz. 


all  the  proofs  and  has  rewritten  §  8  in  the  chapter  on 
Units  and  Measures,  where  the  original  was  inappli- 
cable to  this  country  and  slightly  out  of  date. 

Thomas  J.  McCormack. 
La  Salle,  III.,  June  28,  1893. 


R.  R.  DONNELLEY  *  SONS  CO..  CHICAGO 


TRANSLATOR'S  PREFACE. 

The  Open  Court  Publishing  Company  has*acquired 
the  sole  right  of  English  translation  of  this  work, 
which  in  its  German   original   formed  a  volume  of 
the  Internationale  wissenschaftliche  Bibliothek,  of  F.  A. 
BrockhauSy  of  Leipsic. 

In  the  reproduction,  many  textual  errors  and  ir- 
regularities have  been  corrected,  marginal  titles  have 
been  inserted,  and  the  index  has  been  amplified.  It 
is  believed  that  the  usefulness  of  the  book  has  thus 
been  increased. 

No  pains  have  been  spared  to  render  the  author's 
meaning  clearly  and  faithfully.  In  this,  it  has  often 
been  necessary  to  depart  widely  from  the  form  of  the 
original,  but  never,  it  is  hoped,  from  its  spirit. 

The  thanks  of  the  translator  are  due  to  Mr.  C.  S. 
Peirce,  well  known  for  his  studies  both  of  analytical 
mechanics  and  of  the  history  and  logic  of  physics,  for 
numerous  suggestions  and  notes.  Mr.  Peirce  has  read 
all  the  proofs  and  has  rewritten  §  8  in  the  chapter  on 
Units  and  Measures,  where  the  original  was  inappli- 
cable to  this  country  and  slightly  out  of  date. 

Thomas  J.  McCormack. 

La  Salle,  III.,  June  28,  1893. 


AUTHOR'S  PREFACE  TO  THE  TRANS- 
LATION. 

■ 

Having  read  the  proofs  of  the  present  translation 
of  my  work,  Die  Mechanik  in  ihrer  Eniwickelungy  I  can 
testify  that  the  publishers  have  supplied  an  excellent, 
accurate,  and  faithful  rendering  of  it,  as  their  previous 
translations  of  essays  of  mine  gave  me  every  reason  to 
expect.  My  thanks  are  due  to  all  concerned,  and 
especially  to  Mr.  McCormack,  whose  intelligent  care 
in  the  conduct  of  the  translation  has  led  to  the  dis- 
covery of  many  errors,  heretofore  overlooked.  I  may, 
thus,  confidently  hope,  that  the  rise  and  growth  of  the 
ideas  of  the  great  inquirers,  which  it  was  my  task  to 
portray,  will  appear  to  my  new  public  in  distinct  and 
sharp  outlines.  E.  Mach. 

Prague,  April  8th,  1893. 


r 


PREFACE  TO  THE  FIRST  EDITION. 

■ 

The  present  volume  is  not  a  treatise  upon  the  ap- 
plication of  the  principles  of  mechanics.  Its  aim  is 
to  clear  up  ideas,  expose  the  real  significance  of  the 
matter,  and  get  rid  of  metaphysical  obscurities.  The 
little  mathematics  it  contains  is  merely  secondary  to 
this  purpose. 

Mechanics  will  here  be  treated,  not  as  a  branch  of 
mathematics,  but  as  one  of  the  physical  sciences.  If 
the  reader's  interest  is  in  that  side  of  the  subject,  if  he 
is  curious  to  know  how  the  principles  of  mechanics 
have  been  ascertained,  from  what  sources  they  take 
their  origin,  and  how  far  they  can  be  regarded  as  per- 
manent acquisitions,  he  will  find,  I  hope,  in  these 
pages  some  enlightenment.  All  this,  the  positive  and 
physical  essence  of  mechanics,  which  makes  its  chief 
and  highest  interest  for  a  student  of  nature,  is  in  exist- 
ing treatises  completely  buried  and  concealed  beneath 
a  mass  of  technical  considerations. 

The  gist  and  kernel  of  mechanical  ideas  has  in  al- 
most every  case  grown  up  in  the  investigation  of  very 
simple  and  special  cases  of  mechanical  processes  ;  and 
the  analysis  of  the  history  of  the  discussions  concern- 


VIII  PREFACE  TO  THE  FIRST  EDITION. 

ing  these  cases  must  ever  remain  the  method  at  once 
the  most  effective  and  the  most  natural  for  laying  this 
gist  and  kernel  bare.  Indeed,  it  is  not  too  much  to 
say  that  it  is  the  only  way  in  which  a  real  comprehen- 
sion of  the  general  upshot  of  mechanics  is  to  be  at- 
tained. 

I  have  framed  my  exposition  of  the  subject  agree- 
ably to  these  views.  It  is  perhaps  a  little  long,  but,  on 
the  other  hand,  I  trust  that  it  is  clear.  I  have  not  in 
every  case  been  able  to  avoid  the  use  of  the  abbrevi- 
ated and  precise  terminology  of  mathematics.  To  do 
so  would  have  been  to  sacrifice  matter  to  form  \  for  the 
language  of  everyday  life  has  not  yet  grown  to  be  suf- 
ficiently accurate  for  the  purposes  of  so  exact  a  science 
as  mechanics. 

The  elucidations  which  I  here  offer  are,  in  part, 
substantially  contained  in  my  treatise,  Die  Geschichte 
und  die  Wurzel  des  Satzes  von  der  Erhaltung  der  Arbeit 
(Prague,  Calve,  1872).  At  a  later  date  nearly  the  same 
views  were  expressed  by  Kirchhoff  (  Vorlesungen  Uber 
mathematische  Physik:  Mechanik^  Leipsic,  1874)  and  by 
Helmholtz  ^Die  Thatsachen  in  der  Wahrnehmung^ 
Berlin,  1879),  and  have  since  become  commonplace 
enough.  Still  the  matter,  as  I  conceive  it,  does  not 
seem  to'  have  been  exhausted,  and  I  cannot  deem  my 
exposition  to  be  at  all  superfluous. 

In  my  fundamental  conception  of  the  nature  of  sci- 
ence as  Economy  of  Thought, — a  view  which  I  in- 
dicated both  in  the  treatise  above  cited  and  in  my 


PREFACE  TO  THE  FIRST  EDITION,  ix 

pamphlet,  Die  Gestalten  der  Flussigkeit  (Prague,  Calve, 
1872),  and  which  I  somewhat  more  extensively  devel- 
oped in  my  academical  memorial  address.  Die  okono- 
mische  Natur  der  physikalischen  Forschung  (Vienna,  Ce- 
roid, 1882, — I  no  longer  stand  alone.  I  have  been 
much  gratified  to  find  closely  allied  ideas  developed, 
in  an  original  manner,  by  Dr.  R.  Avenarius  {Philoso- 
phie  als  Denken  der  Welt,  gerndss  detn  Princip  des  klein- 
sten  Kra/tmaasses,  Leipsic,  Fues,  1876).  Regard  for 
the  true  endeavor  of  philosophy,  that  of  guiding  into 
one  common  stream  the  many  rills  of  knowledge,  will 
not  be  found  wanting  in  my  work,  although  it  takes  a 
determined  stand  against  the  encroachments  of  meta- 
physical methods. 

The  questions  here  dealt  with  have  occupied  me 
since  my  earliest  youth,  when  my  interest  for  them  was 
powerfully  stimulated  by  the  beautiful  introductions  of 
Lagrange  to  the  chapters  of  his  Analytic  Mechanics,  as 
well  as  by  the  lucid  and  lively  tract  of  Jolly,  Principien 
der  Mechanik  (Stuttgart,  1852).  If  Duehring's  esti- 
mable work,  Kritische  Geschichte  der  Principien  der  Me- 
chanik (Berlin,  1873),  did  not  particularly  influence 
me,  it  was  that  at  the  time  of  its  appearance,  my  ideas 
had  been  not  only  substantially  worked  out,  but  actually 
published.  Nevertheless,  the  reader  will,  at  least  on 
the  destructive  side,  find  many  points  of  agreement 
between  Dtihring's  criticisms  and  those  here  expressed. 

The  new  apparatus  for  the  illustration  of  the  sub- 
ject, here  figured  and  described,  were  designed  entirely 


X  PREFACE  TO  THE  FIRST  EDITION. 

by  me  and  constructed  by  Mr.  F.  Hajek,  the  mechani- 
cian of  the  physical  institute  under  my  control. 

In  less  immediate  connection  with  the  text  stand 
the  fac-simile  reproductions  of  old  originals  in  my  pos- 
session. The  quaint  and  naive  traits  of  the  great  in- 
quirers, which  find  in  them  their  expression,  have  al- 
ways exerted  upon  me  a  refreshing  influence  in  my 
studies,  and  I  have  desired  that  my  readers  should 
share  this  pleasure  with  me. 

E.  Mach. 

Prague,  May,  1883. 


PREFACE  TO  THE  SECOND  EDITION. 

In  consequence  of  the  kind  reception  which  this 
book  has  met  with,  a  very  large  edition  has  been  ex- 
hausted in  less  than  iive  years.  This  circumstance  and 
the  treatises  that  have  since  then  appeared  of  E.  Wohl- 
will,  H.  Streintz,  L.  Lange,  J.  Epstein,  F.  A.  Miiller, 
J.  Popper,  G.  Helm,  M.  Planck,  F.  Poske,  and  others 
are  evidence  of  the  gratifying  fact  that  at  the  present 
day  questions  relating  to  the  theory  of  cognition  are 
pursued  with  interest,  which  twenty  years  ago  scarcely 
anybody  noticed. 

As  a  thoroughgoing  revision  of  my  work  did  not 
yet  seem  to  me  to  be  expedient,  I  have  restricted  my- 
self, so  far  as  the  text  is  concerned,  to  the  correction 
of  typographical  errors,  and  have  referred  to  the  works 
that  have  appeared  since  its  original  publication,  as 
far  as  possible,  in  a  few  appendices. 

E.  Mach. 
Prague,  June,  1888. 


TABLE  OF  CONTENTS. 

PAOB 

Translator's  Preface v 

Anthor's  Preface  to  the  Translation vi 

Preface  to  the  First  Edition vii 

Preface  to  the  Second  Edition xi 

Table  of  Contents xiii 

Introduction I 

CHAPTER  I. 

THE   DEVELOPMENT  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS. 

I.     The  Principle  of  the  Lever 8 

II.  The  Principle  of  the  Inclined  Plane 24 

III.  The  Principle  of  the  Composition  of  Forces  .     .     .     .     33 

IV.  The  Principle  of  Virtual  Velocities 49 

V.     Retrospect  of  the  Development  of  Statics 77 

VI.  The  Principles  of  Statics  in  Their  Application  to  Fluids    86 

VII.  The  Principles  of  Statics  in  Their  Application  to  Gas- 

eous Bodies no 

CHAPTER  n. 

THE  DEVELOPMENT  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  DYNAMICS. 

I.     Galileo's  Achievements 128 

n.     The  Achievements  of  Huygens    .     .  155 

III.  The  Achievements  of  Newton 187 

IV.  Discussion  and  Illustration  of  the  Principle  of  Reaction  201 
V.     Criticism  of  the  Principle  of  Reaction  and  of  the  Con- 
cept of  Mass 216 

VI.     Newton's  Views  of  Time,  Space,  and  Motion      .     .     .  222 

VII.  Synoptical  Critique  of  the  Newtonian  Enunciations.     .  238 

VIII.  Retrospect  of  the  Development  of  Dynamics ....  245 


% 


XIV  TABLE  OF  CONTENTS, 

CHAPTER  III. 

THE  EXTENDED  APPLICATION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES    OF 
MECHANICS  AND  THE  DEDUCTIVE  DEVELOP- 
MENT OF  THE  SCIENCE. 

PAGiE 

I.     Scope  of  the  Newtonian  Principles 256 

II.    The  Formulae  and  Units  of  Mechanics 269 

III.  The  Laws  of  the  Conservation  of  Momentum,  of  the 

Conservation  of  the  Centre  of  Gravity,  and  of  the 

Conservation  of  Areas 287 

IV.  The  Laws  of  Impact 305 

V.     D'AIembert's  Principle 331 

VI      The  Principle  of  Vis  Viva 343 

VII.     The  Principle  of  Least  Constraint 350 

VIII.     The  Principle  of  Least  Action 364 

IX.     Hamilton's  Principle ...  380 

X.     Some  Applications  of  the  Principles  of  Mechanics  to 

Hydrostatic  and  Hydrodynamic  Questions  .     .     .     .384 

CHAPTER  IV. 

THE  FORMAL  DEVELOPMENT  OF  MECHANICS. 

I.  The  Isoperimetrical  Problems 421 

II.     Theological,  Animistic,  and  Mystical  Points  of  View 

in  Mechanics 446 

III      Analytical  Mechanics .  465 

IV.     The  Economy  of  Science 481 

CHAPTER  V. 

THE    RELATION    OF    MECHANICS    TO    OTHER    DEPART- 
MENTS   OF    KNOWLEDGE. 

I      The  Relations  of  Mechanics  to  Physics 495 

II.  The  Relations  of  Mechanics  to  Physiology     .     .     .     .504 

Appendix 509 

Chronological  Table  of  a  Few  Eminent  Inquirers  and  of  Their 

More  Important  Mechanical  Works 519 

Index    .     .     .• 523 


THE   SCIENCE   OF   MECHANICS 


INTRODUCTION. 

1.  That  branch  of  physics  which  is  at  once  the  old-  The  science 
est   and   the  simplest  and  which  is  therefore  treated  ics. 

as  introductory  to  other  departments  of  this  science, 
is  concerned  with  the  motions  and  equilibrium  of 
masses.     It  bears  the  name  of  mechanics. 

2.  The  history  of  the  development  of  mechanics, 
is  quite  indispensable  to  a  full  comprehension  of  the 
science  in  its  present  condition.  It  also  affords  a  sim- 
ple and  instructive  example  of  the  processes  by  which 
natural  science  generally  is  developed. 

An  instinctive  J  irreflective  knowledge  of  the  processes  instinctive 
of  nature  will  doubtless  always  precede  the  scientific, 
conscious  apprehension,  or  investigation,  of  phenom- 
ena. The  former  is  the  outcome  of  the  relation  in 
which  the  processes  of  nature  stand  to  the  satisfac- 
tion of  our  wants.  The  acquisition  of  the  most  ele- 
mentary truth  does  not  devolve  upon  the  individual 
alone  :  it  is  pre-effected  in  the  development  of  the  race. 

In  point  of  fact,  it  is  necessary  to  make  a  dis-  Mechanical 
tinction  between  mechanical  experience  and  mechan-  ®*p®"*°^®* 
ical  science,  in  the  sense  in  which  the  latter  term  is  at 
present  employed.  Mechanical  experiences  are,  un- 
questionably, very  o\d.  If  we  carefully  examine  the 
ancient  Egyptian  and  Assyrian  monuments,  we  shall 
find  there  pictorial  representations  of  many  kinds  of 


a  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

Tbcme-  implements  and  mechanical  contrivances;  but  ac- 
knoviad^s  counts  of  the  scientific  knowledge  of  these  peoples 
are  either  totally  lacking,  or  point  conclusively  to  a 
very  inferior  grade  of  attainment.  By  the  side  of 
highly  ingenious  ap- 
pliances, we  behold 
the  crudest  and  rough- 
est expedients  em- 
ployed— as  the  use  of 
sleds,  for  instance,  for 
the  transportation  of 
enormous  blocks  of 
stone.  All  bears  an 
instinctive,  un perfec- 
ted, accidental  char- 
acter. 

So,  too,  prehistoric 
graves  contain  imple- 
^  mentswhoseconstruc- 

f"  tion  and  employment 

imply  no  little  skill 
and  much  mechanical 
experience.  Thus, long 
before  theory  was 
dreamed  of,  imple- 
ments, machines,  me- 
chanical experien- 
ces, and  mechanical 
knowledge  were  abun- 

Hbvcih  3.    The  idea   often 

ill  suggests     Itself     that 

perhaps  the  incom- 
plete accounts  we  pos- 


INTRODUCTION.  3 

sess  have  led  us  to  underrate  the.  science  of  the  ancient 
world.  Passages  occur  in  ancient  authors  which  seem 
to  indicate  a  profounder  knowledge  than  we  are  wont 
to  ascribe  to  those  nations.  Take,  for  instance,  the 
following  passage  from  Vitruvius,  ^  i>^  Architectural 
Lib.  V,  Cap.  Ill,  6  ;  L.      -^  .^.     ^  <^  >ci  ^ 


<< 


The  voice  is  a  flowing  breath,  made  sensible  to  a  passage 


from  Vitm- 
vius. 


**  the  organ  of  hearing  by  the  movements  it  produces 
'<in  the  air.  It  is  propagated  in  infinite  numbers  of 
** circular  zones:  exactly  as  when  a  stone  is  thrown 
*'into  a  pool  of  standing  water  countless  circular  un- 
'^dulations  are  generated  therein,  which,  increasing 

*  *  as  they  recede  from  the  centre,  spread  out  over  a 
**  great  distance,  unless  the  narrowness  of  the  locality 
**or  some  obstacle  prevent  their  reaching  their  ter- 

*  *  mination  ;  for  the  first  line  of  waves,  when  impeded 
*'by  obstructions,  throw  by  their  backward  swell  the 
•*  succeeding  circular  lines  of  waves  into  confusion. 
"  Conformably  to  the  very  same  law,  the  voice  also 
*'  generates  circular  motions ;  but  with  this  distinction, 
**  that  in  water  the  circles,  remaining  upon  the  surface, 
**  are  propagated  in  the  horizontal  direction  only,  while 

*  *  the  voice  is  propagated  both  horizontally  and  ver- 
**tically." 

Does  not  this  sound  like  the  imperfect  exposition  controvert- 
of  a  popular  author,  drawn  from  more  accurate  disqui-  evidencc.**^ 
sitions  now  lost  ?  In  what  a  strange  light  should  we 
ourselves  appear,  centuries  hence,  if  our  popular  lit- 
erature, which  by  reason  of  its  quantity  is  less  easily 
destructible,  should  alone  outlive  the  productions  of 
science  ?  This  too  favorable  view,  however,  is  very 
rudely  shaken  by  the  multitude  of  other  passages  con- 
taining such  crude  and  patent  errors  as  cannot  be  con- 
ceived to  exist  in  any  high  stage  of  scientific  culture. 


4  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

The  origin         4.  When,  where,  and  in  what  manner  the  develop- 
ment of  science  actually  began,  is  at  this  day  difficult 
historically  to  determine.     It  appears  reasonable  to 
assume,  however,  that  the  instinctive  gathering  of  ex- 
periential facts  preceded  the  scientific  classification  of 
them.    Traces  of  this  process  may  still  be  detected  in 
the  science  of  to-day;  indeed,  they  are  to  be  met  with, 
now  and  then,  in  ourselves.     The  experiments  that 
man  heedlessly  and  instinctively  makes  in  his  strug- 
gles to  satisfy  his  wants,  are  just  as  thoughtlessly  and 
unconsciously  applied.   Here,  for  instance,  belong  the 
primitive  experiments  concerning  the  application  of 
the  lever  in  all  its  manifold  forms.     But  the  things 
that  are  thus  unthinkingly  and  instinctively  discovered, 
can  never  appear  as  peculiar,  can  never  strike  us  as 
surprising,  and  as  a  rule  therefore  will  never  supply  an 
impetus  to  further  thought. 
Thefunc-  The  transition  from  this  stage  to  the  classified, 

da?  ciassM  Scientific  knowledge  and  apprehension  of  facts,  first  be- 
veioi>ment  comes  possible  on  the  rise  of  special  classes  and  pro- 
fessions who  make  the  satisfaction  of  definite  social 
wants  their  lifelong  vocation.  A  class  of  this  sort  oc- 
cupies itself  with  particular  kinds  of  natural  processes. 
The  individuals  of  the  class  change ;  old  members 
drop  out,  and  new  ones  come  in.  Thus  arises  a  need 
of  imparting  to  those  who  are  newly  come  in,  the 
stock  of  experience  and  knowledge  already  possessed  ;     'la 

a  need  of  acquainting  them  with  the  conditions  of  the     )  I  n 

ill 

The  com-    attainment  of  a  definite  end  so  that  the  result  may  be  (  I  w 

of  knowi-    determined  beforehand.  The  communication  of  knowl-  '  I  ni 

edge  is  thus  the  first  occasion  that  compels  distinct  re-  es 

flection,   as  everybody  can  still  observe  in  himself.  tk 

Further,  that  which  the  old  members  of  a  guild  me-  .     i^ 

chanically  pursue,  strikes  a  new  member  as  unusual  I     W( 

( 


INTRODUCTION,  ^  5 

and  strange,  and  thus  an  impulse  is  given  to  fresh  re- 
flection and  investigation. 

When  we  wish  to  bring  to  the  knowledge  of  a  per-  involves 

dotcriptioiL 

son  any  phenomena  or  processes  of  nature,  we  have 
the  choice  of  two  methods  :  we  may  allow  the  person  to 
observe  matters  for  himself,  when  instruction  comes 
to  an  end  ;  or,  we  may  describe  to  him  the  phenomena 
in  some  way,  so  as  to  save  him  the  trouble  of  per- 
sonally making  anew  each  experiment.  Description, 
however,  is  only  possible  of  events  that  constantly  re- 
cur, or  of  events  that  are  made  up  of  component 
parts  that  constantly  recur.  That  only  can  be  de- 
scribed, and  conceptually  represented  which  is  uniform 
and  conformable  to  law ;  for  description  presupposes 
the  employment  of  names  by  which  to  designate  its 
elements  ;  and  names  can  acquire  meanings  only  when 
applied  to  elements  that  constantly  reappear. 

5.   In  the  infinite  variety  of  nature  many  ordinary  a  unitary 

•^  .  ■'  -^  ■'  conception 

events  occur;  while  others  appear  uncommon,  per- of  nature, 
plexing,  astonishing,  or  eVen  contradictory  to  the  or- 
dinary run  of  things.  As  long  as  this  is  the  case  we 
do  not  possess  a  well-settle4  and  unitary  conception  of 
nature.  Thence  is  imposed  the  task  of  everywhere 
seeking  out  in  the  natural  phenomena  those  elements 
that  are  the  same,  and  that  amid  all  multiplicity  are 
ever  present.  By  this  means,  on  the  one  hand,  the 
most  economical  and  briefest  description  and  com- 
munication are  rendered  possible;  and  on  the  other.  The  nature 
when  once  a  person  has  acquired  the  skill  of  recog-edge. 
nising  these  permanent  elements  throughout  the  great- 
est range  and  variety  of  phenomena,  of  seeing  them  in 
the  same,  this  ability  leads  to  a  comprehensive^  compact^ 
consistent f  and  facile  conception  of  the  facts.  When  once 
we  have  reached  the  point  where  we  are  everywhere 


I 


6  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

Theadap-  able  to  detect  the  same  few  simple  elements,  combin- 

tation  of      .         ,  , 

thoughts  to  ing  in  the  ordinary  manner,  then  they  appear  to  us  as 
things  that  are  familiar ;  we  are  no  longer  surprised, 
there  is  nothing  new  or  strange  to  us  in  the  phenom- 
ena, we  feel  at  home  with  them,  they  no  longer  per- 
plex us,  they  are  explained.   It  is  a  process  of  adaptation 
of  thoughts  to  facts  with  which  we  are  here  concerned. 
The  ccon-         6.  Economy  of  communication  and  of  apprehen- 
tbooght.      sion  is  of  the  very  essence  of  science.     Herein   lies 
its  pacificatory,  its  enlightening,  its  refining  element. 
Herein,  too,  we  possess  an  unerring  guide  to  the  his- 
torical origin  of  science.   In  the  beginning,  all  economy 
had  in  immediate  view  the  satisfaction  simply  of  bodily 
wants.     With  the  artisan,  and  still  more  so  with  the 
investigator,  the  concisest  and  simplest  possible  knowl- 
edge of  a  given  province  of  natural  phenomena — a 
knowledge  that  is  attained  with  the  least  intellectual 
expenditure — naturally  becomes  in  itself  an  econom- 
ical aim ;  but  though  it  was  at  first  a  means  to  an  end,     ! 
when  the  mental  motives  connected  therewith  are  once 
developed  and  demand  their  satisfaction,  all  thought 
of  its  original  purpose,  ths  personal  need,  disappears. 
Further  de-       To  find,  then,  what  remains  unaltered  in  the  phe- 
pf  these      nomena  of  nature,  to  discover  the  elements  thereof 

ideas* 

and  the  mode  of  their  interconnection  and  interdepend- 
ence— this  is  the  business  of  physical  science.  It  en- 
deavors, by  comprehensive  and  thorough  description, 
to  make  the  waiting  for  new  experiences  unnecessary ;  ' 
it  seeks  to  save  us  the  trouble  of  experimentation,  by 
making  use,  for  example,  of  the  known  interdepend- 
ence of  phenomena,  according  to  which,  if  one  kind  of 
event  occurs,  we  may  be  sure  beforehand  that  a  certain 
other  event  will  occur.  Even  in  the  description  itself 
labor  may  be  saved,  by  discovering  methods  of  de- 


WTRODUCTIOA'.  7 

scribing  the  greatest  possible  number  of  different  ob-  Their  prea- 

ent  discus- 

jects  at  once  and  in  the  concisest  manner.   All  this  will  sion  merely 

....    preparatory 

be  made  clearer  by  the  examination  of  points  of  detail 
than  can  be  done  by  a  general  discussion.  It  is  fitting, 
however,  to  prepare  the  way,  at  this  stage,  for  the 
most  important  points  of  outlook  which  in  the  course 
of  our  work  we  shall  have  occasion  to  occupy. 

7.  We  now  propose  to  enter  more  minutely  into  the  proposed 
subject  of  our  inquiries,  and,  at  the  same  time,  without  rreatment. 
making  the  history  of  mechanics  the  chief  topic  of 
discussion,  to  consider  its  historical  development  so 
far  as  this  is  requisite  to  an  understanding  of  the  pres- 
ent state  of  mechanical  science,   and  so  far  as  it  does 
not  conflict  with  the   unity  of  treatment  of  our  main 
subject.    Apart  from  the  consideration  that  we  cannot 
afford  to  neglect  the  great  incentives  that  it  is  in  our 
power  to  derive   from   the  foremost  intellects  of  allxheincer- 
epochs,  incentives  which  taken  as  a  whole  are  more  rived  from 
fruitful  than  the  greatest  men  of  the  present  day  are  with  the 
able  to  offer,  there  is  no  grander,  no  more  intellectually  lects  of  the 
elevating  spectacle  than  that  of  the  utterances  of  the 
fundamental    investigators   in    their   gigantic   power. 
Possessed  as  yet  of  no  methods,  for  these  were  first 
created  by  their  labors,  and  are  only  rendered  compre- 
hensible to  us  by  their  performances,  they  grapple  with 
and  subjugate  the  object  of  their  inquiry,  and  imprint 
upon  it  the  forms  of  conceptual  thought.     They  that 
know  the  entire  course  of  the  development  of  science, 
will,   as  a  matter  of  course,    judge  more  freely  and  And  the  in- 
more  correctly  of  the  significance  of  any  present  scien-  power 
tific  movement  than  they,  who  limited  in  their  views  a  contact 
to  the  age  in  which  their  own  lives  have  been  spent, 
contemplate  merely  the  momentary  trend  that  the  course 
of  intellectual  events  takes  at  the  present  moment. 


{ 


CHAPTER  I. 

'      THE   DEVELOPMENT   OF   THE   PRINCIPLES   OF 

STATICS. 

I. 
THE  PRINCIPLE  OF  THE  LEVER. 

The  earliest        I.  The  earliest  investigations  concerning  mechan- 

mecbanical  .  *        i  •    i_  i_  i        •  •         • 

researches  ics  of  which  we  have  any  account,  the  investigations 
statics.       of  the  ancient  Greeks,  related  to  statics,  or  to  the  doc- 
trine of  equilibrium.     Likewise,  when  after  the  taking 
of  Constantinople  by  the  Turks  in  1453  a  fresh  impulse 
was  imparted  to  the  thought  of  the  Occident  by  the  an- 
cient writings  that  the  fugitive  Greeks  brought  with 
them,  it  was  investigations  in  statics,  principally  evoked 
by  the  works  of  Archimedes,  that  occupied  the  fore- 
most investigators  of  the  period. 
Archimedes       2.   Archimedes  of  Syracuse  (287-2 1 2  B.   C.)  left 
(287-212  B.    behind  him   a  number  of  writings,  of  which  several 
have  come  down  to  us  in  complete  form.     We  will 
first  employ  ourselves  a  moment  with  his  treatise  De 
^quiponderantibusy    which   contains   propositions   re- 
specting the  lever  and  the  centre  of  gravity. 

In  this  treatise  Archimedes  starts  from  the  follow- 
ing assumptions,  which  he  regards  as  self-evident : 
Axiomatic  a.   Magnitudes  of  equal  weight  acting  at  equal 

assump-  .  , 

tions  of  Ar-         distances  (from  their  point  of  support)  are  in  equi- 

chimedes.  i.,     • 

hbnum. 


I 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OP  STATICS.  9 

b.  Magnitudes  of  equal  weight  acting  at  une-  Axiomatic 
qual  distances  (irom  their  point  of  support)  are  dons  of  Ar- 

.  'ft     •  «  1  1      chimedeft. 

not  m  equihbrium,   but   the   one  acting   at   the 
greater  distance  sinks. 
From  these  assumptions  he  deduces  the  following 
proposition  : 

c.  Commensurable  magnitudes  are  in  equilib- 
rium when  they  are  inversely  proportional  to  their 
distances  (from  the  point  of  support). 

It  would  seem  as  if  analysis  could  hardly  go  be- 
hind these  assumptions.  This  is,  however,  when  we 
carefully  look  into  the  matter,  not  the  case. 

Imagine   (Fig.   2)   a  bar,   the  weight  of  which  is 
neglected.    The  bar  rests  on  a  fulcrum.    At  equal  dis- 
tances from  the  fulcrum  we  ap- 
pend two  equal  weights.     That        1 7^ 

the  two    weights,   thus  circum-      rS 
stanced,    are   in   equilibrium,   is 
the  assumption  from  which  Archi- 
medes starts.     We  might  suppose  that  this  was  self- Analysis  of 
evident  entirely  apart  from  any  experience,  agreeably  to  medean  as- 
the  so-called  principle  of  sufRcient  reason  ;  that  in  view  '""P"°"' 
of  the  symmetry  of  the  entire  arrangement  there  is  no 
reason  why  rotation  should  occur  in  the  one  direction 
rather  than  in  the  other.     But  we  forget,  in  this,  that 
a  great  multitude  of  negative  and  positive  experiences 
is  implicitly  contained  in  our  assumption  ;  the  negative, 
for  instance,  that  dissimilar  colors  of  the  lever-arms, 
the  position  of  the  spectator,  an  occurrence  in  the  vi- 
cinity, and  the  like,  exercise  no  influence  ;  the  positive, 
on  the  other  hand,  (as  it  appears  in  the  second  as- 
sumption,) that  not  only  the  weights  but  also  their  dis- 
tances from  the  supporting  point  are  decisive  factors 
in  the  disturbance  of  equilibrium,  that  they  also  are  cir- 


lo  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

cumstances  determinative  of  motion.  By  the  aid  of 
these  experiences  we  do  indeed  perceive  that  rest  (no 
motion)  is  the  only  motion  which  can  be  uniquely*  de- 
termined, or  defined,  by  the  determinative  conditions 
of  the  case.f 
Character  Now  we  are  entitled  to  regard  our  knowledge  of 

the  Archi-   the  decisive  conditions  of  any  phenomenon  as  sufficient 
suits.  only  in  the  event  that  such  conditions  determine  the 

phenomenon  precisely  and  uniquely.     Assuming  the 
fact  of  experience  referred  to,  that  the  weights  and 
their  distances  alone  are  decisive,  the  first  proposition 
of  Archimedes  really  possesses  a  high  degree  of  evi- 
dence and  is  eminently  qualified  to  be  made  the  foun- 
dation of  further  investigations.   If  the  spectator  place 
himself  in  the  plane  of  symmetry  of  the  arrangement 
in  question,  the  first  proposition  manifests  itself,  more- 
over, as  a  highly  imperative  instinctive  perception, — a 
result  determined  by  the  symmetry  of  our  own  body. 
The  pursuit  of  propositions  of  this  character  is,  fur- 
thermore, an  excellent  means  of  accustoming  ourselves 
in  thought  to  the  precision  that  nature  reveals  in  her 
processes. 
The  general        3-  We  will  now  reproduce  in  general  outlines  the 
of  tfe  leUr  train  of  thought  by  which  Archimedes  endeavors  to  re- 
the  simple  duce  the  general  proposition  of  the  lever  to  the  par- 
uUrcMe.^   ticular   and   apparently  self-evident   case.     The   two 
equal  weights  i  suspended  at  a  and  b  (Fig.  3)  are,  if 
the  bar  ab  be  free  to  rotate  about  its  middle  point  r,  in 
equilibrium.     If  the  whole  be  suspended  by  a  cord  at 
r,  the  cord,  leaving  out  of  account  the  weight  of  the 

*  So  as  to  leave  only  a  single  possibility  open. 

t  If,  for  example,  we  were  to  assume  that  the  weight  at  the  right  de- 
scended, then  rotation  in  the  opposite  direction  also  would  be  determined  by 
the  spectator,  whose  person  exerts  no  influence  on  the  phenomenon,  taking 
np  bis  position  on  the  opposite  side. 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS. 


II 


bar,  will  have  to  support  the  weight  2.  The  e'qual  The  general 
weights  at  the  extremities  of  the  bar  supply  accor-  of  £e  lever 
dingly  the  place  of  the  double  weight  at  the  centre.       the  timpie 


@L 


a 


£ 


0 


\ 


r 


and  partic- 
ular case. 


i  b3 


"i 


Fir.  3. 


Fig.  4. 


On  a  lever  (Fig.  4),  the  arms  of  which  are  in  the 
proportion  of  i  to  2,  weights  are  suspended  in  the  pro- 
portion of  2  to  I.  The  weight  2  we  imagine  replaced 
by  two  weights  i,  attached  on  either  side  at  a  distance 
I  from  the  point  of  suspension.  Now  again  we  have 
complete  symmetry  about  the  point  of  suspension,  and 
consequently  equilibrium. 

On  the  lever-arms  3  and  4  (Fig.  5)  are  suspended 
the  weights  4  and  3.  The  lever-arm  3  is  prolonged 
the  distance  4,  the  arm  4  is  prolonged  the  distance  3, 
and  the  weights  4  and  3  are  replaced  respectively  by 


/:,. 


-A^ 


t 


rK 


G 


"N/' 


ti  t  t'^h  h  h  h\h"h  5 


7, 


Fig.  5 

4  and  3  pairs  of  symmetrically  attached  weights  J, 
in  the  manner  indicated  in  the  figure.     Now  again  we 
have   perfect  symmetry.     The   preceding   reasoning,  The  genep 
which  we  have  here  developed  with  specific  figures,  is  *  *""°"* 
easily  generalised. 

4.  It  will  be  of  interest  to  look  at  the  manner  in 
which  Archimedes's  mode  of  view,  after  the  precedent 
of  Stevinus,  was  modified  by  Galileo. 


12 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 


tn 


n 


m 


n 


2  m 

2« 

Fig.  6. 


Galileo's  'Galileo  imagines  (Fig.  6)  a  heavy  horizontal  prism, 

treatment,   homogeneous  in  material  composition,  suspended  by 

its  extremities  from  a  homogeneous  bar  of  the  same 

length.      The   bar   is   provided   at    its    middle  point 

with  a  suspensory  attach  - 
ment.    In  this  case  equi- 
librium will  obtain ;  this 
we  perceive  at  once.   But 
in  this  case  is  contained 
every  other  case.  Which 
Galileo    shows     in     the 
following  manner.     Let 
us    suppose    the    whole 
length  of  the  bar  or  the  prism  to  be  2(»i  -j-  «)•     Cut 
the  prism  in  two,  in  such  a  manner  that  one  portion 
shall  have  the  length  2m  and  the  other  the  length  2«. 
We  can  effect  this  without  disturbing  the  equilibrium 
by  previously  fastening  to  the  bar  by  threads,  close  to 
the  point  of  proposed  section,  the  inside  extremities  of 
the  two  portions.  We  may  then  remove  all  the  threads, 
if  the  two  portions  of  the  prism  be  antecedently  at- 
tached to  the  bar  by  their  centres.     Since  the  whole 
length  of  the  bar  is  2(w  +  «),  the  length  of  each  half 
is  m  -{-  n.     The  distance  of  the  point  of  suspension  of 
the  right-hand  portion  of  the  prism  from  the  point  of 
suspension  of  the  bar  is  therefore  m,  and  that  of  the 
left-hand  portion    «.     The   experience  that  we  have 
here  to  deal  with  the  weight,  and  not  with  the  form, 
of  the  bodies,  is  easily  made.    It  is  thus  manifest,  that 
equilibrium  will  still  subsist  if  any  weight  of  the  mag- 
nitude 2m  be  suspended  at  the  distance  n  on  the  one 
side  and  any  weight  of  the  magnitude  2«  be  suspended 
at  the  distance  m  on  the  other.   The  instinctive  elements 
of  our  perception  of  this  phenomenon  are  even  more 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS.  13 

prominently  displayed  in  this  form  of  the  deduction 
than  in  that  of  Archimedes.  . 

We  may  discover,  moreover,  in  this  beautiful  pre- 
sentation, a  remnant  of  the  ponderousness  which  was 
particularly  characteristic  of  the  investigators  of  an- 
tiquity. 

How  a  modem  physicist  conceived  the  same  prob-  Lagrange's 
lem,  may  be  learned  from  the  following  presentation  of  tion. 
Lagrange.  Lagrange  says :  Imagine  a  horizontal  ho- 
mogeneous prism  suspended  at  its  centre.  Let  this 
prism  (Fig.  7)  be  conceived  divided  into  two  prisms 
of  the  lengths  im  and  2«.  If  now  we  consider  the 
centres  of  gravity  of  these  two  parts,  at  which  we  may 
imagine  weights  to  act  proportional  to  7.fn  and  iriy  the 


2m 


2n 


Fig.  7. 

two  centres  thus  considered  will  have  the  distances  n 
and  m  from  the  point  of  support.  This  concise  dis- 
posal of  the  problem  is  only  possible  to  the  practised 
mathematical  perception. 

5.  The  object  that  Archimedes  and  his  successors  object  of 
sought  to  accomplish  in  the  considerations  we  have  here  and  his  sac- 
presented,  consists  in  the  endeavor  to  reduce  the  more 
complicated  case  of  the  lever  to  the  simpler  and  ap- 
parently self-evident  case,  to  discern  the  simpler  in  the 
more  complicated,  or  vice  versa.  In  fact,  we  regard 
a  phenomenon  as  explained,  when  we  discover  in  it 
known  simpler  phenomena. 

But  surprising  as  the  achievement  of  Archimedes 
and  his  successors  may  at  the  first  glance  appear  to 
us,  doubts  as  to  the  correctness  of  it,  on  further  reflec- 


14  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

Critique  of  tion,  nevertheless  spring  up.    From  the  mere  assump- 
ods.  tion  of  the  equilibrium  of  equal  weights  at  equal  dis- 

tances is  derived  thp  inverse  proportionality  of  weight 
and  lever-arm  !  How  is  that  possible  ?  If  we  were 
unable  philosophically  and  a  priori  to  excogitate  the 
simple  fact  of  the  dependence  of  equilibrium  on  weight 
and  distance,  but  were  obliged  to  go  for  that  result  to 
experience,  in  how  much  less  a  degree  shall  we  be  able, 
by  speculative  methods,  to  discover  the  form  of  this 
dependence,  the  proportionality  ! 
The  Statical       As  a  matter  of  fact,  the  assumption  that  the  equi- 

moment  in- 
volved in     librium- disturbing  effect  of  a  weight  P  2X  the  distance 

all  their  de-  .       °  .  ° 

ductions.  L  from  the  axis  of  rotation  is  measured  by  the  product 
P,L  (the  so-called  statical  moment),  is  more  or  less 
covertly  or  tacitly  introduced  by  Archimedes  and  all 
his  successors.  For  when  Archimedes  substitutes  for 
a  large  weight  a  series  of  symmetrically  arranged  pairs 
of  small  weights,  which  weights  extend  beyond  the  point 
of  support ^  he  employs  in  this  very  act  the  doctrine  of 
the  centre  of  gravity  in  its  more  general  form,  which  is 
itself  nothing  else  than  the  doctrine  of  the  lever  in  its 
more  general  form. 
Without  it  Without  the  assumption  above  mentioned  of  the  im- 
tion?°im*  port  of  the  product  /'.Z,  no  one  can  prove  (Fig.  8) 

i>ossible.  ^1      .      *   1  1  1     • 

that  a  bar,  placed  in 
C^  any  way  on   the   ful- 


crum Sy  is  supported, 
with   the    help   of     a 

I     string  attached  to  its 

^^  centre  of  gravity  and 

^^^  ^'  carried  over  a  pulley, 

by  a  weight  equal  to  its  own  weight.  But  this  is  con- 
tained in  the  deductions  of  Archimedes,  Stevinus, 
Galileo,  and  also  in  that  of  Lagrange. 


?i 


THE  PRINCIPLMS  OF  STATICS. 


6.  HuYGENS,  indeed,  reprehends  this  method,  andHa»aiu'> 
gives  a  different  deduction,  in  which  he  believes  he  has 
avoided  the  error.  If  in 
the  presentation  of  La- 
grange we  imagine  the 
two  portions  into  which 
the  prism  is  divided 
turned  ninety  degrees 
about  two  vertical  axes 
passing  through  the  cen- 
tres of  gravity  s,s  of  the 
prism -portions  (see  Fig. 
911),  and  it  be  shown 
that  under  these  circum 
stances  equilibrium  still  . 
continues  to  subsist,  we  Fig.  9. 

shall    obtain    the   Huygenian    deduction.     Abridged 


and  simplified,  it  is  as  follows. 


ightless 


plane  (Fig.  9)  through  the  p>oint  S  we  draw  a  straight 
line,  on  which  we  cut  off  on  the  one  side  the  length  i 


i6 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 


His  own  de- and  on  the  other  the  length  2,  at  A  and  B  respectively. 
On  the  extremities,  at  right  angles  to  this  straight 
line,  we  place,  with  the  centres  as  points  of  contact,  the 
heavy,  thin,  homogeneous  prisms  CD  and  EF^  of  the 
lengths  and  weights  4  and  2.  Drawing  the  straight 
line  HSG  (where  AG=^\AC^  and,  parallel  to  it,  the 
line  CFy  and  translating  the  prism-portion  CG  by  par- 
allel displacement  to  FH^  everything  about  the  axis 
GH  is  symmetrical  and  equilibrium  obtains.  But 
equilibrium  also  obtains  for  the  axis  AB ;  obtains  con- 
sequently for  every  axis  through  S,  and  therefore  also 
for  that  at  right  angles  to  AB :  wherewith  the  new 
case  of  the  lever  is  given. 
Apparently  Apparently,  nothing  else  is  assumed  here  than  that 
able.  equal  weights  /,/  (Fig.  10)  in  the  same  plane  and  at 

equal  distances  /,/  from  an  axis  A  A'  (in  this  plane) 
equilibrate  one  another.  If  we  place  ourselves  in  the 
plane  passing  through  A  A*  perpendicularly  to  /,/,  say 


P 


M 


A' 

Pig.  zo. 


Fig,  II. 


at  the  point  M,  and  look  now  towards  A  and  now 
towards  A\  we  shall  accord  to  this  proposition  the 
same  evidentness  as  to  the  first  Archimedean  proposi- 
tion. The  relation  of  things  is,  moreover,  not  altered  if 
we  institute  with  the  weights  parallel  displacements 
with  respect  to  the  axis,  as  Huygens  in  fact  does. 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS.  17 

The  error  first  arises  in  the  inference  :  if  equilib-  Yet  invow- 
rium  obtains  for  two  axes  of  the  plane,  it  also  obtains  final  infer- 

,  -  .  •  1  1      1  .  r  •  ®°ce  an  er- 

for  every  other  axis  passing  through  the  point  of  inter-  ror. 
section  of  the  first  two.  This  inference  (if  it  is  not  to 
be  regarded  as  a  purely  instinctive  one)  can  be  drawn 
only  upon  the  condition  that  disturbant  effects  are  as- 
cribed to  the  weights  proportional  to  their  distances 
from  the  axis.  But  in  this  is  contained  the  very  kernel 
of  the  doctrine  of  the  lever  and  the  centre  of  gravity. 
Let  the  heavy  points  of  a  plane  be  referred  to  a 
system  of  rectangular  co5rdinates  (Fig.  11).  The  co- 
ordinates of  the  centre  of  gravity  of  a  system  of  masses 
mm'  m" , , ,  having  the  coSrdinates  xx*  x"  ,  .  .  yy'  y"  .  .  . 
are,  as  we  know, 

Mathemat- 
^         2mx  2my  »cal  discos- 

inference. 

If  we  turn  the  system  through  the  angle  a,  the  new  co- 
ordinates of  the  masses  will  be 

x^  =  x  cosa  — y  sina,  y^=y  cosa  -f-  x  sina 

and   consequently  the   coordinates   of  the   centre  of 
gravity 

J,        Sm(xcosa  —  ysina)                2mx        .      2my 
S.  = ^^ ^ =  cosa  -^ smar  -.^^ 

=  S  cosa  —  Tf  sina 
and,  similarly, 

ff^  =  ij  cosa  +  S  sina. 

We  accordingly  obtain  the  coordinates  of  the  new 
centre  of  gravity,  by  simply  transforming  the  coordi- 
nates of  the  first  centre  to  the  new  axes.  The  centre 
of  gravity  remains  therefore  M^  self-same  point.  If 
we  select  the  centre  of  gravity  itself  as  origin,  then 
2mx=^2my=i^.  On  turning  the  system  of  axes,  this 
relation  continues  to  subsist.     If,  accordingly,  equi- 


i8  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

librium  obtains  for  two  axes  of  a  plane  that  are  per- 
pendicular to  each  other,  it  also  obtains,  and  obtains 
then  only,  for  every  other  axis  through  their  point  of 
intersection.  Hence,  if  equilibrium  obtains  for  any 
two  axes  of  a  plane,  it  will  also  obtain  for  every  other 
axis  of  the  plane  that  passes  through  the  point  of  in- 
tersection of  the  two. 
The  infer-         These  conclusions,  however,  are  not  deducible  if 

enca  admis- 
sible only    the  coordinates  of  the  centre  of  gravity  are  determined 

on  one  con-  . 

dition.        by  some  other,  more  general  equation,  say 

tn  -\-  tn  -\-  tn    -f-  .  .  . 

The  Huygenian  mode  of  inference,  therefore,  is  in- 
admissible, and  contains  the  very  same  error  that  we 
remarked  in  the  case  of  Archimedes. 
Seif-decep-  Archimedes's  self-deception  in  this  his  endeavor  to 
chimedes.  reduce  the  complicated  case  of  the  lever  to  the  case 
instinctively  grasped,  probably  consisted  in  his  uncon- 
scious employment  of  studies  previously  made  on  the 
centre  of  gravity  by  the  help  of  the  very  proposition  he 
sought  to  prove.  It  is  characteristic,  that  he  will  not 
trust  on  his  own  authority,  perhaps  even  on  that  of 
others,  the  easily  presented  observation  of  the  import 
of  the  product  P.Ly  but  searches  after  a  further  verifi- 
cation of  it. 

Now  as  a  matter  of  fact  we  shall  not,  at  least  at 
this  stage  of  our  progress,  attain  to  any  comprehension 
whatever  of  the  lever  unless  we  directly  discern  in  the 
phenomena  the  product  P,L  as  the  factor  decisive  of 
the  disturbance  of  equilibrium.  In  so  far  as  Archi- 
medes, in  his  Grecian  mania  for  demonstration,  strives 
to  get  around  this,  his  deduction  is  defective.  But  re- 
garding the  import  of  P.L  as  given,  the  Archimedean 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS. 


19 


deductions  still  retain  considerable  value,  in  so  far  as  Function  of 
the  modes  of  conception  of  different  cases  are  supported  medean  de- 
the  one  on  the  other,  in  so  far  as  it  is  shown  that  one 
simple  case  contains  all  others,  in  so  far  as  the  same 
mode  of  conception  is  established  for  all  cases.  Im- 
agine (Fig.  12)  a  homogeneous  prism,  whose  axis  is 
ABy  supported  at  its  centre  C,  To  give  a  graphical 
representation  of  the  sum  of  the  products  of  the  weights 
and  distances,  the  sum  decisive  of  the  disturbance  of 
equilibrium,  let  us  erect  upon  the  elements  of  the  axis, 
which  are  proportional  to  the  elements  of  the  weight, 
the  distances  as  ordinates ;  the  ordinates  to  the  right 


Pig.  IS. 

of  C*(as  positive)  being  drawn  upwards,  and  to  the  left  illustration 
of  C  (as  negative)  downwards.  The  sum  of  the  areas  °  *'*  ^  "* 
of  the  two  triangles,  A  CD  -f  CBE  =  0,  illustrates  here 
the  subsistence  of  equilibrium.  If  we  divide  the  prism 
into  two  parts  at  M,  we  may  substitute  the  rectangle 
MUWB  for  MTEB,  and  the  rectangle  MVXA  for 
TMCAD,  where  TP=\TE  and  TR  =  \TD,  and  the 
prism-sections  MB,  MA  are  to  be  regarded  as  placed 
at  right  angles  to  AB  by  rotation  about  Q  and  S. 


\ 


20 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 


In  the  direction  here  indicated  the  Archimedean 
view  certainly  remained  a  serviceable  one  even  after 
no  one  longer  entertained  any  doubt  of  the  significance 
of  the  product  /'.Z,  and  after  opinion  on  this  point  had 
been  established  historically  and  by  abundant  verifica- 
tion. 
Treatment         7.  The  manner  in  which  the  laws  of  the  lever,  as 

of  the  lever ,         ,     -     , 

bjr  modem  handed  down  to  us  from  Archimedes  in  their  original 
simple  form,  were  further  generalised  and  treated  by 
modern  physicists,  is  very  interesting  and  instructive. 
Leonardo  DA  Vinci  (1452-1519),  the  famous  painter 
and  investigator,  appears  to  have  been  the  first  to  rec- 
ognise the  importance  of  the  general  notion  of  the  so- 

B 


Fig.  13. 

Leonardo  called  Statical  moments.  In  the  manuscripts  he  has 
(X453-1519).  left  us,  several  passages  are  found  from  which  this 
clearly  appears.  He  says,  for  example :  We  have  a 
bar  AD  (Fig.  13)  free  to  rotate  about  A^  and  suspended 
from  the  bar  a  weight  /*,  and  suspended  from  a  string 
which  passes  over  a  pulley  a  second  weight  Q.  What 
must  be  the  ratio  of  the  forces  that  equilibrium  may  ob- 
tain? The  lever- arm  for  the  weight  P  is  not  ADy  but 
the  "potential"  lever  AB,  The  lever-arm  for  the 
weight  ^  is  not  AD^  but  the  ** potential"  lever  AC, 
The  method  by  which  Leonardo  arrived  at  this  view 
is  difficult  to  discover.     But  it  is  clear  that  he  recog- 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS.  21 

nised  the  essential  circumstances  by  which  the  effect 
of  the  weight  is  determined. 

Considerations  similar   to   those  of  Leonardo  da  Guide 

Ubaldi. 

Vinci  are  also  found  in  the  writings  of  Guido  Ubaldi. 
8.   We  will  now  endeavor  to  obtain  some  idea  of 
the  way  in  which  the  notion  of  statical  moment,  by 
which  as  we  know  is  understood  the  product  of  a  force 
into  the  perpendicular  let  fall  from  the  axis  of  rotation 
upon  the  line  of  direction  of  the  force,  could  have  been 
arrived  at, — although  the  way  that  really  led  to  this 
idea  is  not  now  fully  ascertainable.     That  equilibrium 
exists  (Fig.  14)  if  we  lay  a 
cord,  subjected  at  both  sides 
to  equal  tensions,   over  a 
pulley,  is  perceived  without 
difficulty.   We  shall  always 
find  a  plane  of  symmetry  for 
the    apparatus — the    plane 
which  stands  at  right  angles  p'«-  '♦• 

to  the  plane  of  the  cord  and  bisects  {EE)  the  angle  made 
by  its  two  parts.    The  motion  that  might  be  supposed  a  method 
possible  cannot  in  this  case  be  precisely  determined  or  the  notion 

,    ^         ,  ,  ,  ,  .  .,,     ,  ofthestat- 

defined  by  any  rule  whatsoever  :  no  motion  will  there- icai  mo- 

,  ,  ,  -r  rill  ment  might 

tore  take  place.  If  we  note,  now,  further,  that  the  mate-  have  been 
rial  of  which  the  pulley  ig  made  is  only  essential  to  the 
extent  of  determining  the  form  of  motion  of  the  points 
of  application  of  the  strings,'  we  shall  likewise  easily 
perceive  that  without  disturbing  the  equilibrium  of 
the  machine^  almost  any  portion  of  the  pulley  may  be 
removed.  Essential  remain  only  the  rigid  radii  that 
lead  out  to  the  tangential  points  of  the  string.  We 
see,  thus,  that  the  rigid  radii  (or  the  perpendiculars  on 
the  linear  directions  of  the  strings)  play  here  a  part 
similar  to  the  lever-arms  in  the  lever  of  Archimedes. 


22 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 


This  notioD 
derived 
from  the 
considera- 
tion of  a 
wheel  and 
axle. 


Let  US  examine  a  so-called  wheel  and  axle  (Fig^. 
15)  of  wheel-radius  2  and  axle-radius  i,  provided  re- 
spectively with  the  cord-hung  loads  i  and  2  ;  an  appa- 
ratus which  corresponds  in  every  respect  to  the  lever 
of  Archimedes.  If  now  we  place  about  the  axle,  in 
any  manner  we  may  choose,  a  second  cord,  which  we 
subject  at  each  side  to  the  tension  of  a  weight  2,  the 
second  cord  will  not  disturb  the  equilibrium.  It  is 
plain,  however,  that  we  are  also  permitted  to  regard 


Fig.  15.  Fig.  x6. 

the  two  pulls  marked  in  Fig.  16  as  being  in  equilib- 
rium, by  leaving  the  two  others,  as  mutually  destruc- 
tive, out  of  account.  But  we  arrive  in  so  doing,  dis- 
missing from  consideration  all  unessential  features,  at 
the  perception  that  not  only  the  pulls  exerted  by  the 
weights  but  also  the  perpendiculars  let  fall  from  the 
axis  on  the  lines  of  the  pulls,  are  conditions  deter- 
minative of  motion.  The  decisive  factors  are,  then, 
the  products  of  the  weights  into  the  respective  per- 
pendiculars let  fall  from  the  axis  on  the  directions  of 
the  pulls ;  ih  other  words,  the  so-called  statical  mo- 
ments. 
The  princi-  9.  What  we  have  so  far  considered,  is  the  devel- 
fe Jar  all*  opmcnt  of  our  knowledge  of  the  principle  of  the  lever, 
explain  the  Quite  independently  of  this  was  developed  the  knowl- 

other  in&.* 

chines.       edge  of  the  principle  of  the  inclined  plane.      It  is  not 
necessary,  however,  for  the  comprehension  of  the  ma- 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS. 


23 


chines,  to  search  after  a  new  principle  beyond  that  of 
the  lever ;  for  the  latter  is  sufficient  by  itself.  Galileo, 
for  example,  explains  the  inclined  plane  from  the  lever 
in  the  following  manner. 
We  have  before  us  (Fig. 
17)  an  inclined  plane,  on 
which  rests  the  weight 
Qj  held  in  equilibrium 
by  the  weight  F,  Gali- 
leo, now,  points  out  the  p>8-  17. 
fact,  that  it  is  not  requisite  that  Q  should  lie  directly 
upon  the  inclined  plane,  but  that  the  essential  point 
is  rather  the  form,  or  character,  of  the  motion 
of  Q.  We  may,  consequently,  conceive  the  weight 
attached  to  the  bar  AC,  perpendicular  to  the  inclined 
plane,  and  rotatable  about  C     If  then  we  institute  a  Galileo's 

.  explanation 

very  slight  rotation  about  the  point  C,  the  weight  willofthein- 
move  in  the  element  of  an  arc  coincident  with  the  in-  plane  by 

the  lever. 

clined  plane.  That  the  path  assumes  a  curve  on  the 
motion  being  continued  is  of  no  consequence  here, 
since  this  further  movement  does  not  in  the  case  of 
equilibrium  take  place,  and  the  movement  of  the  in- 
stant alone  is  decisive.  Reverting,  however,  to  the 
observation  before  mentioned  of  Leonardo  da  Vinci, 
we  readily  perceive  the  validity  of  the  theorem  Q,  CB 
=  F.  CA  or  Q/F  =CA/CB  =  cafcb,  and  thus  reach 
the  law  of  equilibrium  on  the  inclined  plane.  Once  we 
have  reached  the  principle  of  the  lever,  we  may,  then, 
easily  apply  that  principle  to  the  comprehension  of 
the  other  machines. 


24 


TUB  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 


II. 


Fig.  i8. 


THE  PRINCIPLE  OF  THE  INCLINED  PLANE. 

stevinus  i.  Stevinus,  Of  Stevin,  (1548-1620)  was  the  first 

first  investi- who  iiivestie^ated  the  mechanical  properties  of  the  in- 

gates  the 

mechftiiics  clined  plane :  and  he  did  so  in  an  eminently  original 

of  the  in-  r  >  .    i_^,.     /t- 

clined  ,  -  manner.    If  a  weight  lie  (Fig. 

plane.  /  o  v      o 

18)  on  a  horizontal  table,  we 
perceive  at  once,  since  the 
pressure  is  directly  perpendic- 
ular to  the  plane  of  the  table, 
by  the  principle  of  symmetry, 
that  equilibrium  subsists.  On  a 
vertical  wall,  on  the  other  hand,  a  weight  is  not  at  all 
obstructed  in  its  motion  of  descent.  The  inclined  plane 
accordingly  will  present  an  intermediate  case  between 
these  two  limiting  suppositions.  Equilibrium  will  not 
exist  of  itself,  as  it  does  on  the  horizontal  support,  but 
it  will  be  maintained  by  a  less  weight  than  that  neces- 
sary to  preserve  it  on  the  vertical  wall.  The  ascertain- 
ment of  the  statical  law  that  obtains  in  this  case,  caused 
the  earlier  inquirers  considerable  difficulty. 
His  mode  of  Steviuus's  manner  of  procedure  is  in  substance  as 
law.  follows.   He  imagines  a  triangular  prism  with  horizon- 

tally placed  edges,  a  cross-section  of  which  ABC  is 
represented  in  Fig.  19.  For  the  sake  of  illustration 
we  will  say  that  AB  =  iBC ;  also  that  ^C  is  horizon- 
tal. Over  this  prism  Stevinus  lays  an  endless  string 
on  which  14  balls  of  equal  weight  are  strung  and  tied 
at  equal  distances  apart.  We  can  advantageously  re 
place  this  string  by  an  endless  uniform  chain  or  cord. 
The  chain  will  either  be  in  equilibrium  or  it  will  not. 
If  we  assume  the  latter  to  be  the  case,  the  chain,  since 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS.  i; 

the  conditions  of  the  event  are  not  altered  by  its  mo- 
tion, must,  when  onc£  actually  in  motion,  continue  to 
move  for  ever,  that  is,  it  must  present  a  perpetual  mo- 
tion, which  Stevinus  deems  absurd.  Consequently  only  sieviai 
the  first  case  is  conceivable.  The  chain  remains  in  equi-  ot  ib"! 
librium.     The  symmetrical  portion  y^iJC  may,  there- cUnad 
fore,  without  disturbing  the  equilibrium,  be  removed. ''""' 
The  portion  A£  of  the  chain  consequently  balances 
the  portion  SC.      Hence  :  on  inclined  planes  of  equal 
heights  equal  weights  act  in  the  inverse  proportion  of 
the  lengths  of  the  planes. 


In  the  cross-section  of  the  prism  in  Fig.  20  let  us 
imagine  AC  horizontal,  .5 C  vertical,  and  AB ^  2BC; 
furthermore,  the  chain-weights  Q  and  P  on  AB  and 
BC  proportional  to  the  lengths ;  it  will  follow  then  that 


26  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

Q/P=i  AB/BC=2,     The  generalisation  is  self-evi- 
dent. 
The  as-  2.   Unquestionably  in  the  assumption  from  which 

ofstevi"*  Stevinus  starts,  that  the  endless  chain  does  not  move, 
dncdon.      there  is  contained  primarily  only  a  purely  ins  tine  tw^ 
cognition.     He  feels  at  once,  and  we  with  him,  that 
we  have  never  observed  anything  like  a  motion  of  the 
kind  referred  to,  that  a  thing  of  such  a  character  does 
not  exist.  This  conviction  has  so  much  logical  cogency 
that  we  accept  the  conclusion  drawn  from  it  respecting 
the  law  of  equilibrium  on  the  inclined  plane  without  the 
thought  of  an  objection,  although  the  law  if  presented 
as  the  simple  result  of  experiment,  or  otherwise  put. 
Their  in-     would  appear  dubious.  We  cannot  be  surprised  at  this 
character,   when  We  reflect  that  all  results  of  experiment  a^-e  ob- 
scured by  adventitious  circumstances  (as  friction,  etc.), 
and  that  every  conjecture  as  to  the  conditions  which  are 
determinative  in  a  given  case  is  liable  to  error.     That 
Stevinus  ascribes  to  instinctive  knowledge  of  this  sort 
a  higher  authority  than  to  simple,  manifest,  direct  ob- 
servation might  excite  in  us  astonishment  if  we  did  not 
ourselves  possess  the  same  inclination.     The  question 
accordingly  forces  itself  upon  us :  Whence  does  this 
higher  authority  come  ?  If  we  remember  that  scientific 
demonstration,   and   scientific  criticism   generally  can 
only  have  sprung  from  the  consciousness  of  the  individ- 
ual fallibility  of  investigators,  the  explanation  is  not  far 
Their  COR-  to  Seek.     We  feel  clearly,  that  we  ourselves  have  con- 

ency. 

tributed  nothing  to  the  creation  of  instinctive  knowl- 
edge, that  we  have  added  to  it  nothing  arbitrarily,  but 
that  it  exists  in  absolute  independence  of  our  partici- 
pation. Our  mistrust  of  our  own  subjective  interpre- 
tation of  the  facts  observed,  is  thus  dissipated. 

Stevinus's  deduction  is  one  of  the  rarest  fossil  in- 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS.  27 

dications  that  we  possess  in  the  primitive  history  of  HiRhhistor- 
mechanics,  and  throws  a  wonderful  light  on  the  pro-  stevinns's 
cess  of  the  formation  of  science  generally,  on  its  rise 
from   instinctive  knowledge.     We  will  recall  to  mind 
that  Archimedes  pursued  exactly  the  same  tendency 
as  Stevinus,  only  with  much  less  good  fortune.     In 
later  times,   also,   instinctive  knowledge  is  very  fre- 
quently taken  as  the  starting-point  of  investigations. 
Every  experimentator  can  daily  observe  in  himself  the 
guidance  that  instinctive  knowledge  furnishes  him.    If 
he  succeed  in  abstractly  formulating  what  is  contained 
in  it,  he  will  as  a  rule  have  made  an  important  advance 
in  science. 

Stevinus's  procedure  is  no  error.  If  an  error  were  The  trust- 
contained  in  it,  we  should  all  share  it.  Indeed,  it  is  of  instinc- 
perfectly  certain,  that  the  union  of  the  strongest  in- edge, 
stinct  with  the  greatest  power  of  abstract  formulation 
alone  constitutes  the  great  natural  inquirer.  This  by 
no  means  compels  us,  however,  to  create  a  new  mysti- 
cism out  of  the  instinctive  in  science  and  to  regard  this 
factor  as  infallible.  That  it  is  not  infallible,  we  very 
easily  discover.  Even  instinctive  knowledge  of  so 
great  logical  force  as  the  principle  of  symmetry  em- 
ployed by  Archimedes,  may  lead  us  astray.  Many  of 
my  readers  will  recall  to  mind, perhaps,  the  intellectual 
shock  they  experienced  when  they  heard  for  the  first 
time  that  a  magnetic  needle  lying  in  the  magnetic 
meridian  is  deflected  in  a  definite  direction  away  from 
the  meridian  by  a  wire  conducting  a  current  being  car- 
ried along  in  a  parallel  direction  above  it.  The  instinc- 
tive is  just  as  fallible  as  the  distinctly  conscious.  Its  only 
value  is  in  provinces  with  which  we  are  very  familiar. 
Let  us  rather  put  to  ourselves,  in  preference  to 
pursuing  mystical  speculations  on  this  subject,   the 


28  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

The  origin  question :  How  does  instinctive  knowledge  originate 

of  instinc- 

tiveknowi-  and  what  are  its  contents?     Everything  which  we  ob- 
serve in  nature  imprints  itself  uncomprehended  and  u^ti- 
analysed  in  our  percepts  and  ideas,  which,  then,  in  their 
turn,  mimic  the  processes  of  nature  in  their  most  gen- 
eral and  most  striking  features.    In  these  accumulated 
experiences  we  possess  a  treasure-store  which  is  ever 
close  at  hand  and  of  which  only  the  smallest  portion 
is  embodied  in  clear  articulate  thought.     The  circum- 
stance that  we  are  easier  able  to  employ  these  expe- 
riences than  we  are  nature  itself,  and  that  they  are, 
notwithstanding  this,  free,  in  the  sense  indicated,  from 
all  subjectivity,  invests  them  with  a  high  value.     It 
is  a  peculiar  property  of  instinctive  knowledge  that  it 
is  predominantly  of  a  negative  nature.     We  cannot  so 
well  say  what  must  happen  as  we  can  what  cannot  hap- 
pen, since  the  latter  alone  stands  in  glaring  contrast  to 
the  obscure  mass  of  experience  in  us  in  which  single 
characters  are  not  distinguished. 
Instinctive         Still,  great  as  the  importance  of  instinctive  knowl- 
and%tera-edge  may  be,  for  discovery,  we  must  not,  from  our 
mutnaiiy     poiut  of  vicw,  rest  Content  with  the  recognition  of  its 
each  other,  authority.     We  must  inquire,  on  the  contrary  :  Under 
what  conditions  could  the  instinctive  knowledge  in 
question  have  originated?  We  then  ordinarily  find  that 
the  very  principle  to  establish  which  we  had  recourse 
to  instinctive  knowledge,  constitutes  in  its  turn  the  fun- 
damental condition  of  the  origin  of  that  knowledge. 
And  this  is  quite  obvious  and  natural.     Our  instinctive 
knowledge  leads  us  to  the  principle  which  explains  that 
knowledge  itself,  and  which  is  in  its  turn  also  corrobo- 
rated by  the  existence  of  that  knowledge,  which  is  a 
separate  fact  by  itself.     This  we  will  find  on  close  ex- 
amination is  the  state  of  things  in  Stevinus's  case. 


iA 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  ST  A  TICS,  29 

3.  The  reasoning  of  Stevinus  impresses  us  as  soTheinRen- 
highly  ingenious  because  the  result  at  which  he  arrives  vinns's  rea- 
apparently  contains  more  than  the  assumption  from 
which  he  starts.  While  on  the  one  hand,  to  avoid  con- 
tradictions, we  are  constrained  to  let  the  result  pass,  on 
the  other  an  incentive  remains  which  impels  us  to  seek 
further  insight.  If  Stevinus  had  distinctly  set  forth 
the  entire  fact  in  all  its  aspects,  as  Galileo  subsequently 
did,  his  reasoning  would  no  longer  strike  us  as  ingen- 
ious ;  but  we  should  have  obtained  a  much  more  satis- 
factory and  clear  insight  into  the  matter.  In  the 
endless  chain  which  does  not  glide  upon  the  prism,  is 
contained,  in  fact,  everything.  We  might  say,  the 
chain  does  not  glide  because  no  sinking  of  heavy  bodies 
takes  place  here.  This  would  not  be  accurate,  how- 
ever, for  when  the  chain  moves  many  of  its  links  really 
do  descend,  while  others  rise  in  their  place.  We  must 
say,  therefore,  more  accurately,  the  chain  does  not 
glide  because  for  every  body  that  could  possibly  de-  critique  of 
scend  an  equally  heavy  body  would  have  to  ascend  deduction, 
equally  high,  or  a  body  of  double  the  weight  half  the 
height,  and  so  on.  This  fact  was  familiar  to  Stevinus, 
who  presented  it,  indeed,  in  his  theory  of  pulleys ; 
but  he  was  plainly  too  distrustful  of  himself  to  lay 
down  the  law,  without  additional  support,  as  also  valid 
for  the  inclined  plane.  But  if  such  a  law  did  not  exist 
universally,  our  instinctive  knowledge  respecting  the 
endless  chain  could  never  have  originated.  With  this 
our  minds  are  completely  enlightened. — The  fact  that 
Stevinus  did  not  go  as  far  as  this  in  his  reasoning  and 
rested  content  with  bringing  his  (indirectly  discovered) 
ideas  into  agreement  with  his  instinctive  thought,  need 
not  further  disturb  us. 

The  service  which  Stevinus  renders  himself  and  his 


30  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

hemsrit   readers,  consists,  therefore,  in  the  contrast  and  coin- 

ji-aproce-  parison  of  knowledge  that  is  instinctive  with  knowledge 

that  is  clear,  in  the  bringing  the  two  into  connection 

and  accord  with  one  another,  and  in  the  supporting 


the  one  upon  the  other.  The  strengthening  of  mental 
view  which  Stevinus  acquired  by  this  procedure,  we 
learn  from  the  fact  that  a  picture  of  the  endless  chain 
and  the  prism  graces  as  vignette,  with  the  inscrlptioa 
"Wonder  en  is  gheen  wonder,"  the  title-page  of  his 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS. 


31 


work  Hypomnemata  Mathematica  (Leyden,  1605).*  As 
a  fact,  every  enlightening  progress  made  in  science  is 
accompanied  with  a  certain  feeling  of  disillusionment. 
We  discover  that  that  which  appeared  wonderful  to 
us  is  no  more  wonderful  than  other  things  which  we 
know  instinctively  and  regard  as  self-evident ;  nay, 
that  the  contrary  would  be  much  more  wonderful ;  that 
everywhere  the  same  fact  expresses  itself.  Our  puzzle 
turns  out  then  to  be  a  puzzle  no  more  ;  it  vanishes  into 
nothingness,  and  takes  its  place  among  the  shadows 
of  history. 

4.  After  he  had  arrived  at  the  principle  of  the  in- 
clined plane,  it  was  easy  for  Stevinus  to  apply  that 
principle  to  the  other  machines;  and  to  explain  by  it 
their  action.  ^He  makes,  for  example,  the  following 
application.  ■ 

We  have,  let  us  suppose,  an  inclined  plane  (Fig. 
22)  and  on  it  a  load  Q,  We  pass  a  string  over  the 
pulley  A  at  the  summit  and  imagine  the  load  Q  held  in 
equilibrium  by  the  load  P, 
Stevinus, now,  proceeds  by 
a  method  similar  to  that 
later  taken  by  Galileo.  He 
remarks  that  it  is  not  ne- 
cessary that  the  load  Q 
should  lie  directly  on  the 
inclined  plane.     Provided  '  p»k-  «« 

only  the  form  of  the  machine's  motion  be  preserved,  the 
proportion  between  force  and  load  will  in  all  cases  re- 
main the  same.  We  may  therefore  equally  well  conceive 
the  load  Q  to  be  attached  to  a  properly  weighted  string 
passing  over  a  pulley  D:  which  string  is  normal  to  the 

*The  title  given  is  that  of  Willebrord  Snell's  Latin  translation  (1608)  of 
Simon  Stevin's  IVisconstigt  Gtdackttnisstnt  Leyden,  i6o5.~7Va»r. 


Enlighten- 
ment in 
science  al- 
ways ac- 
companied 
with  disillu- 
sionment. 


Explana- 
tion of  the 
other  ma- 
chines by 
Stevinus's 
principle. 


32 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 


The  funicu- 
lar machine 


And  the 
special  case 
ox  the  paral- 
lelogram of 
forces. 


The  general 
form  of  the 
last-men- 
tioned prin- 
ciple also 
employed. 


inclined  plane.     If  we  carry  out  this  alteration,   ive 
shall  have  a  so-called  funicular  machine.     We  nomr 
perceive  that  we  can  ascertain  very  easily  the  portion 
of  weight  with  which  the  body  on  the  inclined  plane 
tends  downwards.     We  have  only  to  draw  a  vertical 
line  and  to  cut  off  on  it  a  portion  ab  corresponding  to 
the  load  Q,     Then  drawing  on  aA  the  perpendicular 
bcy  we  have  F/Q  =  AC/AB  =  ac/ab.     Therefore  ac 
represents  the  tension  of  the  string  aA,     Nothing  pre- 
vents us,  now,   from  making  the  two  strings  change 
functions  and  from  imagining  the  load  Q  to  lie  on  the 
dotted  inclined  plane  EDF.     Similarly,  here,  we  ob- 
tain ad  for  the  tension  of  the  second  string.     In  this 
manner,  accordingly,  Stevinus  indirectly  arrives  at  a 
knowledge  of  the  statical  relations  of  the  funicular 
machine  and  of  the  so-called  parallelogram  of  forces ;  at 
first,  of  course,  only  for  the  particular  case  of  strings 
(or  forces)  ac^  ad  at  right  angles  to  one  another. 

Subsequently,  indeed,  Stevinus  employs  the  prin- 
ciple of  the  composition  and  resolution  of  forces  in 
a  more  general  form ;  yet  the  method  by  which  he 

X 


Fig.  23  Fi(5.  34. 

reached  the  principle,  is  not  very  clear,  or  at  least  is 
not  obvious.  He  remarks,  for  example,  that  if  we 
have  three  strings  AB^  AC,  AD,   stretched  at  any 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS. 


33 


given  angles,  and  the  weight  F  is  suspended  from  the 
first,  the  tensions  may  be  determined  in  the  following 
manner.     We  produce  (Fig.  23)  AB  to  X  and  cut  off 
on  it  a  portion  AE.     Drawing  from  the  point  E^  EF 
parallel  to  AD  and  EG  paral- 
lel to  A  C\  the  tensions  of  AB, 
AC,  AD  are  respectively  pro- 
portional to  AEj  AF,  AG. 

With  the  assistance  of  this 
principle  of  construction  Ste- 
vinus   solves    highly   compli-  fir.  25. 

Gated    problems.     He   determines,   for  instance,   the  solution  of 
tensions  of  a  system  of  ramifying  strings  like  that  pUcYted"^ 
illustrated  in  Fig.  24;  in  doing  which  of  course  he^'**  **™*' 
starts  from  the  given  tension  of  the  vertical  string. 

The  relations  of  the  tensions  of  a  funicular  polygon 
are  likewise  ascertained  by  construction,  in  the  man- 
ner indicated  in  Fig.  25. 

We  may  therefore,  by  means  of  the  principle  of  the  General  re- 
inclined  plane,  seek  to  elucidate  the  conditions  of  op- 
eration of  the  other  simple  machines,  in  a  manner  sim- 
ilar to  that  which  we  employed  in  the  case  of  the  prin- 
ciple of  the  lever. 


III. 

THE  PRINCIPLE  OF  THE  COMPOSITION  OF  FORCES. 

I.  The  principle  of  the  parallelogram  of  forces,  atTheprinci- 

which  Stevinus  arrived  and  employed,  (yet  without  ex-  parallelog- 
ram of 


pressly  formulating  it,)  consists,  as  we  know,  of  thefoi 
following  truth.     If  a  body  A  (Fig.  26)  is  acted  upon 
by  two  forces  whose  directions  coincide  with  the  lines 
AB  and  AC,  and  whose  magnitudes  are  proportional  to 
the  lengths  AB  and  AC,  these  two  forces  produce  the 


orces. 


34 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 


Pig.  26. 


same  effect  as  a  single  force,  which  acts  in  the  direction 
of  the  diagonal  AD  of  the  parallelogram  ABCD  and  is 
proportional  to  that  diagonal.     For  instance,  if  on  the 

strings  AB^  AC  weights 
exactly  proportional  to  the 
lengths  AB^  AC  be  sup- 
posed to  act,  a  single 
weight  acting  on  the  string 
>4Z>  exactly  proportional  to 
the  length  AD  will  produce  the  same  effect  as  the  first 
two.  The  forces  AB  and  A  C  are  called  the  compo- 
nents, the  force  AD  the  resultant.  It  is  furthermore 
obvious,  that  conversely,  a  single  force  is  replaceable 
by  two  or  several  other  forces. 
Method  by         2.  We  shall  now  endeavor,  in  connection  with  the 

which  the 

general  no-  investigations  of  Stevinus,  to  give  ourselves  some  idea 

tion  of  the  »         o 

paraiieio-  of  the  manner  in  which  the 

gram  of  \,^  Jf 

forces         \  f  general  proposition  of  the 

beenar-         \^^^^-"^"'|\  parallelogram    of     forces 

rived  at.  Af^^ si  \  •    i.    ,  l  •       j 

might  have  been  arrived 
at.  The  relation, — dis- 
covered by  Stevinus, — 
that  exists  between  two 
mutually  perpendicular 
forces  and  a  third  force 
that  equilibrates  them,  we 
shall  assume  as  (indi- 
rectly) given.  We  sup- 
pose now  (Fig.  27)  that 
there  act  on  three  strings 
OX,  O  y,  OZ,  pulls  which 


X. 


Fig.  27. 

balance  each  other.  Let  us  endeavor  to  determine  the 
nature  of  these  pulls.  Each  pull  holds  the  two  remain- 
ing ones  in  equilibrium.    The  pull  (7Kwe  will  replace 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS.  35 

(following  Stevinus's  principle)  by  two  new  rectangular  The  dedac- 
pulls,   one  in  the   direction   Ou  (the  prolongation  ofRenerai 

principie 

OX\  and  one  at  right  angles  thereto  in  the  direction  xrom  the 

"^  c»  t»  ^  special  case 

Ov,  And  let  us  similarly  resolve  the  pull  OZ  in  theofstevinus. 
directions  Ou  and  Ow.  The  sum  of  the  pulls  in  the  di- 
rection Ouy  then,  must  balance  the  pull  OX,  and  the 
two  pulls  in  the  directions  Ov  and  Oiv  must  mutually 
destroy  each  other.  Taking  the  two  latter  as  equal 
and  opposite,  and  representing  them  by  Om  and  On, 
we  determine  coincidently  with  the  operation  the  com- 
ponents Op  and  Of  parallel  to  Ou,  as  well  also  as  the 
pulls  Or,  Os,  Now  the  sum  Op  -j-  Oq  is  equal  and  op- 
posite to  the  pull  in  the  direction  of  OX ;  and  if  we 
draw  st  parallel  to  O  Y,  or  rt  parallel  to  OZ,  either  line 
will  cut  off  the  portion  Ot  =^  Op  -\-  Oq :  with  which  re- 
sult the  general  principle  of  the  parallelogram  of  forces 
is  reached. 

The  general  case  of  composition  may  be  deduced  a  different 
in  still  another  way  from  the  special  composition  of  same  de- 
rectangular  forces.  Let  OA  and  OB  be  the  two  forces 
acting  at  ^.  For  ^.5  substitute 
a  force  OC  acting  parallel  to 
OA  and  a  force  OD  acting  at 
right   angles  to  OA,      There 
then  act  for  OA  and  OB  the 
two  forces  OE  =  OA  -\-  OC  ^^'  ^• 

and  OD,  the  resultant  of  which  forces  OF  is  at  the  same 
time  the  diagonal  of  the  parallelogram  OAFB  con- 
structed on  OA  and  OB  as  sides. 

^      3.  The  principle  of  the  parallelogram  of  forces,  The  pnn- 
when  reached  by  the  method  of  Stevinus,  presents  it-  presena  it- 
self as  an  indirect  discovery.     It  is  exhibited  as  a  con-  indirect 
sequence  and  as  the  condition  of  known  facts.     We 
perceive,  however,  merely  that  it  does  exist,  not,  as  yet 


0     ( 

C              A      E 

\ 

■^\ 

I 

i    J 

5                 7- 

36 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 


And  is  first  why  it  exists ;  that  is,  we  cannot  reduce  it  (as  in  dy- 
enunciated  namics)  to  Still  simpler  propositions.     In  statics,  in- 
and  varig-  deed,  the  principle  was  not  fully  admitted  until  the 
time  of  Varignon,  when  dynamics,  which  leads  directly 
to  the  principle,  was  already  so  far  advanced  that  its 
adoption  therefrom  presented  no  difficulties.   The  prin- 
ciple of  the  parallelogram  of  forces  was  first  clearly 
^enunciated  by  Newton  in  his  Principles  of  Natural  Phi- 
losophy.  In  the  same  year,  Varignon,  independently  of 
Newton,  also  enunciated  the  principle,  in  a  work  sub- 
mitted to  the  Paris  Academy  (but  not  published  un- 
til after  its  author's  death),  and  made,  by  the  aid  of  a 
geometrical  theorem,   extended  practical  application 
of  it.* 

The  geometrical  theorem  referred  to  is  this.  If  we 
consider  (Fig.  29)  a  parallelogram  the  sides  of  which 
are/  and  ^,  and  the  diagonal  is  r,  and  from  any  point  m 

in  the  planq  of  the  par- 
allelogram we  draw  per- 
pendiculars   on    these 
three     straight      lines, 
which     perpendiculars 
we    will    designate    as 
Uy  V,   Wy   then  /.«-(- 
q  ,  V  :=.  r .  w.     This  is 
easily  proved  by  draw- 
Fig.  39.  Fig.  30.  ing  straight  lines  from  m 
to  the  extremities  of  the  diagonal  and  of  the  sides  of 
the  parallelogram,  and  considering  the  areas  of  the 
triangles  thus  formed,  which  are  equal  to  the  halves 
of  the  products  specified.     If  the  point  m  be  taken 
within  the  parallelogram  and  perpendiculars  then  be 


The  geo- 
metrical 
theorem 
emplojred 
by  Varig- 
non. 


*  In  the  same  year,  1687,  Father  Bernard  Lami  published  a  little  appendix 
to  his  Traiti  <U  michanique^  developing  the  same  principle.— TVtfjw. 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS.  yj 

drawn,  the  theorem  passes  into  the  form p ,u  —  q ,v 
z=r  .w.  Finally,  if  m  be  taken  on  the  diagonal  and 
perpendiculars  again  be  drawn,  we  shall  get,  since  the 
perpendicular  let  fall  on  the  diagonal  is  now  zero, 
/.  u  —  ^.z;  =  0  or/,  u  ^=  q ,v. 

With  the  assistance  of  the  observation  that  forces  The  dedoc- 
are  proportional  to  the  motions  produced  by  them  in 
equal  intervals  of  time,  Varignon  easily  advances  from 
the  composition  of  motions  to  the  composition  of  forces. 
Forces,  which  acting  at  a  point  are  represented  in 
magnitude  and  direction  by  the  sides  of  a  parallelo- 
gram, are  replaceable  by  a  single  force,  similarly  rep- 
resented by  the  diagonal  of  that  parallelogram. 

If  now,  in  the  parallelogram  considered,/  and  ^Moments of 
represent  the  concurrent  forces  (the  components)  and  r  °'^"'* 
the  force  competent  to  take  their  place  (the  resultant), 
then  the  products  pu,  qv,  rw  are  called  the  moments 
of  these  forces  with  respect  to  the  point  m.  If  the  point 
m  lie  in  the  direction  of  the  resultant,  the  two  moments 
pu  and  qv  are  with  respect  to  it  equal  to  each  other. 

4.   With  the  assistance  of  this  principle  Varignon  is  vangnon's 

•-.•         .      .         -  treatment 

now  m  a  position  to  treat  y  of  the  sim- 

the  machines  in  a  much  \      /  ?h1nes. 

simpler  manner  than  were 
his  predecessors.  Let  us 
consider,  for  example, 
(Fig.  31)  a  rigid  body 
capable  of  rotation  about 
an  axis  passing  through 
O,  Perpendicular  to  the 
axis  we  conceive  a  plane, 
'and     select    therein    two  ^'^  ^'' 

points  Ay  B,  on  which  two  forces  P  and  Q  in  the  plane 
are  supposed  to  act.     We  recognise  with  Varignon 


38  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

Tho  deduc-  that  the  effect  of  the  forces  is  not  altered  if  their  points 

ttnn  of  the 

law  of  the    of  application  be  displaced  along  their  line  of  action, 

lever  from       .  ,  . 

the  parai-    since  all  points  in  the  same  direction  are  rigidly  con- 

lelosram* 

principle,  nected  with  one  another  and  each  one  presses  and  pulls 
the  other.  We  may,  accordingly,  suppose  P  applied 
at  any  point  in  the  direction  AX,  and  Q  at  any  point 
in  the  direction  BY^  consequently  also  at  their  point 
of  intersection  M.  With  the  forces  as  displaced  to  My 
then,  we  construct  a  parallelogram,  and  replace  the 
forces  by  their  resultant.  We  have  now  to  do  only 
with  the  effect  of  the  latter.  If  it  act  only  on  movable 
points,  equilibrium  will  not  obtain.  If,  however,  the 
direction  of  its  action  pass  through  the  axis,  through 
the  point  O,  which  is  not  movable,  no  motion  can  take 
place  and  equilibrium  will  obtain.  In  the  latter  case 
^  is  a  point  on  the  resultant,  and  if  we  drop  the  per- 
pendiculars u  and  V  from  O  on  the  directions  of  the 
forces  /,  q,  we  shall  have,  in  conformity  with  the  the- 
orem before  mentioned,  p  -  u=zq  •  v.  With  this  we 
have  deduced  the  law  of  the  lever  from  the  principle 
of  the  parallelogram  of  forces. 
The  statics  Varignon  explains  in  like  manner  a  number  of  other 
adyna2?csa  cases  of  equilibrium  by  the  equilibration  of  the  result- 
ant force  by  some  obstacle  or  restraint.  On  the  in- 
clined plane,  for  example,  equilibrium  exists  if  the  re- 
sultant is  found  to  be  at  right  angles  to  the  plane.  In 
fact,  Varignon  rests  statics  in  its  entirety  on  a  dynamic 
foundation ;  to  his  mind,  it  is  but  a  special  case  of  dy- 
namics. The  more  general  dynamical  case  constantly 
hovers  before  him  and  he  restricts  himself  in  his  inves- 
tigation voluntarily  to  the  case  of  equilibrium.  We 
are  confronted  here  with  a  dynamical  statics,  such 
as  was  possible  only  after  the  researches  of  Galileo. 
'        Incidentally,  it  may  be  remarked,  that  from  Varignon 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STA  TICS, 


39 


is  derived  the  majority  of  the  theorems  and  methods 
of  presentation  which  make  up  the  statics  of  modem 
elementary  text-books. 

5.  As  we  have  abready  seen,  purely  statical  consid-  special 

.  .  staticalcoo- 

erations  also  lead  to  the  proposition  of  the  parallel-  siderations 
ogram  of  forces.  In  special  cases,  in  fact,  the  principle  the  prin- 
admits  of  being  very  easily  verified.  We  recognise  at 
once,  for  instance,  that  any  number  whatsoever  of  equal 
forces  acting  (by  pull  or  pressure)  in  the  same  plane  at 
a  point,'  around  which  their  suc- 
cessive lines  make  equal  angles, 
are  in  equilibrium.  If,  for  exam- 
ple, (Fig.  32)  the  three  equal 
forces  OAj  OB,  OC  act  on  the 
point  O  at  angles  of  120°,  each 
two  of  the  forces  holds  the  third 
in  equilibrium.  We  see  imme- 
diately that  the  resultant  of  OA 
and  OB  is  equal  and  opposite  to  ^C  It  is  represented 
by  OD  and  is  at  the  same  time  the  diagonal  of  the 
parallelogram  OADB,  which  readily  follows  from  the 
fact  that  the  radius  of  a  circle  is  also  the  side  of  the 
hexagon  included  by  it. 

6.  If  the  concurrent  forces  act  in  the  same  or  in  The  case  of 
opposite  directions,  the  resultant  is  equal  to  the  sum  forces  ^ 
or  the  difference  of  the  parttcaiar 

_  .  t«r  O  A  case  of  the 

components.     We  rec-  1 — ^^-^  ^        Renerai 

ognise  both  cases  with-     B*  ^  r»        C    P^ncipie. 

out     any    difficulty    as 
particular  cases  of  the 
principle  of  the  paral- 
lelogram of  forces.     If  in  the  two  drawings  of  Fig.  33 
we  imagine  the  angle  A  OB  to  be  gradually  reduced 
to  the  value  0°,  and  the  angle  A'  ff  B'  increased  to  the 


Fig.  3a. 


Fig.  33. 


40  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

value  1 80°,  we  shall  perceive  that  repasses  into  OA  -(- 
AC=OA-^OBzxi^  a  C  into  a  A  —  A  C  =  a  A* 
—  (y  B.  The  principle  of  the  parallelogram  of  forces 
includes,  accordingly,  propositions  which  are  generally 
made  to  precede  it  as  independent  theorems. 
The  princi-       7.  The  principle  of  the  parallelogram  of  forces,  in 

pteapropo-  ***«-' 

shionde-    the  form  in  which  it  was  set  forth  by  Newton  and 

rived  from  ,  ,  ,   . 

eiperieuce.  Varignon,  clearly  discloses  itself  as  a  proposition  de- 
rived from  experience.  A  point  acted  on  by  two  forces 
describes  with  accelerations  proportional  to  the  forces 
two  mutually  independent  motions.  On  this  fact  the 
parallelogram  construction  is  based.  Daniel  Ber- 
noulli, however,  was  of  opinion  that  the  proposition  of 
the  parallelogram  of  forces  was  a  geometrical  truth,  in- 
dependent of  physical  experience.  And  he  attempted 
to  furnish  for  it  a  geometrical  demonstration,  the  chief 
features  of  which  we  shall  here  take  into  consideration, 
as  the  Bernoullian  view  has  not,  even  at  the  present 
day,  entirely  disappeared. 
Daniel  Ber-  If  two  equal  forces,  at  right  angles  to  each  other 
tempted  (Fig.  34),  act  on  a  point,  there  can  be  no  doubt,  ac- 
Seuons^a-  ^  cording  to  Bernoulli,  that  the  line 

^  y1\  o^   bisection  of  the   angle   (con- 

formably to  the  principle  of  sym- 
metry) is  the  direction  of  the  re- 
sultant r.  To  determine  geomet- 
rically also  the  magnitude  of  the 
resultant,  each  of  the  forces  /  is 
^**-  3^'  decomposed  into  two  equal  forces 

qy  parallel  and  perpendicular  to  r.  The  relation  in 
respect  of  magnitude  thus  produced  between  /  and  q 
is  consequently  the  same  as  that  between  r  and  /.  We 
have,  accordingly: 

p  =  ^,  q  and  r  =1  fx  .  f\  whence  r  =  fx'^q. 


fometricai 
euonstra 

tion  of  the 

truth 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS. 


41 


Since,  however,  the  forces  q  acting  at  right  angles 
to  r  destroy  each  other,  while  those  parallel  to  r  con- 
stitute the  resultant,  it  further  follows  that 

r  =  2^;  hence  jx  =  l/2,  and  r  =  i/2  .  /. 

The  resultant,  therefore,  is  represented  also  in  re- 
spect of  magnitude  by  the  diagonal  of  the  square  con- 
structed on  /  as  side. 

Similarly,  the  magnitude  may  be  determined  of  the  The  case  of 
resultant  of  unequal  rectangular  components.     Here,  rectangaiar 

however,  nothing  is  known  before-  ^ 

hand  concerning  the  direction  of 
the  resultant  r.  If  we  decompose 
the  components  /,  q  (Fig.  35),  A 
parallel  and  perpendicular  to  the 
yet  undetermined  direction  r,  into 
the  forces  «,  j  and  v,  /,  the  new 
forces  will  form  with  the  compo- 
nents /,  q  the  same  angles  that  fi, 
q  form  with  r.  From  which  fact  the  following  relations 
in  respect  of  magnitude  are  determined : 


Fig.  35. 


u  a        V 


s  p         t' 


p        u  Q        '^     Q 

from  which  two  latter  equations  follows  s  =z  t  =  pq/r. 
On  the  other  hand,  however. 


/ 


2 


r  =  «+»  =  -"—+  -i^  or  r*  =/»  +  g*. 

r  r 

The  diagonal  of  the  rectangle  constructed  on  /  and 
q  represents  accordingly  the  magnitude  of  the  result- 
ant. 

Therefore,  for  all  rhombs,  the  direction  of  the  re-  General  re- 
sultant is  determined ;  for  all  rectangles,  the  magni- 
tude; and  for  squares  both  magnitude  and  direction. 
Bernoulli  then  solves  the  problem  of  substituting  for 


42  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

two  equal  forces  acting  at  one  given  angle,  other  equal, 
equivalent  forces  acting  at  a  different  angle  ;  and  finally 
arrives  by  circumstantial  considerations,  not  wholly 
exempt  from  mathematical  objections,  but  amended 
later  by  Poisson,  at  the  general  principle. 
Critiqne  of        8.   Let  US  uow  examine  the  physical  aspect  of  this 

Bernoulli's  '^'  a^      A    t 

method,  question.  As  a  proposition  derived  from  experience, 
the  principle  of  the  parallelogram  of  forces  was  already 
known  to  Bernoulli.  What  Bernoulli  really  does,  there- 
fore, is  to  simulate  towards  himself  a  complete  ignorance 
of  the  proposition  and  then  attempt  to  philosophise 
it  abstractly  out  of  the  fewest  possible  assumptions. 
Such  work  is  by  no  means  devoid  of  meaning  and  pur- 
pose. On  the  contrary,  we  discover  by  such  proce- 
dures, how  few  and  how  imperceptible  the  experiences 
are  that  suffice  to  supply  a  principle.  Only  we  must 
not  deceive  ourselves,  as  Bernoulli  did  ;  we  must  keep 
before  our  minds  all  the  assumptions,  and  should  over- 
look no  experience  which  we  involuntarily  employ. 
What  are  the  assumptions,  then,  contained  in  Bernoul- 
li's deduction? 
The  as-  Q.  Statics,  primarily,  is  acquainted  with  force  only 

ofhlsd"*  as  a  pull  or  a  pressure,  that  from  whatever  source  it 
rived^from  may  come  always  admits  of  being  replaced  by  the  pull 
experience.  ^^  ^^  pressure  of  a  weight.  All  forces  thus  may  be  re- 
garded as  quantities  of  the  same  kind  and  be  measured 
by  weights.  Experience  further  instructs  us,  that  the 
particular  factor  of  a  force  which  is  determinative  of 
equilibrium  or  determinative  of  motion,  is  contained 
not  only  in  the  magnitude  of  the  force  but  also  in  its 
direction^  which  is  made  known  by  the  direction  of  the 
resulting  motion,  by  the  direction  of  a  stretched  cord, 
or  in  some  like  manner.  We  may  ascribe  magnitude 
indeed  to  other  things  given  in  physical  experience, 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OE  STATICS.  43 

such  as  temperature,  potential  function,  but  not  direc- 
tion. The  fact  that  both  magnitude  and  direction  are 
determinative  in  the  efficiency  of  a  force  impressed  on 
a  point  is  an  important  though  it  may  be  an  unob- 
trusive experience. 

Granting,  then,  that  the  magnitude  and  direction  M^itude 
of  forces  impressed  on  a  point  alone  are  decisive,  it  will  tion  the  sole 
be  perceived  that  two  equal  and  opposite  forces,  as  they  factors, 
cannot  uniquely  and  precisely  determine  any  motion, 
are  in  equilibrium.  So,  also,  at 
right  angles  to  its  direction,  a 
force/  is  unable  uniquely  to  de-  ' 

termine  a  motional  effect.     But  

if  a  force  /  is  inclined  at  an  an- 
gle to  another  direction  ss*  (Fig. 

36),  it  is  able  to  determine  a  mo-  

tion  in  that  direction.     Yet  ex-         ^'  * 

perience  alone  can  inform  us,  **'  ^  * 

that  the  motion  is  determined  in  the  direction  of  s*  s 
and  not  in  that  of  x/  ;  that  is  to  say,  in  the  direction 
of  the  side  of  the  acute  angle  or  in  the  direction  of  the 
projection  of  /  on  s's. 

Now  this  latter  experience  is  made  use  of  by  Ber-  Thec^ee/of 
noulli  at  the  very  start.     The  sense,  namely,  of  the  re-  derfSabS 
sultant  of  two  equal  forces  acting  at  right  angles  to  one  exiMrienca 
another  is  obtainable  only  on  the  ground  of  this  expe- 
rience.    From  the  principle  of  symmetry  follows  only, 
that  the  resultant  falls  in  the  plane  of  the  forces  and 
coincides  with  the  line  of  bisection  of  the  angle,  not 
however  that  it  falls  in  the  acute  angle.    But  if  we  sur- 
render this  latter  determination,  our  whole  proof  is  ex- 
ploded before  it  is  begun. 

10.  If,  now,  we  have  reached  the  conviction  that 
our  knowledge  of  the  effect  of  the  direction  of  a  force  is 


44  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

So  also       solely  obtainable  from  experience,  still  less  then  shall 

must  the  ,     ,-  -^  .  .    .     ,  ., 

form  of  the  we  believe  it  m  our  power  to  ascertain  by  any  other  way 

efftfct  be 

thusde-  the^r^i  of  this  effect.  It  is  utterly  out  of  our  power, 
to  divine,  that  a  force  p  acts  in  a  direction  s  that  makes 
with  its  own  direction  the  angle  or,  exactly  as  a  force 
/  cos  a  in  the  direction  s  ;  a  statement  equivalent  to  the 
proposition  of  the  parallelogram  of  forces.  Nor  was 
it  in  Bernoulli's  power  to  do  this.  Nevertheless,  he 
makes  use,  scarcely  perceptible  it  is  true,  of  expe- 
riences that  involve  by  implication  this  very  mathe- 
matical fact. 
The  man-  A  person  already  familiar  with  the  composition 

which  the    and  resolution  of  forces  is  well  aware  that  several  forces 

assump- 
tions men-  acting  at  a  point  are,  as  regards  their  effect,  replaceable, 

tioned  enter ,  - .  .         - 

into  Bcr-     m  evcry  respect  and  in  every  direction,  by  a  single  force. 

ducUon.  This  knowledge,  in  Bernoulli's  mode  of  proof,  is  ex- 
pressed in  the  fact  that  the  forces  />,  q  are  regarded  as 
absolutely  qualified  to  replace  in  all  respects  the  forces 
J,  u  and  /,  v,  as  well  in  the  direction  of  r  as  in  every 
other  direction.  Similarly  r  is  regarded  as  the  equiv- 
alent of  /  and  q.  It  is  further  assumed  as  wholly  in- 
different, whether  we  estimate  j,  «,  /,  v  first  in  the 
directions  of/,  q^  and  then/,  q  in  the  direction  of  r,  or 
J,  «,  /,  v  be  estimated  directly  and  from  the  outset  in 
the  direction  of  r.  But  this  is  something  that  a  person 
only  can  know  who  has  antecedently  acquired  a  very 
extensive  experience  concerning  the  composition  and 
resolution  of  forces.  We  reach  most  simply  the  knowl- 
edge of  the  fact  referred  to,  by  starting  from  the  knowl- 
edge of  another  fact,  namely  that  a  force  /  acts  in  a 
direction  making  with  its  own  an  angle  a^  with  an  effect 
equivalent  to  p  •  cos  a.  As  a  fact,  this  is  the  way  the 
perception  of  the  truth  was  reached. 

Let  the  coplanar  forces  P,  P\  P*\  .  .  be  applied  to 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STA  TICS.  45 

one  and  the  same  point  at  the  angles  a,  a\  or"  .  .  .  with  Mathemat- 

leal  analy~ 

a  given  direction  X.     These  forces,  let  us  suppose,  are  sis  of  the 
replaceable  by  a  single  force  U,  which  makes  with  Jf  the  true  and 

necessary 

an  angle  /i.     By  the  familiar  principle  we  have  then  assumptioa 

2Pcosa  =  7Icos/i. 

If  n  is  still  to  remain  the  substitute  of  this  system  of 
forces,  whatever  direction  X  may  take  on  the  system 
being  turned  through  any  angle  6,  we  shall  further 
have 

:^/'cos  (a  +  tf)  ==  77  COS  (pi  +  6), 
or 

(^Pcosa—IIcospi)  cos6  —  {2Psina  —  ilsin/^)  sind  =  0. 

If  we  put 

2P  cosa  — 77  cos//  =  A, 

—  {2Psina  —  77  sin//)  ==  B, 

B 
tanr  =  j-, 
A 

it  follows  that 

A  cos6  +  B  sintf  =  \/A^  +  B^  sin  (rf  +  t)  =  0, 

which  equation  can  subsist  for  ^vrry  6  only  on  the  con- 
dition that 

A  =  2Pcosa  —  IJcosju  =  0 
and 

B  =  {2Fsina  —  11  sin//)  =  0  ; 

whence  results 

77  cos//  =  2P  cosa 

77  sin//  =  2Psina. 

From  these  equations  follow  for  77  and  //  the  deter- 
minate values  * 

n=i/l{2Psmay  +  (2Pcosay'\ 

and 

2Psina  >  ' 

tan//  =  ^^ . 

2 P  cosa 


46  THE  SCIENCE  OF  AfECHANICS, 

The  actual         Granting,  therefore,  that  the  effect  of  a  force  in  every 

resnlts  not    _..  ,  j,.  ••  tt* 

deducibie    direction  Can  be  measured  by  its  projection  on  that  di- 

on  any  •  i  i  i.    #• 

other  sup-  rection,  then  truly  every  system  of  forces  acting  at  a 
point  is  replaceable  by  a  single  force,  determinate  in 
magnitude  and  direction.  This  reasoning  does  not  hold, 
however,  if  we  put  in  the  place  of  cos  a  any  general  func- 
tion of  an  angle,  (p  (a).  Yet  if  this  be  done,  and  we  still 
regard  the  resultant  as  determinate,  we  shall  obtain  for 
9?  (a),  as  may  be  seen,  for  example,  from  Poisson's 
deduction,  the  form  cos  a.  The  experience  that  several 
forces  acting  at  a  point  are  always,  in  every  respect, 
replaceable  by  a  single  force,  is  therefore  mathemat- 
ically equivalent  to  the  principle  of  the  parallelogram 
of  forces  or  to  the  principle  of  projection.  The  prin- 
ciple of  the  parallelogram  or  of  projection  is,  how- 
ever, much  easier  reached  by  observation  than  the 

General  re-  more  general  experience  above  mentioned  by  statical 
observations.  And  as  a  fact,  the  principle  of  the  par- 
allelogram was  reached  earlier.  It  would  require  in- 
deed an  almost  superhuman  power  of  perception  to 
deduce  mathematically,  without  the  guidance  of  any 
further  knowledge  of  the  actual  conditions  of  the  ques- 
tion, the  principle  of  the  parallelogram  from  the  gen- 
eral principle  of  the  equivalence  of  several  forces  to  a 
single  one.  We  criticise  accordingly  in  the  deduction 
of  Bernoulli  this,  that  that  which  is  easier  to  observe 
is  reduced  to  that  which  is  more  difficult  to  observe. 
This  is  a  violation  of  the  economy  of  science.  Bernoulli 
is  also  deceived  in  imagining  that  he  does  not  proceed 
from  any  fact  whatever  of  observation. 

An  addi-  We  must  further  remark  that  the  fact  that  the  forces 

aumption  of  are  independent  of  one  another,  which  is  involved  in 

Bernoulli.     .,         i  r    ^i      •  '^^  •  .^i 

the  law  of  their  composition,  is  another  experience 
which  Bernoulli  throughout  tacitly  employs.     As  long 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS.  47 

as  we  have  to  do  with  uniform  or  symmetrical  systems 
of  forces,  all  equal  in  magnitude,  each  can  be  affected 
by  the  others,  even  if  they  are  not  independent,  only 
to  the  same  extent  and  in  the  same  way.  Given  but 
three  forces,  however,  of  which  two  are  symmetrical 
to  the  third,  and  even  then  the  reasoning,  provided 
we  admit  that  the  forces  may  not  be  independent,  pre- 
sents considerable  difticulties. 

11.  Once  we  have  been  led,  directly  or  indirectly.  Discussion 
to  the  principle  of  the  parallelogram  of  forces,  once  we  scter  of  Oie 
have  perceived  it,  the  principle  is  just  as  much  an  ob-**      ^** 
servation  as  any  other.    If  the  observation  is  recent,  it 

of  course  is  not  accepted  with  the  same  confidence  as 
old  and  frequently  verified  observations.  We  then  seek 
to  support  the  new  observation  by  the  old,  to  demon- 
strate their  agreement.  By  and  by  the  new  observa- 
tion acquires  equal  standing  with  the  old.  It  is  then 
no  longer  necessary  constantly  to  reduce  it  to  the  lat- 
ter. Deduction  of  this  character  is  expedient  only  in 
cases  in  which  observations  that  are  difficult  directly 
to  obtain  can  be  reduced  to  simpler  ones  more  easily 
obtained,  as  is  done  with  the  principle  of  the  parallel- 
ogram of  forces  in  d3mamics. 

12.  The  proposition  of  the  parallelogram  of  forces  Bzi>erimen- 
has   also  been  illustrated  by  experiments  especially  tfon  of' he 
instituted  for  the  purpose.     An  apparatus  very  wellScontnv- 
adapted  to  this  end  was  contrived  by  Cauchy.     The  Suchy. 
centre  of  a  horizontal  divided  circle  (Fig.  37)  is  marked 

by  a  pin.  Three  threads /,/*, /",  tied  together  at  a 
point,  are  passed  over  grooved  wheels  r,  r*,  r",  which 
can  be  fixed  at  any  point  in  the  circumference  of  the 
circle,  and  are  loaded  by  the  weights  /,  /',  /".  If  three 
equal  weights  be  attached,  for  instance,  and  the  wheels 
placed  at  the  marks  of  division  o,  120,  240,  the  point  at 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 


Eipsrimea- which  the  Strings  are  knotted  will  assume  a  position 
1  just  above  the  centre  of  the  circle.    Three  equal  forces 
acting  at  angles  of  120°,  accordingly,  are  in  equilib- 
rium. 


principle. 


If  we  wish  to  represent  another  and  different  case, 
we  may  proceed  as  follows.  We  imagine  any  two 
forces/,  g  acting  at  any  angle  a,  represent  (Fig.  38) 
them  by  lines,  and  construct  on  them  as  sides  a  paral- 
lelogram. We  supply,  further,  a  force 
equal  and  opposite  to  the  resultant  r. 
The  three  forces  p,q,  —  r  hold  each 
other  in  equilibrium,  at  the  angles  vis- 
ible from  the  construction.  We  now 
place  the  wheels  of  the  divided  circle  on 
the  points  of  division  o,  a,  a-\-  j5,  and 
load  the  appropriate  strings  with  the 
weights/,  q,  r.  The  point  at  which  the 
strings  are  knotted  will  come  to  a  position  exactly 
above  the  middle  point  pf  thq  circle. 


n«-38. 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STA  TICS,  49 


IV. 
THE  PRINCIPLE  OF  VIRTUAL  VELOCITIES. 

I .  We  now  pass  to  the  discussion  of  the  principle  The  truth 

.  .  of  the  prin- 

of  virtual   (possible)   displacements.*     The  truth   of cipie first 

^  '  remarked 

this  principle  was  first  remarked  by  Stevinus  at  the  by  stevinus 
close  of  the  sixteenth  century  in  his  investigations  on 
the  equilibrium  of  pulleys  and  combinations  of  pulleys. 
Stevinus  treats  combinations  of  pulleys  in  the  same 
way  they  are  treated  at  the  present  day.     In  the  case 

*  Termed  in  English  the  principle  of  "  virtual  velocities,"  this  being  the 
original  phrase  (vUesst  virtuelU)  introduced  by  John  Bernoulli.  See  the 
text,  page  56.  The  word  virtualis  seems  to  have  been  the  fabrication  of  Duns 
Scotus  (see  the  Century  Dictionary ^  under  virtual) ;  but  virtualiter  was  used 
by  Aquinas,  and  virtu*  had  been  employed  for  centuries  to  translate  dbvafUC, 
and  therefore  as  a  synonym  for  potentia.  Along  with  many  other  scholastic 
terms,  virtual  passed  into  the  ordinary  vocabulary  of  the  English  language. 
Everybody  remembers  the  passage  in  the  third  book  of  Paradise  Lost^ 

"  Love  not  the  heav'niy  Spirits,  and  how  thir  Love 
Express  they,  by  looks  onely,  or  do  they  mix 
Irradiance,  virttiai  or  immediate  touch  r  " — Milton. 

So,  we  all  remember  how  it  was  claimed  before  our  revolution  that  America 
had  "  p/r/aM/ representation  "  in  parliament.  In  these  passages,  as  in  Latin, 
virtual  means :  existing  in  effect,  but  not  actually.  In  the  same  sense,  the 
word  passed  into  French ;  and  was  made  pretty  common  among  philosophers 
by  Leibnitz.  Thus,  he  calls  innate  ideas  in  the  mind  of  a  child,  not  yet  brought 
to  consciousness,  "des  connoissances  virtuelles.*^  This  does  not  mean  "  pos- 
sible," but  just  what  v/r/wa/ ordinarily  means  now,  as  just  defiuQd. 

The  principle  in  question  was  an  extension  to  the  case  of  more  than  two 
forces  of  the  old  rule  that  "what  a  machine  gains  in  power ^  it  loses  in  velocity.''* 
Bernoulli's  modification  reads  that  the  sum  of  the  products  of  the  forces  intojl 
their  virtual  velocities  must  vanish  to  give  equilibrium.  He  says,  in  effect :  || 
give  the  system  any  possible  and  infinitesimal  motion  you  please,  and  then 
the  simultaneous  displacements  of  the  points  of  application  of  the  forces, 
resolved  in  the  directions  (^  those  for ces^  though  they  are  not  exactly  velocities, 
since  they  are  only  displacements  in  one  time,  are,  nevertheless,  virtually 
velocities,  for  the  purpose  of  applying  the  rule  that  what  a  machine  gains  in 
power,  it  loses  in  velocity. 

Thomson  and  Tait  say  :  "  If  the  point  of  application  of  a  force  be  dis- 
placed through  a  small  space,  the  resolved  part  of  the  displacement  in  the  di- 
rection of  the  force  has  been  called  its  Virtual  Velocity.  This  is  positive  or 
negative  according  as  the  virtual  velocity  is  in  the  same,  or  in  the  opposite, 
direction  to  that  of  the  force."  This  agrees  with  Bernoulli's  definition  which 
may  be  found  in  Varignon's  Nouvelle  micanique^  Vol.  II,  Chap,  vl.— Trans, 


so  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

sie^noi'«  a  (Fig.  39)  equilibrium  obtains,  when  an  equal  weight  P 
''on«  ™  ihe  is  suspended  at  each  aide,  for  reasons  already  familiar. 
ofpuiiejB.    In  b,  the  weight  P  is  suspended  by  two  parallel  cords. 


each  of  which  accordingly  supports  the  weight  /*/2, 
with  which  weight  in  the  case  of  equilibrium  the  free 
end  of  the  cord  must  also  be  loaded.  In  c,  P  is  sus- 
pended by  six  cords,  and  the  weighting  of  the  free  ex- 
tremity with  /'/6  will  accordingly  produce  equilibrium. 
\Tid,  the  so-called  Archimedean  or  potential  pulley,*  P 
in  the  first  instance  is  suspended  by  two  cords,  each 
of  which  supports  Pji  ;  one  of  these  two  cords  in  turn 
is  suspended  by  two  others,  and  so  on  to  the  end,  so 
that  the  free  extremity  will  be  held  in  equilibrium  by 
the  weight  Pj%.  If  we  impart  to  these  assemblages 
of  pulleys  displacements  corresponding  to  a  descent  of 
the  weight  P  through  the  distance  h,  we  shall  observe 
that  as  a  result  of  the  arrangement  of  the  cords 


the  counterweight  P 

a  distance  A  i 

Pl^ 

p/e 

will  ascend 

P/8 

"       "     8A  ' 

THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS.  51 

In  a  system  of  pulleys  in  equilibrium,  therefore,  His  conciu- 

'  810ns  too 

the  products  of  the  weights  into  the  displacements  germ  of  the 
they  sustain  are  respectively  equal.  (**  Ut  spatium 
agentis  ad  spatium  patientis,  sic  potentia  patientis  ad 
potentiam  agentis." — Stevini,  Hypomnematay  T.  IV, 
lib.  3,  p.  172.)  In  this  remark  is  contained  the  germ 
of  the  principle  of  virtual  displacements. 

2.  Galileo  recognised  the  truth  of  the  principle  in  GaiUeo** 

,  ,     ,  ,  .  ,  recognition 

another  case,  and  that  a  somewhat  more  general  one ;  of  the  prin- 

•        .  ciple  in  the 

namely,  in  its  application  to  the  mclined  plane.     On  case  of  the 
an  inclined  plane  (Fig.  40),  plane, 

the  length  of  which  AB  is 
double  the  height  BC,  3.  load 
Q  placed  on  AB  is  held  in 
equilibrium  by  the  load  P  act- 
ing along  the  height  BCy  if 
P  =  Q/i,     If  the  machine  be 

set  in  motion,  P  =  Q/2  will  descend,  say,  the  vertical 
distance  h,  and  Q  will  ascend  the  same  distance  h  along 
the  incline  AB,  Galileo,  now,  allowing  the  phenom- 
enon to  exercise  its  full  effect  on  his  mind,  perceives, 
that  equilibrium  is  determined  not  by  the  weights 
alone  but  also  by  their  possible  approach  to  and  reces- 
sion from  the  centre  of  the  earth.  Thus,  while  Q/2  de- 
scends along  the  vertical  height  the  distance  h,  Q  as- 
cends h  along  the  inclined  length,  vertically,  however^ 
only  h/2  ;  the  result  being  that  the  products  Q{h/2) 
and  {Q/2')h  come  out  equal  on  both  sides.  The  eluci- 
dation that  Galileo's  observation  affords  and  the  light  character 
it  diffuses,  can  hardly  be  emphasised  strongly  enough,  observation 
The  observation  is  so  natural  and  unforced,  moreover, 
that  we  admit  it  at  once.  What  can  appear  simpler 
.  than  that  no  motion  takes  place  in  a  system  of  heavy 


52  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

bodies  when  on  the  whole  no  heavy  mass  can  descend. 
Such  a  fact  appears  instinctively  acceptable. 
Comparison       Galileo's  conception  of  the  inclined  plane  strikes 

of  it  with  .  . 

thatofste-  US  as  much  less  ingenious  than  that  of  Stevinus,  but 
we  recognise  it  as  more  natural  and  more  profound.  It 
is  in  this  fact  that  Galileo  discloses  such  scientific  great- 
ness :  that  he  had  the  intellectual  audacity  to  see,  in  a 
subject  long  before  investigated,  more  than  his  prede- 
cessors had  seen,  and  to  trust  to  his  own  perceptions. 
With  the  frankness  that  was  characteristic  of  him  he 
unreservedly  places  before  the  reader  his  own  view, 
together  with  the  considerations  that  led  him  to  it. 

The  Torn-         3.  ToRRiCELLi,  by  the  employment  of  the  notion  of 

cellian  , 

form  of  the  "centre  of  gravity,*'  has  put  Galileo's  principle  in  a 

principle.  «j  ^ 

form  in  which  it  appeals  still  more  to  our  instincts,  but 
in  which  it  is  also  incidentally  applied  by  Galileo  him- 
self. According  to  Torricelli  equilibrium  exists  in  a 
machine  when,  on  a  displacement  being  imparted  to  it, 
the  centre  of  gravity  of  the  weights  attached  thereto 
cannot  descend.  On  the  supposition  of  a  displacement 
in  the  inclined  plane  last  dealt  with,  P^  let  us  say,  de- 
scends the  distance  A,  in  compensation  wherefor  Q 
vertically  ascends  h .  sin  a.  Assuming  that  the  centre 
of  gravity  does  not  descend,  we  shall  have 

P.h — ^.-^sina       „         ^,        xi/-  a 
^  j-y^ =  0,  or  Z'.  ^  —  ^ .  //  sin  a  =  0, 

or 

If  the  weights  bear  to  one  another  some  different  pro- 
portion, then  the  centre  of  gravity  can  descend  when  a 
displacement  is  made,  and  equilibrium  will  not  obtain. 
We  expect  the  state  of  equilibrium  instinctively,  when 
-    the  centre  of  gravity  of  a  system  of  heavy  bodies  can- 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STA  TICS.  ^    53 

not  descend.  The  Torricellian  form  of  expression,  how- 
ever, contains  in  no  respect  more  than  the  Galilean. 

4.  As  with  systems  of  pulleys  and  with  the  inclined  The  appu- 
plane,  so  also  the  validity  of  *the  principle  of  virtual  the  pnnci- 
displacements  is  easily  demonstrable  for  the  other  ma-  other  ma- 
chines :  for  the  lever,  the  wheel  and  axle,  and  the  rest. 

In  a  wheel  and  axle,  for  instance,  with  the  radii  R,  r 
and  the  respective  weights  P^  Q,  equilibrium  exists, 
as  we  know,  when  PR  =  Qr.  If  we  turn  the  wheel 
and  axle  through  the  angle  a,  P  will  descend  Pa,  and 
Q  will  ascend  ra.  According  to  the  conception  of 
Stevinus  and  Galileo,  when  equilibrium  exists,  P.  Pa 
=  Q .  ra,  which  equation  expresses  the  same  thing  as 
the  preceding  one. 

5.  When  we  compare  a  system  of  heavy  bodies  in  The  cnte- 
which  motion  is  taking  place,  with  a  similar  system  state  of 
which  is  in  equilibrium,  the  question  forces  itself  upon  *^"*    ""™ 
us:  What  constitutes  the  difference  of  the  two  cases? 

What  is  the  factor  operative  here  that  determines  mo- 
tion, the  factor  that  disturbs  equilibrium, — the  factor 
that  is  present  in  the  one  case  and  absent  in  the  other? 
Having  put  this  question  to  himself,  Galileo  discovers 
that  not  only  the  weights,  but  also  the  distances  of 
their  vertical  descents  (the  amounts  of  their  vertical 
displacements)  are  the  factors  that  determine  motion. 
Let  us  call  P,  P\  P"  .  .  ,  the  weights  of  a  system  of 
heavy  bodies,  and  A,  K,  h*  ,  ,  ,  their  respective,  simul- 
taneously possible  vertical  displacements,  where  dis- 
placements downwards  are  reckoned  as  positive,  and 
displacements  upwards  as  negative.  Galileo  finds 
then,  that  the  criterion  or  test  of  the  state  of  equilib- 
rium is  contained  in  the  fulfilment  of  the  condition 
Ph  +  />'//  +  P"  >4"  +  .  .  .  =  0.  The  sum  Ph  +  P'h* 
-j-  P"h!*'\-  ...  is  the  factor  that  destroys  equilibrium. 


54  ^^^  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

the  factor  that  determines  motion.     Owing  to  its  im- 
portance this  sum  has  in  recent  times  been  character- 
ised by  the  special  designation  work. 
There  is  no       6.  Whereas  the  earlier  investigators,  in  the  compari- 
our  choice  son  of  cascs  of  equilibrium  and  cases  of  motion,  directed 
teria.  their  attention  to  the  weights  and  their  distances  from 

the  axis  of  rotation  and  recognised  the  statical  mo- 
ments as  the  decisive  factors  involved,  Galileo  fixes 
his  attention  on  the  weights  and  their  distances  of  de- 
scent and  discerns  work  as  the  decisive  factor  involved. 
It  cannot  of  course  be  prescribed  to  the  inquirer 
what  mark  or  criterion  of  the  condition  of  equilibrium 
he  shall  take  account  of,  when  several  are  present  to 
choose  from.  The  result  alone  can  determine  whether 
his  choice  is  the  right  one.  But  if  we  cannot,  for  rea- 
And  all  are  SOUS  already  stated,  regard  the  significance  of  the  stat- 
from  the     ical  moments  as  given  independently  of  experience,  as 


source.  Something  self-evident,  no  more  can  we  entertain  this 
view  with  respect  to  the  import  of  work.  Pascal  errs, 
and  many  modern  inquirers  share  this  error  with  him, 
when  he  says,  on  the  occasion  of  applying  the  principle 
of  virtual  displacements  to  fluids:  '*  Etant  clair  que  c'est 
la  meme  chose  de  faire  faire  un  pouce  de  chemin  k  cent 
livres  d'eau,  que  de  faire  faire  cent  pouces  de  chemin 
^  une  livre  d'eau. "  This  is  correct  only  on  the  suppo- 
sition that  we  have  already  come  to  recognise  work  as 
the  decisive  factor ;  and  that  it  is  so  is  a  fact  which 
experience  alone  can  disclose. 
Illustration  If  we  have  an  equal- armed,  equally- weighted  lever 
ceding  re-  before  US,  we  recognise  the  equilibrium  of  the  lever  as 
the  only  effect  that  is  uniquely  determined,  whether  we 
regard  the  weights  and  the  distances  or  the  weights 
and  the  vertical  displacements  as  the  conditions  that 
determine  motion.     Experimental  knowledge  of  this 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS.  55 

or  a  similar  character  must,  however,  in  the  necessity  of 

the  case  precede  any  judgment  of  ours  with  regard  to 

the  phenomenon  in  question.     The  particular  way  in 

which  the  disturbance  of  equilibrium  depends  on  the 

conditions  mentioned,  that  is  to  say,  the  significance 

of  the  statical  moment  {PL)  or  of  the  work  {Pk),  is 

even  less  capable  of  being  philosophically  excogitated 

than  the  general  fact  of  the  dependence. 

7.  When  two  equal  weights  with  equal  and  op-  RsdncUon 

posite  possible  displacements   are  opposed    to    eachenicuaot 
'^  ,  '^  .  ,  ,    .  ,  .,.,     iheprinci- 

other,  we  recognise  at  once  the  subsistence  of  equilib-  pia  to  iba 

ftlioplflr  HOd 

num.  We  might  now  be  tempted  to  reduce  the  more>pBci.ic«io 
general  case  of  the  weights  P,  P'  with  the  capacities  of 
displacement^, A',  where 
Ph  =  P'h',  to  the  sim- 
pler case.  Suppose  we 
have,  for  example,  (Fig, 
41)  the  weights  3  P  and 
^  Poaa.  wheel  and  axle 
with  the  radii  4  and  3. 
We  divide  the  weights 
into  equal  portions  of  the 

definite  magnitude  P,  which  we  designate  by  a,  b,  c, 
''■  'i  /'  S-  We  then  transport  a,  b,  c  to  the  level  +  3, 
and  d,  e,  f  to  the  level  —  3.  The  weights  will,  of 
themselves,  neither  enter  on  this  displacement  nor 
will  they  resist  it.  We  then  take  simultaneously  the 
weight  g  at  the  level  0  and  the  weight  a  at  the  level 
-|-  3,  push  the  first  upwards  to  —  i  and  the  second 
downwards  to  -f-  4,  then  again,  and  in  the  same  way, 
f  to  —  2  and  ^  to  4-  4,  f  to  —  3  and  <:  to  +  4.  To  all 
these  displacements  the  weights  offer  no  resistance, 
nor  do  they  produce  them  of  themselves.  Ultimately, 
however,  a,  b,  c  (or  3/^  appear  at  the  level  -f-  4  and 


56  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

The  gen-     //,  ^,  /,  g  (pr  \P)  at  the  level  —  3.     Consequently, 
with  respect  also  to  the  last-mentioned  total  displace- 
ment, the  weights  neither  produce  it  of  themselves 
nor  do  they  resist  it ;  that  is  to  say,  given  the  ratio  of 
displacement  here  specified,  and  the  weights  will  be 
in  equilibrium.     The  equation  4  .  3/* —  3 .  ^F=  0  is, 
therefore,  characteristic  of  equilibrium  in  the  case  as- 
sumed.    The   generalisation    (Fh  —  P'h'  =  0)  is  ob- 
vious. 
Thecondi-         If  we  Carefully  examine  the  reasoning  of  this  case, 
character    we  shall  quite  readily  perceive  that  the  inference  in- 
ence.        "volved  Cannot  be  drawn  unless  we  take  for  granted 
that  the  order  of  the  operations  performed  and  the  path 
by  which  the  transferences  are  effected,  are  indifferent, 
that  is  unless  we  have  previously  discerned  that  work 
is  determinative.     We  should  commit,  if  we  accepted 
this  inference,  the  same  error  that  Archimedes  com- 
mitted in  his  deduction  of  the  law  of  the  lever ;  as  has 
been  set  forth  at  length  in  a  preceding  section  and 
need  not  in  the  present  case  be  so  exhaustively  dis- 
cussed.    Nevertheless,   the   reasoning   we  have   pre- 
sented is  useful,  in  the  respect  that  it  brings  palpably 
home  to  the  mind  the  relationship  of  the  simple  and 
the  complicated  cases. 
Theuniver-        8.   The  universal  applicability  of  the  principle  of 
bUiry^ofThe  virtual  displacements  to  all  cases  of  equilibrium,  was 
Srstper-*     perceived  by  John  Bernoulli  ;  who  communicated  his 
John  Ber-    discovery  to  Varignon  in  a  letter  written  in  171 7.    We 
will  now  enunciate  the  principle  in  its  most  general 
form.    At  the  points  A,  Bf  C ,  .  .  (Fig.  42)  the  forces 
P,  P\  P'*  .  .  .  are  applied.     Impart  to  the  points  any 
infinitely  small  displacements  7^,  v\  v'* .  .  .  compatible 
with  the  character  of  the  connections  of  the  points  (so- 
called  virtual  displacements),  and  construct  the  pro- 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  ST  A  TICS.  57 

jections  /,  p\  p"  of  these  displacements  on  the  direc-  General 

.      ,         ,  _,_  .        .  .  ,       enunciation 

tions  of  the  forces.     These  projections  we  consider  of  the  pnn- 

positive  when  they  fall  in  ji  p         > 

the  direction  of  the  force,  $^ 

and  negative  when  they  fall 

in   the  opposite  direction. 

The    products    Fp,    P* p\ 

/•"/",  .  .  .  are  called  virtual 

moments,    and   in  the  two 

cases  just  mentioned  have  K6-4a- 

contrary  signs.    Now,  the  principle  asserts,  that  for  the 

case  of  equilibrium  Pp  +  /"/  +  P"  f  +  ...==  0,  or 

more  briefly  '^Pp  =  0. 

9.  Let  us  now  examine  a  few  points  more  in  detail.  Detailed 
Previous  to  Newton  a  force  was  almost  universally  tion  of  the 
conceived  simply  as  the  pull  or  the  pressure  of  a  heavy 
body.  The  mechanical  researches  of  this  period  dealt 
almost  exclusively  with  heavy  bodies.  When,  now, 
in  the  Newtonian  epoch,  the  generalisation  of  the  idea 
of  force  was  effected,  all  mechanical  principles  known 
to  be  applicable  to  heavy  bodies  could  be  transferred 
at  once  to  any  forces  whatsoever.  It  was  possible  to 
replace  every  force  by  the  pull  of  a  heavy  body  on  a 
string.  In  this  sense  we  may  also  apply  the  principle 
of  virtual  displacements,  at  first  discovered  only  for 
heavy  bodies,  to  any  forces  whatsoever. 

Virtual  displacements  are  displacements  consistent  Definition 
with  the  character  of  the  connections  of  a  system  and  diBpiace- 
with  one  another.  If,  for  example,  the  two  points  of 
a  system,  A  and  B^  at  which  forces  act,  are  connected 
(Fig.  43,  i)  by  a  rectangularly  bent  lever,  free  to  re- 
volve about  C,  then,  if  CB  =:i2CAy  all  virtual  dis- 
placements of  B  and  A  are  elements  of  the  arcs  of  cir- 
cles having  C  as  centre ;  the  displacements  of  B  are 


J 


I 


58  T//E  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

always  double  the  displacements  of  Ay  and  both  are  in 
every  case  at  right  angles  to  each  other.  If  the  points 
Ay  B  (Fig.  43,  2)  be  connected  by  a  thread  of  the  length 

/,  adjusted  to  slip  through 

stationary  rings  at  C  and  Z>, 

then  all  those  displacements 

^         2        ®-^   of  A  and  B  are  virtual  in 

Fig.  43.  which  the  points  referred  to 

move  upon  or  within  two  spherical  surfaces  described 

with  the  radii  r^  and  r^  about  C  and  D  as  centres, 

where  ''1  +  ''2  +  ^^  =  ^• 

The  reason        The  use  of  infinitely  small  displacements  instead  of 

of  inaniteiyfinile  displacements,  such  as  Galileo  assumed,  is  justi- 

piacements.  fied  by  the  following  consideration.     If  two  weights 

are  in  equilibrium  on  an  inclined  plane  (Fig.  44),  the 

equilibrium  will  not  be  disturbed  if  the  inclined  plane, 

at  points  at  which  it  is  not  in  immediate  contact  with 

the  bodies  considered,  passes  into 
a  surface  of  a  different  form.  The 
essential  condition  is,  therefore, 
the  momentary  possibility  of  dis- 
Fig.  44.  placement  in  the  momentary  con- 

figuration of  the  system.  To  judge  of  equilibrium  we 
must  assume  displacements  vanishingly  small  and  such 
only ;  as  otherwise  the  system  might  be  carried  over 
into  an  entirely  different  adjacent  configuration,  for 
which  perhaps  equilibrium  would  not  exist. 
A  Hmita-  That  the  displacements  themselves  are  not  decisive 

but  only  the  extent  to  which  they  occur  in  the  direc- 
tions of  the  forces,  that  is  only  their  projections  on  the 
lines  of  the  forces,  was,  in  the  case  of  the  inclined  plane, 
perceived  clearly  enough  by  Galileo  himself. 

With  respect  to  the  expression  of  the  principle,  it 
will  be  observed,  that  no  problem  whatever  is  .presented 


tion 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS. 


59 


if  all  the  material  points  of  the  system  on  which  forces  General  re- 
act, are  independent  of  each  other.  Each  point  thus 
conditioned  can  be  in  equilibrium  only  in  the  event 
that  it  is  not  movable  in  the  direction  in  which  the  force 
acts.  The  virtual  moment  of  each  such  point  vanishes 
separately.  If  some  of  the  points  be  independent  of 
each  other,  while  others  in  their  displacements  are  de- 
pendent on  each  other,  the  remark  just  made  holds 
good  for  the  former ;  and  for  the  latter  the  fundamental 
proposition  discovered  by  Galileo  holds,  that  the  sum 
of  their  virtual  moments  is  equal  to  zero.  Hence,  the 
sum-total  of  the  virtual  moments  of  all  jointly  is  equal 
to  zero. 

lo.  Let  us  now  endeavor  to  get  some  idea  of  the  Examples, 
significance  of  the  principle,  by  the  consideration  of  a 
few  simple  examples  that  cannot  be 
dealt  with  by  the  ordinary  method 
of  the  lever,  the  inclined  plane,  and 
the  like. 

The  differential  pulley  of  Wes- 
ton (Fig.  45)  consists  of  two  coax- 
ial rigidly  connected  cylinders  of 
slightly   different   radii  r^   and  r^ 
<r^.     A  cord  or  chain  is  passed 
round  the  cylinders  in  the  manner 
indicated  in  the  figure.     If  we  pull 
in  the  direction  of  the  arrow  with 
the  force  P,  and  rotation  takes  place 
through  the  angle  ^,  the  weight  Q  attached  below  will 
be  raised.     In  the  case  of  equilibrium  there  will  exist 
between  the  two  virtual  moments  involved  the  equa- 
tion 


The  differ- 
ential pal- 
ley  of  We» 
ton. 


Fig.  45. 


Q^'-^<p  =  ^r^<p,oxF 


''l—  ''2 


2r, 


6o 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 


A  suspend-  A  wheel  and  axle  of  weight  Q  (Fig.  46),  which  on 
and  aiie.  the  unroUing  of  a  cord  to  which  the  weight  P  is  at- 
tached rolls  itself  up  on  a  second  cord 
wound  round  the  axle  and  rises,  gives 
for  the  virtual  moments  in  the  case  of 
equilibrium  the  equation 

F{R^r)cp=Qrcp,  or  P=  ^-^. 

In  the  particular  case  R  —  r  =  0,  we 
must  also  put,  for  equilibrium,  Qr  =  0,  or, 
for  finite  values  of  r,  Q  =  0.  In  reality  the 
string  behaves  in  this  case  like  a  loop  in 
which  the  weight  Q  is  placed.  The  lat- 
ter can,  if  it  be  different  from  zero,  continue  to  roll  itself 
downwards  on  the  string  without  moving  the  weight  P, 
If,  however,  when  R^^r,  we  also  put  ^  =  0,  the  re- 
sult will  he  P=^,  an  indeterminate  value.  As  a  mat- 
ter of  fact,  every  weight  P  holds  the  apparatus  in  equi- 
librium, since  when  R  =  r  none  can  possibly  descend. 
A  double  A  double  cylinder  (Fig.  47)  of  the  radii  r,  R  lies  with 

a^horizon"  frictiou  On  a  horizontal  surface,  and  a  force  Q  is  brought 

to  bear  on  the  string  at- 
tached to  it.  Calling  the  re- 
sistance due  to  friction  P, 

_  equilibrium     exists     when 

^^^^^^^^  />=  {R-r/R)  Q,     If  P> 
FiK. 47.  {R^r/R)  Q,  the  cylinder, 

on  the  application  of  the  force,  will  roll  itself  up  on 
the  string. 

Roberval's  Balance  (Fig.  48)  consists  of  a  paral- 
lelogram with  variable  angles,  two  opposite  sides  of 
which,  the  upper  and  lower,  are  capable  of  rotation 
about  their  middle  points  A,  B.  To  the  two  remaining 
sides,  which  are  always  vertical,  horizontal  rods  are 


Roberval's 
balance. 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  ST  A  TICS. 


6x 


fastened.     If  from  these  rods  we  suspend  two  equal 

weights  Py  equilibrium  will  subsist  independently  of 

the  position  of  the  points 

of  suspension,  because  on 

displacement  the  descent 

of  the  one  weight  is  always 

equal  to  the  ascent  of  the 

other. 

At  three  fixed  points  A^ 
B,  C(Fig.  49)  let  pulleys 

be  placed,  over  which  three  strings  are  passed  loaded  three  knot 
with  equal  weights  and  knotted  dX  O,     In  what  posi-      •*^"*** 
tion  of  the  strings  will  equilibrium  exist?    We  will  call 
the  lengths  of  the  three  strings  AO  =  s^,  BO  =  s^, 


Fig.  48- 


Discuaaion 
of  the  case 
of  equilib- 
rium of 


Tl 


B 


9 


Fig.  49. 

CO  =  s^,  To  obtain  the  equation  of  equilibrium,  let 
us  displace  the  point  O  in  the  directions  s^  and  s^  the 
infinitely  small  distances  ds^  and  6s ^^  and  note  that  by 
so  doing  every  direction  of  displacement  in  the  plane 
ABC  (Fig.  50)  can  be  produced.  The  sum  of  the  vir- 
tual moments  is 


Fig.  50. 


2  —  B6s^  cos  a  +  Pds^  cos  (^  +  /^  I       q 


B6s 
+  P6s^  —  P6s^  cos/?  +  P6s^  cos  {a  -f  /3) 


or 


[1  —  cos  or  +  cos  (or  +  /^]  6s^  -f  [1  — cos/3 
+  cos  (or  +  /?)]  ^^3  =  0. 

But  since  each  of  the  displacements  6s ^,  6s ^  is  ar- 


6a 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 


bitrary,  and  each  independent  of  the  other,  and  may  by 
themselves  be  taken  =  0,  it  follows  that 


Therefore 


1  —  cos  a  -f  cos  (or  4"  /^  =  ^ 
1  _  cos/?  +  cos  («+/?)  =  0. 

cos  a  =  cos  fit 


Remarks  on 


and  each  of  the  two  equations  may  be  replaced  by 

1  —  cos  a  +  cos  2a  =  0; 

or  cos  a  =  \y 
wherefore  a  +  /?  =  120° 

Accordingly,  in  the  case  of  equilibrium,  each  of  the 
ingcase.  Strings  makes  with  the  others  angles  of  120°  ;  which  is, 
moreover,  directly  obvious,  since  three  equal  forces  can 
be  in  equilibrium  only  when  such  an  arrangement  ex- 
ists. This  once  known,  we  may  find  the  position  of 
the  point  O  with  respect  to  ABC  in  a  number  of  dif- 
ferent ways.  We  may  proceed  for  instance  as  follows. 
We  construct  on  AB,  BC,  CA,  severally,  as  sides, 
equilateral  triangles.  If  we  describe  circles  about  these 
triangles,  their  common  point  of  intersection  will  be 
the  point  O  sought ;  a  result  which  easily  follows  from 
the  well-known  relation  of  the  angles  at  the  centre  and 
circumference  of  circles. 
The  case  of  A  bar  OA  (Fig.  51)  is  revolvable  about  O  in  the 
voivabie     plane  of  the  paper  and  makes  with  a  fixed  straight  line 

OX  the  variable  angle 
a.  At  A  there  is  ap- 
plied a  force  B  which 


about  one 
of  its  ex- 
tremities. 


Fig.  51. 


makes  with  OX  the 
angle  y,  and  at  B,  on 
a     ring     displaceable 


along  the  length  of  the  bar,  a  force  Q,  making  with 
OX  the  angle  /3,     We  impart  to  the  bar  an  infinitely 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS.  63 

small  rotation,  in  consequence  of  which  B  and  A  move  The  case  of 

a  bar  r©- 

forward  the  distances  6s  and  6s,  at  right  angles  to  OA^  voivaWe 

_      about  one 

and  we  also  displace  the  ring  the  distance  6r  along  the  of  its  ez- 

,  ,  tremities. 

bar.  The  variable  distance  OB  we  will  call  r,  and  we 
will  let  OA  =:  a.  For  the  case  of  equilibrium  we  have 
then 

Q6r  cos  (/?—«)  +  Q6s  sin  (/?—«)  + 
Fds^  sin(a— ;^)  =  0. 

As  the  displacement  6r  has  no  effect  whatever  on 
the  other  displacements,  the  virtual  moment  therein 
involved  must,  by  itself,  =0,  and  since  dr  may  be  of 
any  magnitude  we  please,  the  coefficient  of  this  virtual 
moment  must  also  =  0.     We  have,  therefore, 

e  cos  (/?  —  a)  =  0, 

or  when  Q  is  different  from  zero, 

/?  — a=90°. 

Further,  in  view  of  the  fact  that  6s  ^^=1  {a/r)  6s,  we 
also  have 

rQ  sin  (J3  —  a)  -^  a  P  sin  (a  —  y)  =  0, 

or  since  sin  (J3 —  a)  =  i, 

rQ  +  aP  sin  {a  —  y)  =  0; 

wherewith  the  relation  of  the  two  forces  is  obtained. 

II.  An  advantage,   not  to  be  overlooked,   which  Every  ^en- 
every  general  principle,  and  therefore  also  the  prin-  cipio^in° 

VOlvCS  All 

ciple  of  virtual  displacements,  fur-  1 1    |  ^  economy  of 

nishes,  consists  in  the  fact  that  it  —^l     *  °"*  • 


saves  us  to  a  great  extent  the  ne-        c 
cessity  of  considering  every  new  par-    ^  1 
ticular  case  presented.  In  the  posses- 
sion of  this  principle  we  need  not,  for  Fig.  52. 
example,  trouble  ourselves  about  the  details  of  a  ma- 
chme.     If  a  new  machine  say  were  so  enclosed  in  a 


64  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

box  (Fig.  52),  that  only  two  levers  projected  as  points 
of  application  for  the  force  P  and  the  weight  P\  and 
we  should  find  the  simultaneous  displacements  of  these 
levers  to  be  h  and  h\  we  should  know  immediately  that 
in  the  case  of  equilibrium  Fh  =  P'  h\  whatever  the 
construction  of  the  machine  might  be.  Every  principle 
of  this  character  possesses  therefore  a  distinct  econom- 
ical value. 
Farther  ro-  12.  We  return  to  the  general  expression  of  the  prin- 
the  general  ciple  of  virtual  displacements,  in  order  to  add  a  few 

expression  *■ 

of  the  prin-  further  remarks.   If 

at  the  pomts  A,  B, 
C .  .  .  ,  the  forces 

and  Py  p\  p'* .... 

are  the  projections 
^*8-  53.  of    infinitely   small 

mutually  compatible  displacements,  we  shall  have  for 
the  case  of  equilibrium 

Pp  +  P'p'  +  P'p''  +  .  .  .  =  0. 

If  we  replace  the  forces  by  strings  which  pass  over 
pulleys  in  the  directions  of  the  forces  and  attach  thereto 
the  appropriate  weights,    this  expression   simply  as- 
serts that  the  centre  of  gravity  of  the  system  pf  weights 
as  a  whole  cannot  descend.   If,  however,  in  certain  dis- 
placements it  were  possible  for  the  centre  of  gravity 
to  rise,  the  system  would  still  be  in  equilibrium,  as  the 
heavy  bodies  would  not,  of  themselves,  enter  on  any 
Modifies-    such  motion.     In  this  case  the  sum  above  given  would 
previous     be  negative,  or  less  than  zero.  The  general  expression 
condition,    of  the  condition  of  equilibrium  is,  therefore, 

When  for  every  virtual  displacement  there  exists 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  ST  A  TICS.  65 

another  rquai  and  opposite  to  it,  as  is  the  case  for  ex- 
ample in  the  simple  machines,  we  may  restrict  ourselves 
to  the  upper  sign,  to  the  equation.  For  if  it  were  pos- 
sible for  the  centre  of  gravity  to  ascend  in  certain 
displacements,  it  would  also  have  to  be  possible,  in 
consequence  of  the  assumed  reversibility  of  all  the  vir- 
tual displacements,  for  it  to  descend.  •  Consequently, 
in  the  present  case,  a  possible  rise  of  the  centre  of 
gravity  is  incompatible  with  equilibrium. 

The  question  assumes  a  different  aspect,  however,  The  condi- 

,  ,  -.         ,  ,,  '%   ^  rry  tlOD  18,  that 

when  the  displacements  are  not  all  reversible.     Two  the  sum  of 
bodies  connected  together  by  strings  can  approach  moments 
each  other  but  cannot  recede  from  each  other  beyond  equal  to  or 
the  length  of  the  strings.     A  body  is  able  to  slide  or  zero, 
roll  on  the  surface  of  another  body ;  it  can  move  away 
from  the  surface  of  the  second  body,  but  it  cannot 
penetrate  it.     In  these  cases,  therefore,  there  are  dis- 
placements that  cannot  be  reversed.     Consequently, 
for  certain  displacements  a  rise  of  the  centre  of  gravity 
may  take  place,  while  the  contrary  displacements,  to 
which  the  descent  of  the  centre  of  gravity  corresponds, 
are  impossible.     We  must  therefore  hold  fast  to  the 
more  general  condition  of  equilibrium,  and  say,  the  sum 
of  the  virtual  moments  is  equal  to  or  less  than  zero. 

13.  Lagrange  in  his  Analytical  Mechanics  attempted  The  La- 

Kransiao 

a  deduction  of  the  principle  of  virtual  displacements,  deduction 

,.,  ...  .,  A'l  ^      -n   of  theprin- 

which  we  will  now  consider.  At  the  points  A,  By  cipic. 
C .  .  .  .  (Fig.  54)  the  forces  F,  P\  P'* .  .  .  .  act.  We 
imagine  rings  placed  at  the  points  in  question,  and 
other  rings  A\  B^^C* .  .  .  .  fastened  to  points  lying  in 
the  directions  of  the  forces.  We  seek  some  common 
measure  Qji  of  the  forces  /*,  P\  P** ....  that  enables 
us  to  put : 


66 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 


Effected  by 
means  of  a 
Bet  of  pul- 
leys and  a 
single 
weight 


2«".f  =  /", 

where  «,  «',  «"....  are  whole  numbers.  Further,  we 
make  fast  to  the  ring  A'  a  string,  carry  this  string  back 
2lvA  forth  n  times  between  A*  and  A^  then  through  B^^ 


«'  times  back  and  forth  between  B^  and  B,  then  through 
C\  «"  times  back  and  forth  between  C  and  C,  and, 
finally,  let  it  drop  at  C\  attaching  to  it  there  the  weight 
QJT,,  *  As  the  string  has,  now,  in  all  its  parts  the  ten- 
sion ^/2,  we  replace  by  these  ideal  pulleys  all  the 
forces  present  in  the  system  by  the  single  force  QJT,. 
If  then  the  virtual  (possible)  displacements  in  any  given 
configuration  of  the  system  are  such  that,  these  dis- 
placements occurring,  a  descent  of  the  weight  Qfi.  can 
take  place,  the  weight  will  actually  descend  and  pro- 
duce those  displacements,  and  equilibrium  therefore 
will  not  obtain.  But  on  the  other  hand,  no  motion 
will  ensue,  if  the  displacements  leave  the  weight  Q/i 
in  its  original  position,  or  raise  it.  The  expression  of 
this  condition,  reckoning  the  projections  of  the  virtual 
displacements  in  the  directions  of  the  forces  positive, 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS,  67 

and  having  regard  for  the  number  of  the  turns  of  the 
string  in  each  single  pulley,  is 

2np  +  2«>'  +  2«"/'  +  :  .  .  ':^  0. 

Equivalent  to  this  condition,  however,  is  the  ex- 
pression 

2«  9.p  +  2«'  |-/  +  2«"  -|/'  +  .  .  .  <  0, 
or 

14.  The  deduction  of  Lagrange,  if  stripped  of  the  The  con- 
rather  odd  fiction  of  the  pulleys,  really  possesses  con-  tures  oj  La- 
vincing  features,  due  to  the  fact  that  the  action  of  a  deduction, 
single  weight  is  much  more  immediate  to  our  expe- 
rience and  is  more  easily  followed  than  the  action  of 
several  weights.  Yet  it  is  not  proved  by  the  Lagrangian 
deduction  that  work  is  the  factor  determinative  of  the 
disturbance  of  equilibrium,  but  is,  by  the  employment 
of  the  pulleys,  rather  assumed  by  it.     As  a  matter  of 
fact  every  pulley  involves  the  fact  enunciated  and  rec- 
ognised by  the  principle  of  virtual  displacements.  The 
replacement  of  all  the  forces  by  a  single  weight  that 
does  the  same  work,  presupposes  a  knowledge  of  the 
import  of  work,  and  can  be  proceeded  with  on  this  as- 
sumption alone.     The  fact  that  some  certain  cases  are  it  is  not. 
more  familiar  to  us  and  more  immediate  to  our  expe-  proof, 
rience  has  as  a  necessary  result  that  we  accept  them 
without  analysis  and  make  them  the  foundation  of  our 
deductions  without  clearly  instructing  ourselves  as  to 
their  real  character. 

It  often  happens  in  the  course  of  the  development 
of  science  that  a  new  principle  perceived  by  some  in- 
quirer in  connection  with  a  fact,  is  not  immediately 
recognised  and  rendered  familiar  in  its  entire  generality. 


68  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

Theezpe-   Then,   every  expedient  calculated  to  promote  these 
ployed  to     ends,  is,  as  is  proper  and  natural,  called  into  service. 

support  all     .  ,,  -    ,  .  ,  .    ,       ,  ...  -  ,  , 

newprin-  All  manner  of  facts,  in  which  the  principle,  although 
contained  in  them,  has  not  yet  been  recognised  by  in- 
quirers, but  which  from  other  points  of  view  are  more 
familiar,  are  called  in  to  furnish  a  support  for  the  new 
conception.  It  does  not,  however,  beseem  mature 
science  to  allow  itself  to  be  deceived  by  procedures  of 
this  sort.  If,  throughout  all  facts,  we  clearly  see  and  dis- 
cern a  principle  which,  though  not  admitting  of  proof, 
can  yet  be  known  to  prevail^  we  have  advanced  much 
farther  in  the  consistent  conception  of  nature  than  if 
we  suffered  ourselves  to  be  overawed  by  a  specious 

Value  of  the  demonstration.    If  we  have  reached  this  point  of  view, 

Lagraogian 

proof.  we  shall,  it  is  true,  regard  the-Lagrangian  deduction 
with  quite  different  eyes  ;  yet  it  will  engage  neverthe- 
less our  attention  and  interest,  and  excite  our  satis- 
faction from  the  fact  that  it  makes  palpable  the  simi- 
larity of  the  simple  and  complicated  cases. 

15.  Maupertuis  discovered  an  interesting  proposi- 
tion relating  to  equilibrium,  which  he  communicated 
to  the  Paris  Academy  in  1740  under  the  name  of  the 
"Loi  de  repos."  This  principle  was  more  fully  dis- 
cussed by  EuLER  in  1751  in  the  Proceedings  of  the 
Berlin  Academy.  If  we  cause  infinitely  small  displace- 
Th^Loide  ments  in  any  system,  we  produce  a  sum  of  virtual  mo- 
'''^*'  ments  Fp  +  F'p'  +  P"/'  +-...,  which  only  reduces 
to  zero  in  the  case  of  equilibrium.  This  sum  is  the 
work  corresponding  to  the  displacements,  or  since  for 
infinitely  small  displacements  it  is  itself  infinitely  small, 
the  corresponding  element  of  work.  If  the  displace- 
ments are  continuously  increased  till  a  finite  displace- 
ment is  produced,  the  elements  of  the  work  will,  by 
summation,  produce  a  finite  amount  of  work.   So,  if  we 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS,  69 

Start  from  any  given  initial  configuration  of  the  system  statement- 

1  ^  '  r         ^  r  ,-  .       of  the  priu- 

and  pass  to  any  given  final  configuration,  a  certain  cipie. 
amount  of  work  will  have  to  be  done.  Now  Maupertuis 
observed  that  the  work  done  when  a  final  configura- 
tion is  reached  which  is  a  configuration  of  equilibrium, 
is  generally  a  maximum  or  a  minimum  ;  that  is,  if  we 
carry  the  system  through  the  configuration  of  equilib- 
rium the  work  done  is  previously  and  subsequently 
less  or  previously  and  subsequently  greater  than  at  the 
configuration  of  equilibrium  itself.  For  the  configura- 
tion of  equilibrium 

pp  +  rp'  +  /"/•  + . . .  =  0, 

that  is,  the  element  of  the  work  or  the  differential  (more 
correctly  the  variation)  of  the  work  is  equal  to  zero. 
If  the  differential  of  a  function  can  be  put  equal  to 
zero,  the  function  has  generally  a  maximum  or  mini- 
mum value. 

16.  We  can  produce  a  very  clear  representation  to  Graphical 
the  eye  of  the  import  of  Maupertuis's  principle.  oftheim- 

We  imagine  the  forces  of  a  system  replaced  byprindpie.* 
Lagrange's  pulleys  with  the  weight  Q/2,  We  suppose 
that  each  point  of  the  system  is  restricted  to  movement 
on  a  certain  curve  and  that  the  motion  is  such  that 
when  one  point  occupies  a  definite  position  on  its  curve 
all  the  other  points  assume  uniquely  determined  po- 
sitions on  their  respective  curves.  The  simple  ma- 
chines are  as  a  rule  systems  of  this  kind.  Now,  while 
imparting  displacements  to  the  system,  we  may  carry 
a  vertical  sheet  of  white  paper  horizontally  over  the 
weight  ^/2,  while  this  is  ascending  and  descending 
on  a  vertical  line,  so  that  a  pencil  which  it  carries  shall 
describe  a  curve  upon  the  paper  (Fig.  55).  When  the 
pencil  stands  at  the  points  a,  r,  doi  the  curve,  there  are, 


70  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

L-  we  see,  adjacent  positions  in  the  system  of  points  at 
which  the  weight  Ql'i  will  stand  higher  or  lower  than  in 
the  configuration  given.  The  weight  will  then,  if  the 
system  be  left  to  itself,  pass  into  this  lower  position  and 


displace  the  system  with  it  Accordingly,  under  condi- 
tions of  this  kind,  equilibrium  does  not  subsist.  If 
the  pencil  stands  at  e,  then  there  exist  only  adjacent 
configurations  for  which  the  weight  Q|^  stands  higher. 
But  of  itself  the  system  will  not  pass  into  the  last- 
named  configurations.  On  the  contrary,  every  dis- 
placement in  such  a  direction,  will,  by  virtue  of  the 
tendency  of  the  weight  to  move  downwards,  be  re- 
versed.    Stable  equilibrium,    Iherejore,   is  Ihc  condition 

■AKBtrtA- that  corresponds  to  the  lowest  position  of  the  weight  or  to 
a  maximum  of  work  done  in  the  system.  If  the  pencil 
stands  at  b,  we  see  that  every  appreciable  displace- 
ment brings  the  weight  QI2  lower,  and  that  the  weight 
therefore  will  continue  the  displacement  begun.  But, 
assuming  infinitely  small  displacements,  the  pyencil 
moves  in  the  horizontal  tangent  at  b,  in  which  event 
the  weight  cannot  descend.     Therefore,  unstable  equi- 

labis  tibrium  is  the  stale  that  corresponds  to  the  highest  position 
of  the  weight  Qji,  or  to  a  minimum  of  work  done  in  the 
system.      It  will    be  -noted,   however,   that  conversely 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS.  71 

every  case  of  equilibrium  is  not  the  correspondent  of 
a  maximum  or  a  minimum  of  work  performed.  If  the 
pencil  is  at/,  at  a  point  of  horizontal  contrary  flexure, 
the  weight  in  the  case  of  infinitely  small  displace- 
ments neither  rises  nor  falls.  Equilibrium  exists,  al- 
though the  work  done  is  neither  a  maximum  nor  a 
minimum.  The  equilibrium  of  this  case  is  the  so- 
called  m/x^// equilibrium  "^  :  for  some  disturbances  it  is  Mixed  equi- 
stable,  for  others  unstable.  Nothing  prevents  us  from 
regarding  mixed  equilibrium  as  belonging  to  the  un- 
stable class.  When  the  pencil  stands  at  g,  where  the 
curve  runs  along  horizontally  a  finite  distance,  equi- 
librium likewise  exists.  Any  small  displacement,  in 
the  configuration  in  question,  is  neither  continued  nor 
reversed.  This  kind  of  equilibrium,  to  which  likewise 
neither  a  maximum  nor  a  minimum  corresponds,  is 
termed  [neutral  or]  indifferent.  If  the  curve  described  Nentrai 
by  Qji  has  a  cusp  pointing  upwards,  this  indicates  a*^""***''"" 
minimum  of  work  done  but  no  equilibrium  (not  even 
unstable  equilibrium).  To  a  cusp  pointing  downwards 
a  maximum  and  stable  equilibrium  correspond.  In  the 
last  named  case  of  equilibrium  the  sum  of  the  virtual, 
moments  is  not  equal  to  zero,  but  is  negative. 

17.  In  the  reasoning  just  presented,  we  have  as-xhcpreced- 
sumed  that  the  motion  of  a  point  of  a  system  on  one  tufn applied 
curve  determines  the  motion  of  all  the  other  points  oitoSlneSit' 
the  system  on  their  respective  curves.  The  movability  *^"'*^"®"* 
of  the  system  becomes  multiplex,  however,  when  each 
point  is  displaceable  on  a  surface,  in  a  manner  such 
that  the  position  of  one  point  on  its  surface  determines 

*This  term  is  not  used  in  English,  because  our  writers  bold  tbat  no 
eqailibrinm  is  conceivable  wbich  is  not  stable  or  neutral  for  some  possible 
displacements.  Hence  what  is  called  mixtd  equilibrium  in  the  text  is  called 
onatable  equilibrium  by  EuKlish  writers,  who  deny  the  existence  of  equilibrium 
mutable  in  every  respect.— 7V0»#. 


72  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

uniquely  the  position  of  all  the  other  points  on  their 
surfaces.  In  this  case,  we  are  not  permitted  to  consider 
the  curve  described  by  ^/2,  but  are  obliged  to  picture 
to  ourselves  a  surface  described  by  Q/2,  If,  to  go  a 
step  further,  each  point  is  movable  throughout  a  space, 
we  can  no  longer  represent  to  ourselves  in  a  purely  geo- 
metrical manner  the  circumstances  of  the  motion,  by 
means  of  the  locus  of  Q/2.  In  a  correspondingly  higher 
degree  is  this  the  case  when  the  position  of  one  of  the 
points  of  the  system  does  not  determine  conjointly  all 
the  other  positions,  but  the  character  of  the  system's 
motion  is  more  multiplex  still.  In  all  these  cases,  how- 
ever, the  curve  described  by  Q/2  (Fig.  55)  can  serve 
us  as  a  symbol  of  the  phenomena  to  be  considered.  In 
these  cases  also  we  rediscover  the  Maupertuisian  pro- 
positions. 
Further  ex-  We  have  also  supposed,  in  our  considerations  up  to 
the  same  this  point,  that  constant  forces,  forces  independent  of 
the  position  of  the  points  of  the  system,  are  the  forces 
that  act  in  the  system.  If  we  assume  that  the  forces 
do  depend  on  the  position  of  the  points  of  the  system 
(but  not  on  the  time),  we  are  no  longer  able  to  conduct 

our  operations  with  simple   pulleys,   but 

must  devise  apparatus  the  force  active  in 

which,  still  exerted  by  Q/2,  varies  with  the 

displacement :  the  ideas  we  have  reached, 

however,  still  obtain.     The  depth  of  the 

descent  of  the  weight  Q/2  is  in  every  case 

the  measure  of  the  work  performed,  which 

is  always  the  same  in  the  same  configura- 

F»K-  56.        tion  of  the  system  and  is  independent  of 

the  path  of  transference.     A  contrivance  which  would 

develop  by  means  of  a  constant  weight  a  force  varying 

with  the  displacement,  would  be,  for  example,  a  wheel 


(h 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS.  73 

and  axle  (Fig.  56)  with  a  non-circular  wheel.  It  would 
not  repay  the  trouble,  however,  to  enter  into  the  de- 
tails of  the  reasoning  indicated  in  this  case,  since  we 
perceive  at  a  glance  its  feasibility. 

18.  If  we  know  the  relation  that  subsists  between  The  prin- 

ciple of 
the  work  done  and  the  so-called  vis  viva  of  a  sys- courtivron. 

tern,    a  relation  established    in  dynamics,   we  arrive 

easily  at  the  principle  communicated  by  Courtivron  in 

1 749  to  the   Paris  Academy,  which  is  this :   For  the 

stable 
configuration  of  ,,     equilibrium,  at  which  the 

work  done  is  a  ,  the  vis  viva  of  the  system, 

mmimum  •' 

m 

in   motion,  is  also  a       .   •  in  its  transit  through 

'  mmimum  ^  , 

these  configurations. 

19.  A  heavy,  homogeneous  triaxial  ellipsoid  resting  illustration 
on  a  horizontal  plane  is  admirably  adapted  to  illustrate  ous  kinds  of 

...  .       equilibrium 

the  various  classes  of  equilibrium.  When  the  ellip- 
soid rests  on  the  extremity  of  its  smallest  axis,  it  is  in 
stable  equilibrium,  for  any  displacement  it  may  suffer 
elevates  its  centre  of  gravity.  If  it  rest  on  its  longest 
axis,  it  is  in  unstable  equilib- 
rium. If  the  ellipsoid  stand  on 
its  mean  axis,  its  equilibrium  is 
mixed.  A  homogeneous  sphere 
or  a  homogeneous  right  cylin- 
der on  a  horizontal  plane  illus-  Fi«-  57. 
trates  the  case  of  indifferent  equilibrium.  In  Fig.  57 
we  have  represented  the  paths  of  the  centre  of  gravity 
of  a  cube  rolling  on  a  horizontal  plane  about  one  of  its 
edges.  The  position  a  of  the  centre  of  gravity  is  the 
position  of  stable  equilibrium,  the  position  ^,  the  posi- 
tion of  unstable  equilibrium. 


74  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

The  eaten-         20.  We  will  now  consider  an  example  which  at 

81  ry. 

first  sight  appears  very  complicated  but  is  elucidated 
at  once  by  the  principle  of  virtual  displacements.  John 
and  James  Bernoulli,  on  the  occasion  of  a  conversa- 
tion on  mathematical  topics  during  a  walk  in  Basel, 
lighted  on  the  question  of  what  form  a  chain  would 
take  that  was  freely  suspended  and  fastened  at  both 
ends.  They  soon  and  easily  agreed  in  the  view  that 
the  chain  would  assume  that  form  of  equilibrium  at 
which  its  centre  of  gravity  lay  in  the  lowest  possible 
position.  As  a  matter  of  fact  we  really  do  perceive 
that  equilibrium  subsists  when  all  the  links  of  the  chain 
have  sunk  as  low  as  possible,  when  none  can  sink  lower 
without  raising  in  consequence  of  the  connections  of 
the  system  an  equivalent  mass  equally  high  or  higher. 
When  the  centre  of  gravity  has  sunk  as  low  as  it  pos- 
sibly can  sink,  when  all  has  happened  that  can  happen, 
stable  equilibrium  exists.  The  physical  part  of  the 
problem  is  disposed  of  by  this  consideration.  The  de- 
termination of  the  curve  that  has  the  lowest  centre  of 
gravity  for  a  given  length  between  the  two  points  A^ 
Bt  is  simply  a  ma//ifma/ica/  problem.  (See  Fig.  58.) 
Theprinci-  21.  Collecting  all  that  has  been  presented,  we  see, 
plytherec-  that  there  is  contained  in  the  principle  of  virtual  dis- 

ognition  of      ,  •         %        ^  •   •       •     r         r  1 

a  fact.  placements  simply  the  recognition  of  a  fact  that  was 
instinctively  familiar  to  us  long  previousl)%  only  that 
we  had  not  apprehended  it  so  precisely  and  clearly. 
This  fact  consists  in  the  circumstance  that  heavy 
bodies,  of  themselves,  move  only  downwards.  If  sev- 
eral such  bodies  be  joined  together  so  that  they  can 
suffer  no  displacement  independently  of  each  other, 
they  will  then  move  only  in  the  event  that  some  heavy 
mass  is  on  the  whole  able  to  descend,  or  as  the  prin- 
ciple, with  a  more  perfect  adaptation  of  our  ideas  to 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS, 


76  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

What  this  the  f acts,  more  exactly  expresses  it,  only  in  the  event 
that  work  can  be  performed.  If,  extending  the  notion 
of  force,  we  transfer  the  principle  to  forces  other  than 
those  due  to  gravity,  the  recognition  is  again  con- 
tained therein  of  the  fact  that  the  natural  occurrences 
in  question  take  place,  of  themselves,  only  in  a  definite 
sense  and  not  in  the  opposite  sense.  Just  as  heavy 
bodies  descend  downwards,  so  differences  of  tempera- 
ture and  electrical  potential  cannot  increase  of  their 
own  accord  but  only  diminish,  and  so  on.  If  occur- 
rences of  this  kind  be  so  connected  that  they  can  take 
place  only  in  the  contrary  sense,  the  principle  then  es- 
tablishes, more  precisely  than  our  instinctive  appre- 
hension could  do  this,  the  factor  work  as  determinative 
and  decisive  of  the  direction  of  the  occurrences.  The 
equilibrium  equation  of  the  principle  may  be  reduced 
in  every  case  to  the  trivial  statement,  that  when  noth- 
ing can  happen  nothing  does  happen, 
Theprin-  22.  It  is  important  to' obtain  clearly  the  perception, 

Hgh?o?    *that  we  have  to  deal,   in  the  case  of  all  principles, 
view.         merely  with  the  ascertainment  and  establishment  of  a 
fact.     If  we  neglect  this,  we  shall  always  be  sensible 
of  some  deficiency  and  will  seek  a  verification  of  the 
principle,  that  is  not  to  be  found.    Jacobi  states  in  his 
Lectures  on  Dynamics  that  Gauss  once  remarked  that 
Lagrange's  equations  of  motion  had  not  been  proved, 
but  only  historically  enunciated.    And  this  view  really 
seems  to  us  to  be  the  correct  one  in  regard  to  the  prin- 
ciple of  virtual  displacements. 
The  differ-         The  task  of  the  early  inquirers,  who  lay  the  foun- 

ent  tasks  of,.  .  ,  .r-  •! 

early  and  of  dations  of  any  department  of  mvestigation,  is  entirely 

inqufrers  in  different  from  that  of  those  who  follow.    It  is  the  busi- 

mSn,***      ness  of  the  former  to  seek  out  and  to  establish  the 

facts  of  most  cardinal  importance  only;  and,  as  history 


.7 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STA  TICS,  77 

teaches,  more  brains  are  required  for  this  than  is  gen- 
erally supposed.  When  the  most  important  facts  are 
once  furnished,  we  are  then  placed  in  a  position  to 
work  them  out  deductively  and  logically  by  the  meth- 
ods of  mathematical  physics;  we  can  then  organise  the 
department  of  inquiry  in  question,  and  show  that  in  the 
acceptance  of  some  one  fact  a  whole  series  of  others  is 
included  which  were  not  to  be  immediately  discerned 
in  the  first.  The  one  task  is  as  important  as  the  other. 
We  should  not  however  confound  the  one  with  the 
other.  We  cannot  prove  by  mathematics  that  nature 
must  be  exactly  what  it  is.  But  we  can  prove,  that 
one  set  of  observed  properties  determines  conjointly 
another  set  which  often  are  not  directly  manifest. 

Let  it  be  remarked  in  conclusion,  that  the  princi-  Every  yen- 
pie  of  virtual  displacements,  like  every  general  prin-  pie  brings 

witli  it  Qis- 

ciple,  brings  with  it,  by  the  insight  which  it  furnishes,  iiiuaion- 
disillusiontnent  as  well  as  elucidation.  It  brings  with  well  as  eia< 
it  disillusionment  to  the  extent  that  we  recognise  in  it 
facts  which  were  long  before  known  and  even  instinct- 
ively perceived,  our  present  recognition  being  simply 
more  distinct  and  more  definite ;  and  elucidation,  in 
that  it  enables  us  to  see  everywhere  throughout  the 
most  complicated  relations  the  same  simple  facts. 

v. 

RETROSPECT   OF   THE    DEVELOPMENT    OF    STATICS. 

I.   Having  passed  successively  in  review  the  prin- Review  of 
ciples  of  statics,  we  are  now  in  a  position  to  take  a  whouf.  **  * 
brief  supplementary  survey  of  the  development  of  the 
principles  of  the  science  as  a  whole.  This  development, 
falling  as  it  does  in  the  earliest  period  of  mechanics, 
— the  period  which  begins  in  Grecian  antiquity  and 


78  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

reaches  its  close  at  the  time  when  Galileo  and  his 
younger  contemporaries  were  inaugurating  modern  me- 
chanics,— illustrates  in  an  excellent  manner  the  pro- 
cess of  the  formation  of  science  generally.  All  con- 
ceptions, all  methods  are  here  found  in  their  simplest 
form,  and  as  it  were  in  their  infancy.  These  beginnings 
The  origin  point  unmistakably  to  their  origin  in  the  experiences  of 

of  science. 

the  manual  arts.  To  the  necessity  of  putting  these  ex- 
periences into  communicable  form  and  of  disseminating 
them  beyond  the  confines  of  class  and  craft,  science 
owes  its  origin.  The  collector  of  experiences  of  this 
kind,  who  seeks  to  preserve  them  in  written  form,  finds 
before  him  many  different,  or  at  least  supposably  differ- 
ent, experiences.  His  position  is  one  that  enables  him 
to  review  these  experiences  more  frequently,  more  vari- 
ously, and  more  impartially  than  the  individual  work- 
in  gman,  who  is  always  limited  to  a  narrow  province. 
The  facts  and  their  dependent  rules  are  brought  into 
closer  temporal  and  spatial  proximity  in  his  mind  and 
writings,  and  thus  acquire  the  opportunity  of  revealing 
The  econo-  their  relationship,  their  connection,  and  their  gradual 
munication.  transition  the  one  into  the  other.  The  desire  to  sim- 
plify and  abridge  the  labor  of  communication  supplies 
a  further  impulse  in  the  same  direction.  Thus,  from 
economical  reasons,  in  such  circumstances,  great  num- 
bers of  facts  and  the  rules  that  spring  from  them  are 
condensed  into  a  system  and  comprehended  in  a  single 
expression. 
The  gene-  2.  A  collcctor  of  this  character  has,  moreover,  op- 

ral  charttC' 

ter  of  prin-  portuuity  to  take  note  of  some  new  aspect  of  the  facts 
before  him — of  some  aspect  which  former  observers 
had  not  considered.  A  rule,  reached  by  the  observation 
of  facts,  cannot  possibly  embrace  the  entire  fact,  in  all 
its  infinite  wealth,  in  all  its  inexhaustible  manifoldness ; 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS.  79 

on  the  contrary,  it  can  furnish  only  a  rough  outline  of 
the  fact,  one-sidedly  emphasising  the  feature  that  is  of 
importance  for  the  given  technical  (or  scientific)  aim  in 
view.  What  aspects  of  a  fact  are  taken  notice  of,  will 
consequently  depend  upon  circumstances,  or  even  on  Their  form 

,  .  .in  many  as- 

the  caprice  of  the  observer.  Hence  there  is  always  op-  pects,  «cci- 
portunity  for  the  discovery  of  new  aspects  of  the  fact, 
which  will  lead  to  the  establishment  of  new  rules  of 
equal  validity  with,  or  superior  to,  the  old.  So,  for  in- 
stance, the  weights  and  the  lengths  of  the  lever-arms 
were  regarded  at  first,  by  Archimedes,  as  the  conditions 
that  determined  equilibrium.  Afterwards,  by  Da  Vinci 
and  Ubaldi  the  weights  and  the  perpendicular  distances 
from  the  axis  of  the  lines  of  force  were  recognised  as 
the  determinative  conditions.  Still  later,  by  Galileo, 
the  weights  and  the  amounts  of  their  displacements, 
and  finally  by  Varignon  the  weights  and  the  directions 
of  the  pulls  with  respect  to  the  axis  were  taken  as  the 
elements  of  equilibrium,  and  the  enunciation  of  the 
rules  modified  accordingly. 

3.  Whoever  makes  a  new  observation  of  this  kind,  our  Uabii- 
and  establishes  such  a  new  rule,  knows,  of  course,  our  in  the  men- 
liability  to  error  in  attempting  mentally  to  represent  atrucdon  of 
the  fact,  whether  by  concrete  images  or  in  abstract  con- 
ceptions, which  we  must  do  in  order  to  have  the  mental 
model  we  have  constructed  always  at  hand  as  a  substi- 
tute for  the  fact  when  the  latter  is  partly  or  wholly  in- 
accessible.    The  circumstances,  indeed,  to  which  we 
have  to  attend,  are  accompanied  by  so  many  other, 
collateral  circumstances,  that  it  is  frequently  difficult 
to  single  out  and  consider  those  that  are  essential  to  the 
purpose  in  view.     Just  think  how  the  facts  of  friction, 
the  rigidity  of  ropes  and  cords,  and  like  conditions  in 
machines,  obscure  and  obliterate  the  pure  outlines  of 


8o  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

Thisiiabii-  the  main  facts.   No  wonder,  therefore,  that  the  discov- 

ity  impels 

us  to  seek    erer  or  verifier  of  a  new  rule,  urged  by  mistrust  of  him- 
of  all  new    Self,  seeks  after  a  proof  of  the  rule  whose  validity  he 

rules.  .  , 

believes  he  has  discerned.  The  discoverer  or  verifier 
does  not  at  the  outset  fully  trust  in  the  rule  ;  or,  it  may 
be,  he  is  confident  only  of  a  part  of  it.  So,  Archimedes, 
for  example,  doubted  whether  the  effect  of  the  action 
of  weights  on  a  lever  was  proportional  to  the  lengths  of 
the  lever-arms,  but  he  accepted  without  hesitation  the 
fact  of  their  influence  in  some  way.  Daniel  Bernoulli 
does  not  question  the  influence  of  the  direction  of  a 
force  generally,  but  only  the  form  of  its  influence.  As 
a  matter  of  fact,  it  is  far  easier  to  observe  that  a  circum- 
stance has  influence  in  a  given  case,  than  to  determine 
what  influence  it  has.  In  the  latter -inquiry  we  are  in 
much  greater  degree  liable  to  error.  The  attitude  of  the 
investigators  is  therefore  perfectly  natural  and  defens- 
ible. 
The  natural  The  proof  of  the  correctness  of  a  new  rule  can  be 
proof.  attained  by  the  repeated  application  of  it,  the  frequent 
comparison  of  it  with  experience,  the  putting  of  it  to 
the  test  under  the  most  diverse  circumstances.  This 
process  would,  in  the  natural  course  of  events,  get  car- 
ried out  in  time.  The  discoverer,  however,  hastens  to 
reach  his  goal  more  quickly.  He  compares  the  results 
that  flow  from  his  rule  with  all  the  experiences  with 
which  he  is  familiar,  with  all  older  rules,  repeatedly 
tested  in  times  gone  by,  and  watches  to  see  if  he  do 
not  light  on  contradictions.  In  this  procedure,  the 
greatest  credit  is,  as  it  should  be,  conceded  to  the  oldest 
and  most  familiar  experiences,  the  most  thoroughly 
tested  rules.  Our  instinctive  experiences,  those  gen- 
eralisations that  are  made  involuntarily,  by  the  irresist- 
ible force  of  tb^  iunumerable  facts  that  press  in  upon 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS.  8i 

US,  enjoy  a  peculiar  authority;  and  this  is  perfectly 
warranted  by  the  consideration  that  it  is  precisely  the 
elimination  of  subjective  caprice  and  of  individual  er- 
ror that  is  the  object  aimed  at. 

In  this  manner  Archimedes  proves  his  law  of  the  illustration 
lever,  Stevinus  his  law  of  inclined  pressure,  Daniel  ceding  re- 
Bernoulli  the  parallelogram  of  forces,  Lagrange  the 
principle  of  virtual  displacements.  Galileo  alone  is 
perfectly  aware,  with  respect  to  the  last- mentioned 
principle,  that  his  new  observation  and  perception  are 
of  equal  rank  with  every  former  one — that  it  is  derived 
from  the  same  source  of  experience.  He  attempts  no 
demonstration.  Archimedes,  in  his  proof  of  the  prin- 
ciple of  the  lever,  uses  facts  concerning  the  centre  of 
gravity,  which  he  had  probably  proved  by  means  of  the 
very  principle  now  in  question ;  yet  we  may  suppose 
that  these  facts  were  otherwise  so  familiar,  as  to  be  un- 
questioned,— so  familiar  indeed,  that  it  may  be  doubted 
whether  he  remarked  that  he  had  employed  them  in 
demonstrating  the  principle  of  the  lever.  The  instinc- 
tive elements  embraced  in  the  views  of  Archimedes  and 
Stevinus  have  been  discussed  at  length  in  the  proper 
place. 

4.   It  is  quite  in  order,  on  the  making  of  a  new  dis-  The  posi- 

,,  «     •  1  tiontbatad- 

covery,  to  resort  to  all  proper  means  to  brmg  the  new  vanced  sci- 
rule  to  the  test.  When,  however,  after  the  lapse  of  a  occupy, 
reasonable  period  of  time,  it  has  been  sufficiently  often 
subjected  to  direct  testing,  it  becomes  science  to  recog- 
nise that  any  other  proof  than  that  has  become  quite 
needless ;  that  there  is  no  sense  in  considering  a  rule 
as  the  better  established  for  being  founded  on  others 
that  have  been  reached  by  the  very  same  method  of 
observation,  only  earlier ;  that  one  well-considered  and 
tested  observation  is  as  good  as  another.     To-day,  we 


82  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

should  regard  the  principles  of  the  lever,  of  statical 
moments,  of  the  inclined  plane,  of  virtual  displace- 
ments, and  of  the  parallelogram  of  forces  as  discovered 
by  equivalent  observations.  It  is  of  no  importance  now^ 
that  some  of  these  discoveries  were  made  directly,  while 
others  were  reached  by  roundabout  ways  and  as  de- 
pendent upon  other  observations.  It  is  more  in  keep- 
ing, furthermore,  with  the  economy  of  thought  and  with 
insieht  bet-  the  assthctics  of  science,  directly  to  recognise  a  principle 
dficiaidem-  (say  that  of  the  statical  moments)  as  the  key  to  the  un- 

ODStration.       ,,.  r  ,     'i  r  r  i  , 

derstandmg  of  a//  the  facts  of  a  department,  and  really 
see  how  it  pen^ades  all  those  facts,  rather  than  to  hold 
ourselves  obliged  first  to  make  a  clumsy  and  lame  de- 
duction of  it  from  unobvious  propositions  that  involve 
the  same  principle  but  that  happen  to  have  become 
earlier  familiar  to  us.  This  process  science  and  the  in- 
dividual (in  historical  study)  may  go  through  once  for 
all.  But  having  done  so  both  are  free  to  adopt  a  more 
convenient  point  of  view. 
The  mis-  5-   In  fact,  this  mania  for  demonstration  in  science 

mania  for    results  in  a  rigor  that  is  false  and  mistaken.  Some  pro- 
^emons  ra-  p^gj^j^j^g  ^^^  held  to  be  possessed  of  more  certainty 

than  others  and  even  regarded  as  their  necessary  and 
incontestable  foundation  ;  whereas  actually  no  higher, 
or  perhaps  not  even  so  high,  a  degree  of  certainty  at- 
taches to  them.  Even  the  rendering  clear  of  the  de- 
gree of  certainty  which  exact  science  aims  at,  is  not  at- 
tained here.  Examples  of  such  mistaken  rigor  are  to 
be  found  in  almost  every  text-book.  The  deductions 
of  Archimedes,  not  considering  their  historical  value, 
are  infected  with  this  erroneous  rigor.  But  the  most 
conspicuous  example  of  all  is  furnished  by  Daniel  Ber- 
noulli's deduction  of  the  parallelogram  of  forces  (^Com- 
ment. Acad.  Fetrop,  T.  I.). 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS,  83 

6.  As  already  seen,  instinctive  knowledge  enjoys  The  char- 

acter of  in> 
our  exceptional  confidence.     No  longer  knowing  how  stinctWe 

we  have  acquired  it,  we  cannot  criticise  the  logic  by 
which  it  was  inferred.  We  have  personally  contributed 
nothing  to  its  production.  It  confronts  us  with  a  force 
and  irresistibleness  foreign  to  the  products  of  volun- 
tary reflective  experience.  It  appears  to  us  as  some- 
thing free  from  subjectivity,  and  extraneous  to  us,  al- 
though we  have  it  constantly  at  hand  so  that  it  is  more 
ours  than  are  the  individual  facts  of  nature. 

All  this  has  often  led  men  to  attribute  knowledge  of  its  anthor- 
this  kind  to  an  entirely  different  source,  namely,  to  view  latSy  su- 
it as  existing  a  priori  in  us  (previous  to  all  experience).  ^"™®' 
That  this  opinion  is  untenable  was  fully  explained  in 
our  discussion  of  the  achievements  of  Stevinus.     Yet 
even  the  authority  of  instinctive  knowledge,  however 
important  it  may  be  for  actual  processes  of  develop- 
ment, must  ultimately  give  place  to  that  of  a  clearly  and 
deliberately  observed  principle.   Instinctive  knowledge 
is,  after  all,  only  experimental  knowledge,  and  as  such 
is  liable,  we  have  seen,  to  prove  itself  utterly  insuffi- 
cient and  powerless,  when  some  new  region  of  expe- 
rience is  suddenly  opened  up. 

7.  The  true  relation  and  connection  of  the  different  The  tree  re- 
principles  is  the  historical  one.  The  one  extends  farther  principles 
in  this  domain,  the  other  farther  in  that.     Notwith- cai  one. 
standing  that  some  one  principle,  say  the  principle  of 
virtual    displacements,    may   control    with    facility   a 
greater  number  of  cases  than  other  principles,  still 

no  assurance  can  be  given  that  it  will  always  maintain 
its  supremacy  and  will  not  be  outstripped  by  some  new 
principle.  All  principles  single  out,  more  or  less  arbi- 
trarily, now  this  aspect  now  that  aspect  of  the  same 
facts,  and  contain  an  abstract  summarised  rule  for  the 


t 
84  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

refigurement  of  the  facts  in  thought.     We  can  never 
assert  that  this  process  has  been  definitively  completed. 
Whosoever  holds  to  this  opinion,  will  not  stand  in  the 
way  of  the  advancement  of  science. 
Conception        8.    Let  US,  in  conclusion,  direct  our  attention  for  a 

of  force  in 

statics.  moment  to  the  conception  of  force  in  statics.  Force  is 
any  circumstance  of  which  the  consequence  is  motion. 
Several  circumstances  of  this  kind,  however,  each  single 
one  of  which  determines  motion,  may  be  so  conjoined 
that  in  the  result  there  shall  be  no  motion.  Now  stat- 
ics investigates  what  this  mode  of  conjunction,  in  gen- 
eral terms,  is.  Statics  does  not  further  concern  itself 
about  the  particular  character  of  the  motion  condi- 
tioned by  the  forces.  The  circumstances  determinative 
of  motion  that  are  best  known  to  us,  are  our  own  vo- 
The  origin  litioual  acts — our  innervations.  In  the  motions  which 
tion  of  we  ourselves  determine,  as  well  as  in  those  to  which 
we  are  forced  by  external  circumstances,  we  are  always 
sensible  of  a  pressure.  Thence  arises  our  habit  of  rep- 
resenting all  circumstances  determinative  of  motion  as 
something  akin  to  volitional  acts — as  pressures.  The 
attempts  we  make  to  set  aside  this  conception,  as  sub- 
jective, animistic,  and  unscientific,  fail  invariably.  It 
cannot  profit  us,  surely,  to  do  violence  to  our  own  nat- 
ural-born thoughts  and  to  doom  ourselves,  in  that  re- 
gard, to  voluntary  mental  penury.  We  shall  subse- 
quently have  occasion  to  observe,  that  the  conception 
referred  to  also  plays  a  part  in  the  foundation  of  dy- 
namics. 

We  are  able,  in  a  great  many  cases,  to  replace  the 
circumstances  determinative  of  motion,  '^ich  occur  in 
nature,  by  our  innervations,  and  thus  to  reach  the  idea 
of  a  gradation  of  the  intensity  of  forces.  But  in  the  esti- 
mation of  this  intensity  we  are  thrown  entirely  on  the 


pressure. 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS.  85 

resources  of  our  memory,  and  are  also  unable  to  com-  The  com- 
municate our  sensations.     Since  it  is  possible,  how-acterofaii 
ever,    to   represent    every  condition   that   determines 
motion  by  a  weight,  we  arrive  at  the  perception  that 
all  circumstances  determinative  of  motion  (all  forces) 
are  alike  in  character  and  may  be  replaced  and  meas- 
ured by  quantities  that  stand  for  weight.     The  meas- 
urable weight  serves  us,  as  a  certain,  convenient,  and 
communicable  index,  in  mechanical  researches,  just  as 
the  thermometer  in  thermal  researches  is  an  exacter 
substitute  for  our  perceptions  of  heat.     As  has  pre- The  idea  of 
viously  been  remarked,  statics  cannot  wholly  rid  itself  auxiliary 
of  all  knowledge  of  phenomena  of  motion.     This  par-  statics, 
ticularly  appears  in  the  determination  of  the  direction 
of  a  force  by  the  direction  of  the  motion  which  it  would 
produce  if  it  acted  alone.     By  the  point  of  application 
of  a  force  we  mean  that  point  of  a  body  whose  motion 
is  still  determined  by  the  force  when  the  point  is  freed 
from  its  connections  with  the  other  parts  of  the  body. 

Force  accordingly  is  any  circumstance  that  de-Thegene- 
termines  motion  :  and  its  attributes  may  be  stated  asbutesof 
follows.  The  direction  of  the  force  is  the  direction  of 
motion  which  is  determined  by  that  force,  alone.  The 
point  of  application  is  that  point  whose  motion  is  de- 
termined independently  of  its  coi|nections  with  the 
system.  The  magnitude  of  the  f  Ace  is  that  weight 
which,  acting  (say,  on  a  string)  in  |he  direction  deter- 
mined, and  applied  at  the  point  in  question,  determines 
the  same  motion  or  maintains  th^same  equilibrium. 
The  other  circumstances  that  modify  the  determination 
of  a  motion,  but  by  themselves  alon^  are  unable  to  pro- 
duce it,  such  as  virtual  displacements,  the  arms  of 
levers,  and  so  forth,  may  be  termed  collateral  condi- 
tions determinative  of  motion  and  equilibrium. 


86  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 


VI. 

THE    PRINCIPLES    OF    STATICS    IN    THEIR    APPLICATION    TO 

FLUIDS. 

No  essen-  I*  The  Consideration  of  fluids  has  not  supplied  stat- 

ppinti°or    ics  with  many  essentially  new  points  of  view,  yet  nu- 
volveifjn     merous  applications  and  confirmations  of  the  principles 
««u  J^*^*- already  known  have  resulted  therefrom,  and  physical 
experience  has  been  greatly  enriched  by  the  investiga- 
tions of  this  domain.  We  shall  devote,  therefore,  a  few 
pages  to  this  subject. 

2.  To  Archimedes  also  belongs  the  honor  of  found- 
ing the  domain  of  the  statics  of  liquids.  To  him  we 
owe  the  well-known  proposition  concerning  the  buoy- 
ancy, or  loss  of  weight,  of  bodies  immersed  in  liquids, 
of  the  discovery  of  which  Vitruvius,  De  Architectural 
Lib.  IX,  gives  the  following  account : 
vitruvius's  "Though  Archimcdes  discovered  many  curious 
Archime?  ' '  matters  that  evince  great  intelligence,  that  which  I  am 
covery.*"  **about  to  mention  is  the  most  extraordinary.  Hiero, 
**when  he  obtained  the  regal  power  in  Syracuse,  hav- 
**ing,  on  the  fortunate  turn  of  his  affairs,  decreed  a 
"votive  crown  of  gold  to  be  placed  in  a  certain  temple 
**to  the  immortal  gods,  commanded  it  to  be  made  of 
**  great  value,  and  assigned  for  this  purpose  an  appro- 
*'  priate  weight  of  the  metal  to  the  manufacturer.  The 
**  latter,  in  due  time,  presented  the  work  to  the  king, 
**  beautifully  wrought ;  and  the  weight  appeared  to  cor- 
**  respond  with  that  of  the  gold  which  had  been  as- 
**  signed  for  it. 

**But  a  report  having  been  circulated,  that  some  of 
**  the  gold  had  been  abstracted,  and  that  the  deficiency 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS,  87 

'*  thus  caused  had  been  supplied  by  silver,  Hiero  was  The  ac- 

,     , .  1        r  1  1  •  i       •  1      1      count  of  Vi- 

<<  indignant  at  the  fraud,  and,  unacquainted  with  the  trnyius. 
"method  by  which  the  theft  might  be  detected,  re- 
'*  quested  Archimedes  would  undertake  to  give  it  his 
"attention.  Charged  with  this  commission,  he  by 
"chance  went  to  a  bath,  and  on  jumping  into  the  tub, 
"perceived  that,  just  in  the  proportion  that  his  body 
"became  immersed,  in  the  same  proportion  the  water 
"ran  out  of  the  vessel.  Whence,  catching  at  the 
"  method  to  be  adopted  for  the  solution  of  the  proposi- 
"tion,  he  immediately  followed  it  up,  leapt  out  of  the 
"  vessel  in  joy,  and  returning  home  naked,  cried  out 
"with  a  loud  voice  that  he  had  found  that  of  which  he 
"was  in  search,  for  he  continued  exclaiming,  in  Greek, 
^^evpijxa^  evprjHa,  (I  have  found  it,  I  have  found  it !)" 

3.  The  observation  which  led  Archimedes  to  his  statement 

.  of  the  Ar- 

proposition,  was  accordingly  this,  that  a  body  im-chimedean 
mersed  in  water  must  raise  an  equivalent  quantity  of 
water ;  exactly  as  if  the  body  lay  on  one  pan  of  a  balance 
and  the  water  on  the  other.  This  conception,  which 
at  the  present  day  is  still  the  most  natural  and  the 
most  direct,  also  appears  in  Archimedes's  treatises  On 
Floating  Bodies,  which  unfortunately  have  not  been 
completely  preserved  but  have  in  part  been  resiored 
by  F.  Commandinus. 

The   assumption    from   which   Archimedes    starts 
reads  thus : 

"It  is  assumed  as  the  essential  property  of  a  liquid  The  Archi- 
that  in  all  uniform  and  continuous  positions  of  its  parts  sumption, 
the  portion  that  suffers  the  lesser  pressure  is  forced 
upwards  by  that  which  suffers  the  greater  pressure. 
But  each  part  of  the  liquid  suffers  pressure  from  the 
portion  perpendicularly  above  it  if  the  latter  be  sinking 
or  suffer  pressure  from  another  portion." 


88 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 


Analysis  of 
the  princi- 
ple. 


Fig.  59. 


Archimedes  now,  to  present  the  matter  briefly, 
conceives  the  entire  spherical  earth  as  fluid  in  consti- 
tution, and  cuts  out  of  it  pyramids  the  vertices  of 
which  lie  at  the  centre  (Fig.  59).     All  these  pyramids 

must,  in  the  case  of  equilib- 
rium, have  the  same  weight, 
and  the  similarly  situated 
parts  of  the  same  must  all 
suffer  the  same  pressure. 
If  we  plunge  a  body  a  of 
the  same  specific  gravity  as 
water  into  one  of  the  pyra- 
mids, the  body  will  com- 
pletely submerge,  and,  in 
the  case  of  equilibrium,  will  supply  by  its  weight  the 
pressure  of  the  displaced  water.  The  body  ^,  of  less 
specific  gravity,  can  sink,  without  disturbance  of  equi- 
librium, only  to  the  point  at  which  the  water  beneath 
it  suffers  the  same  pressure  from  the  weight  of  the 
body  as  it  would  if  the  body  were  taken  out  and  the 
submerged  portion  replaced  by  water.  The  body  r, 
of  a  greater  specific  gravity,  sinks  as  deep  as  it  possibly 
can.  That  its  weight  is  lessened  in  the  water  by  an 
amount  equal  to  the  weight  of  the  water  displaced, 
will  be  manifest  if  we  imagine  the  body  joined  to 
another  of  less  specific  gravity  so  that  a  third  body  is 
formed  having  the  same  specific  gravity  as  water, 
which  just  completely  submerges. 
The  state  of  4.  When  in  the  sixteenth  century  the  study  of  the 
in  the  SIX-    works  of  Archimedcs  was  again  taken  up,  scarcely  the 

teenth  cen-        ...  r    i_  •  ■!_  j        ^       j         rni. 

tury.  pnnciples  of  his  researches  were  understood.     The 

complete  comprehension  of  his  deductions  was  at  that 
time  impossible. 

Stevinus  rediscovered  by  a  method  of  his  own  the 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS, 


89 


most  important  principles  of  hydrostatics  and  the  de-  The  discov- 

x-  r-  J  eriesofSte- 

ductions  therefrom.  It  was  principally  two  ideas  from  vinus. 
which  Stevinus  derived  his  fruitful  conclusions.  The 
one  is  quite  similar  to  that  relating  to  the  endless 
chain.  The  other  consists  in  the  assumption  that  the 
solidification  of  a  fluid  in  equilibrium  does  not  disturb 
its  equilibrium. 

Stevinus  first  lays  down  this  principle.     Any  given  The  first 
mass  of  water  A  (Fig.  60),  immersed  in  water,  is  m  tai  pnnd- 
equilibrium  in  all  its  parts.     If  A 


Fig.  6a 


were  not  supported  by  the  sur- 
rounding water  but  should,  let  us 
say,  descend,  then  the  portion  of 
water  taking  the  place  of  A  and 
placed  thus  in  the  same  circum- 
stances, would,  on  the  same  as- 
sumption, also  have  to  descend. 
This  assumption  leads,  therefore,  to  the  establishment 
of  a  perpetual  motion,  which  is  contrary  to  our  ex- 
perience and  to  our  instinctive  knowledge  of  things. 

Water  immersed    in  water   loses   accordingly  its  The  second 
whole  weight.    If,  now,  we  imagine  the  surface  of  the  tai  princi- 

ole 

submerged  water  solidified,  the  vessel  formed  by  this 
surface,  the  vas  superficiarium  as  Stevinus  calls  it,  will 
still  be  subjected  to  the  same  circumstances  of  pres- 
sure. If  empty^  the  vessel  so  formed  will  suffer  an 
upward  pressure  in  the  liquid  equal  to  the  weight  of  the 
water  displaced.  If  we  fill  the  solidified  surface  with 
some  other  substance  of  any  specific  gravity  we  may 
choose,  it  will  be  plain  that  the  diminution  of  the 
weight  of  the  body  will  be  equal  to  the  weight  of  the 
fluid  displaced  on  immersion. 

In  a  rectangular,  vertically  placed  parallelepipedal 
vessel  filled  with  a  liquid,  the  pressure  on  the  horizontal 


go 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 


Stevinna's 
deductioDft. 


Galileo,  in 
the  treat- 
ment of  this 
subject,  em- 
ploys the 
principle  of 
virtual  dis- 
placements 


base  is  equal  to  the  weight  of  the  liquid.  The  pressure 
is  equal,  also,  for  all  parts  of  the  bottom  of  the  same 
area.  When  now  Stevinus  imagines  portions  of  the 
liquid  to  be  cut  out  and  replaced  by  rigid  immersed 
bodies  of  the  same  specific  gravity,  or,  what  is  the 
same  thing,  imagines  parts  of  the  liquid  to  become  so- 
lidified, the  relations  of  pressure  in  the  vessel  will  not 
be  altered  by  the  procedure.  But  we  easily  obtain  in 
this  way  a  clear  view  of  the  law  that  the  pressure  on 
the  base  of  a  vessel  is  independent  of  its  form,  as  well 
as  of  the  laws  of  pressure  in  communicating  vessels, 
and  so  forth. 

5.  Galileo  treats  the  equilibrium  of  liquids  in  com- 
municating vessels  and  the  problems  connected  there- 
with by  the  help  of  the  principle  of  virtual  displace- 
ments. NN  (Fig.  61)  being  the 
common  level  of  a  liquid  in  equilib- 
rium in  two  communicating  vessels, 
Galileo  explains  the  equilibrium 
here  presented  by  observing  that  in 
the  case  of  any  disturbance  the  dis- 
placements of  the  columns  are  to 
each  other  in  the  inverse  proportion 
of  the  areas  of  the  transverse  sec- 
tions and  of  the  weights  of  the  columns — that  is,  as 
with  machines  in  equilibrium.  But  this  is  not  quite  cor- 
rect. The  case  does  not  exactly  correspond  to  the 
cases  of  equilibrium  investigated  by  Galileo  in  ma- 
chines, which  present  indifferent  equilibrium.  With 
liquids  in  communicating  tubes  every  disturbance  of  the 
common  level  of  the  liquids  produces  an  elevation  of 
the  centre  of  gravity.  In  the  case  represented  in  Fig. 
61,  the  centre  of  gravity  S  of  the  liquid  displaced  from 
the  shaded  space  in  A  is  elevated  to  S\  and  we  may 


Pig.  6x. 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS. 


91 


Fig.  6a. 


regard  the  rest  of  the  liquid  as  not  having  been  moved. 
Accordingly,  in  the  case  of  equilibrium,  the  centre  of 
gravity  of  the  liquid  lies  at  its  lowest  possible  point 

6.  Pascal  likewise  employs  the  principle  of  virtual  The  same 

principle 

displacements,  but  in  a  more  correct  manner,  leaving  made  use  of 

,         ,        by  Pascal. 

the  weight  of  the  liquid  out  of  account  and  considering 
only  the  pressure  at  the  surface.  If  we  imagine  two 
communicating  vessels  to  be  closed  by  pistons  (Fig. 
62),  and  these  pistons  loaded  with 
weights  proportional  to  their  surface- 
areas,  equilibrium  will  obtain,  because 
in  consequence  of  the  invariability  of 
the  volume  of  the  liquid  the  displace- 
ments in  every  disturbance  are  in- 
versely proportional  to  the  weights. 
For  Pascal,  accordingly,  it  follows,  as  a  necessary  con- 
sequence, from  the  principle  of  virtual  displacements, 
that  in  the  case  of  equilibrium  every  pressure  on  a  su- 
perficial portion  of  a  liquid  is  propagated  with  undi- 
minished effect  to  every  other  superficial  portion,  how- 
ever and  in  whatever  position  it  be  placed.  No  objec- 
tion is  to  be  made  to  discovering  the  principle  in  this 
way.  Yet  we  shall  see  later  on  that  the  more  natural 
and  satisfactory  conception  is  to  regard  the  principle  as 
immediately  given. 

7.  We  shall  now,  after  this  historical  sketch,  again  Detailed 
examine  the  most  important  cases  of  liquid  equilibrium,  don  of  the 
and  from  such  different  points  of  view  as  may  be  con-  "  ^ 
venient. 

The  fundamental  property  of  liquids  given  us  by 
experience  consists  in  the  flexure  of  their  parts  on  the 
slightest  application  of  pressure.  Let  us  picture  to  our- 
selves an  element  of  volume  of  a  liquid,  the  gravity  of 
which  we  disregard — say  a  tiny  cube.     If  the  slightest 


92  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

The  funda-  excess  of  pressure  be  exerted  on  one  of  the  surfaces  of 

mental  .  . 

proi>ert7of  this  cube,  (which  we  now  conceive,  for  the  moment, 
mobility  of  as  a  fixed  geometrical  locus,  containing  the  fluid  but 

their  parts. 

not  of  its  substance)  the  liquid  (supposed  to  have  pre- 
viously been  in  equilibrium  and  at  rest)  will  yield  and 
pass  out  in  all  directions  through  the  other  five  surfaces 
of  the  cube.  A  solid  cube  can  stand  a  pressure  on  its 
upper  and  lower  surfaces  different  in  magnitude  from 
that  on  its  lateral  surfaces  ;  or  vice  versa,  A  fluid  cube, 
on  the  other  hand,  can  retain  its  shape  only  if  the  same 
perpendicular  pressure  be  exerted  on  all  its  sides.  A 
similar  train  of  reasoning  is  applicable  to  all  polyhe- 
drons. In  this  conception,  as  thus  geometrically  eluci- 
dated, is  contained  nothing  but  the  crude  experience 
that  the  particles  of  a  liquid  yield  to  the  slightest  pres- 
sure, and  that  they  retain  this  property  also  in  the  in- 
terior of  the  liquid  when  under  a  high  pressure ;  it 
being  observable,  for  example,  that  under  the  condi- 
tions cited  minute  heavy  bodies  sink  in  fluids,  and  so  on. 
A  second  With  the  mobility  of  their  parts  liquids  combine 

the  com-  still  another  property,  which  we  will  now  consider.  Li- 
of  their  vol-  quids  suffer  through  pressure  a  diminution  of  volume 
which  is  proportional  to  the  pressure  exerted  on  unit 
of  surface.  Every  alteration  of  pressure  carries  along 
with  it  a  proportional  alteration  of  volume  and  density. 
If  the  pressure  diminish,  the  volume  becomes  greater, 
the  density  less.  The  volume  of  a  liquid  continues  to 
diminish  therefore  on  the  pressure  being  increased,  till 
the  point  is  reached  at  which  the  elasticity  generated 
within  it  equilibrates  the  increase  of  the  pressure. 

8.  The  earlier  inquirers,  as  for  instance  those  of  the 
Florentine  Academy,  were  of  the  opinion  that  liquids 
were  incompressible.  In  1761,  however,  John  Canton 
performed  an  experiment  by  which  the  compressibility 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS.  93 

of  water  was  demonstrated.     A  thermometer  glass  is  Ths  £ni 
filled  wit4i  water,  boiled,  and  then  sealed.  (F\g.  63.)iioDo(ihe 
The  liquid  reaches  to  a.   But  since  the  space  above  a  is  biiitv  ot 
airless,  the  liquid  supports  no  atmospheric  pres- 
sure.    If  the  sealed  end  be  broken  off,  the  liquid      1 
will  sink  to  i.     Only  a  portion,  however,  of  this      L 
displacement  is  to  be  placed  to  the  credit  of  the  '-  W 
compression  of  the  liquid  by  atmospheric  pres- 
sure.    For  if  we  place  the  glass  before  breaking  ^^ 
off  the  top  under  an  air-pump  and  exhaust  the  ^^ 
chamber,  the  liquid  will  sink  to  c.   This  last  phe-  p. 
nomenon  is  due  to  the  fact  that  the  pressure  that 
bears  down  on  the  exterior  of  the  glass  and  diminishes 
its  capacity,  is  now  removed.  On  breaking  off  the  top, 
this  exterior  pressure  of  the  atmosphere  is  compensated 
for  by  the  interior  pressure  then  introduced,  and  an 
enlargement  of  the  capacity  of  the  glass  again  sets  in. 
The  portion  cb,  therefore,  answers  to  the  actual  com- 
pression of  the  liquid  by  the  pressure  of  the  atmos- 

The  first,  to  institute  exact  experiments  on  the  com-  Tho  eipeii 
pressibility  of  water,  was  Oersted,  who  employed  tooBr«t«ion 
this  end  a  very  ingenious   method.     A 
thermometer  glass  A  (Fig.  64)  is  filled 
with  boiled  water  and  is  inverted,  with 
open  mouth,  into  a  vessel  of  mercury. 
Near  it  stands  a  manometer  tube  B  filled 
with  air  and  likewise  inverted  with  open 
mouth  in  the  mercury.      The  whole  ap- 
paratus is  then  placed  in  a  vessel  filled  i 
with  water,  which  is  compressed  by  the  1 
aid  of  a  pump.    By  this  means  the  water         ^*-  *»- 
in  A  is  also  compressed,  and  the  filament  of  quicksilver 
which  rises  in  the  capillary  tube  of  the  thermometer- 


94  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

glass  indicates  this  compression.  The  alteration  of 
capacity  which  the  glass  A  suffers  in  the  present  in- 
stance, is  merely  that  arising  from  the  pressing  to- 
gether of  its  walls  by  forces  which  are  equal  on  all  sides. 
The  expert-       The  most  delicate  experiments  on  this  subject  have 

ments  of 

Grassi.  been  conducted  by  Grassi  with  an  apparatus  con- 
structed by  Regnault,  and  computed  with  the  assist- 
ance of  Lamp's  correction-formulae.  To  give  a  tan- 
gible idea  of  the  compressibility  of  water,  we  will  remark 
that  Grassi  observed  for  boiled  water  at  0°  under  an 
increase  of  one  atmospheric  pressure  a  diminution  of 
the  original  volume  amounting  to  5  in  100,000  parts. 
If  we  imagine,  accordingly,  the  vessel  A  to  have  the 
capacity  of  one  litre  (1000  ccm.),  and  affix  to  it  a  cap- 
illary tube  of  I  sq.  mm.  cross-section,  the  quicksilver 
filament  will  ascend  in  it  5  cm.  under  a  pressure  of 
one  atmosphere. 
Surface-  9.  Surface-pressure,  accordingly,  induces  a  physical 

duces  in  alteration  in  a  liquid  (an  alteration  in  density),  which 
alteration  cau  be  detected  by  sufficiently  delicate  means — even 
optical.  We  are  always  at  liberty  to  think  that  por- 
tions of  a  liquid  under  a  higher  pressure  are  more  dense, 
though  it  may  be  very  slightly  so,  than  parts  under  a 
less  pressure. 
The  impii-  Let  US  imagine  now,  we  have  in  a  liquid  (in  the  in- 
ihii  fact,  terior  of  which  no  forces  act  and  the  gravity  of  which 
we  accordingly  neglect)  two  portions  subjected  to  un- 
equal pressures  and  contiguous  to  one  another.  The 
portion  under  the  greater  pressure,  being  denser,  will 
expand,  and  press  against  the  portion  under  the  less 
pressure,  until  the  forces  of  elasticity  as  le3sened  on  the 
one  side  and  increased  on  the  other  establish  equilib- 
rium at  the  bounding  surface  and  both  portions  are 
equally  compressed. 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS,  95 

If  we  endeavor,  now,  quantitatively  to  elucidate  ourThestate- 
mental  conception  of  these  two  facts,  the  easy  mobility  these  impU- 
and  the  compressibility  of  the  parts  of  a  liquid,  so  that 
they  will  fit  the  most  diverse  classes  of  experience, 
we  shall  arrive  at  the  following  proposition :  When 
equilibrium  subsists  in  a  liquid,  in  the  interior  of  which 
no  forces  act  and  the  gravity  of  which  we  neglect,  the 
same  equal  pressure  is  exerted  on  each  and  every  equal 
surface-element  of  that  liquid  however  and  wherever 
situated.  The  pressure,  therefore,  is  the  same  at  all 
points  and  is  independent  of  direction. 

Special  experiments  in  demonstration  of  this  prin- 
ciple have,  perhaps,  never  been  instituted  with  the  re- 
quisite degree  of  exactitude.  But  the  proposition  has 
by  our  experience  of  liquids  been  made  very  familiar, 
and  readily  explains  it. 

10.  If  a  liquid  be  enclosed  in  a  vessel  (Fig.  65)  Preiimi- 
which  is  supplied  with  a  piston^,  the  cross-section  marks  to 
of  which  is  unit  in  area,  and  with  a  piston  B  which  ion  of  Pas- 

,..,..  ,  cal'sdedno- 

for  the  time  bemg  is  made  station-  ■z±-b>/      '*°"* 

ary,  and   on  the  piston  A  a  load  p         ^^E^3^^ 
be  placed,   then  the  same  pressure       ^^^^E^^^ 
/>,    gravity    neglected,    will    prevail      ^^_-^i^^^ 
throughout  all  the  parts  of  the  vessel.    _J^~-  -  -  -  ~  "^ 
The  piston  will  penetrate  inward  and     y^^^^^gr 
the  walls  of  the  vessel  will  continue      ^Ni^  ' 
to  be  deformed  till  the  point  is  reached  p»8-  ^' 

at  which  the  elastic  forces  of  the  rigid  and  fluid  bodies 
perfectly  equilibrate  one  another.  If  then  we  imagine 
the  piston  B,  which  has  the  cross-section/,  to  be  mov- 
able, a  force  /.  /  alone  will  keep  it  in  equilibrium. 

Concerning  Pascal's  deduction  of  the  proposition 
before  discussed  from  the  principle  of  virtual  displace- 
ments, it  is  to  be  remarked  that  the  conditions  of  dis- 


96  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

Criticism  of  placement  which  he  perceived  hinge  wholly  upon  the 
daction.  fact  of  the  ready  mobility  of  the  parts  and  on  the 
equality  of  the  pressure  throughout  every  portion  of 
the  liquid.  If  it  were  possible  for  a  greater  compression 
to  take  place  in  one  part  of  a  liquid  than  in  another, 
the  ratio  of  the  displacements  would  be  disturbed  and 
Pascal's  deduction  would  no  longer  be  admissible. 
That  the  property  of  the  equality  of  the  pressure  is  a 
property  given  in  experience,  is  a  fact  that  cannot  be 
escaped  ;  as  we  shall  readily  admit  if  we  recall  to  mind 
that  the  same  law  that  Pascal  deduced  for  liquids  also 
holds  good  for  gases,  where  even  approximately  there 
can  be  no  question  of  a  constant  volume.  This  latter 
fact  does  not  afford  any  difficulty  to  our  view ;  but  to 
that  of  Pascal  it  does.  In  the  case  of  the  lever  also,  be 
it  incidentally  remarked,  the  ratios  of  the  virtual  dis- 
placements are  assured  by  the  elastic  forces  of  the 
lever-body,  which  do  not  permit  of  any  great  devia- 
.  tion  from  these  relations. 
Thebehav-        u.  We  shall  now  consider  the  action  of  liquids  un- 

lourofli-  ,  * 

cniids  under  der  the  influence  of  gravity.     The  upper  surface  of  a 

of  gravity.       liquid  in  equilibrium  is  horizontal, 

A7V(Fig.  66).  This  fact  is  at  once 
rendered  intelligible  when  we  re- 
flect that  every  alteration  of  the  sur- 
face in  question  elevates  the  centre 
of  gravity  of  the  liquid,  and  pushes 
Fig.  66.  ^i^g  liquid  mass  resting  in  the  shaded 

space  beneath  NN  and  having  the  centre  of  gravity  »S 
into  the  shaded  space  above  NN  having  the  centre  of 
gravity  S\  Which  alteration,  of  course,  is  at  once  re- 
versed by  gravity. 

Let  there  be  in  equilibrium  in  a  vessel  a  heavy 
liquid  with  a  horizontal  upper  surface.     We  consider 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS,  97 

(Fig.  67)  a  small  rectangular  parallelepipedon  in  the  The  con- 
interior.    The  area  of  its  horizontal  base,  we  will  say,  is  equUibriam 
a,  and  the  length  of  its  vertical  edges  dh.    The  weight  sabjected 
of  this  parallelepipedon  is  therefore  adhSy  where  s  isuonofgrav- 
its  specific  gravity.     If  the  paral-  '  ^' 


p^dp 


lelepipedon  do  not  sink,  this  is 
possible  only  on  the  condition  that 
a  greater  pressure  is  exerted  on  the 
lower  surface  by  the  fluid  than  on 
the  upper.  The  pressures  on  the  . 
upper  and  lower  surfaces  we  will  ^**-  ^• 

respectively  designate  as  ap  and  or  (/  +  dp).  Equi- 
librium obtains  when  adh,s  =  adp  or  dp/dh=:Sy 
where  h  in  the  downward  direction  is  reckoned  as  posi- 
tive. We  see  from  this  that  for  equal  increments  of  h 
vertically  downwards  the  pressure  /  must,  correspond- 
ingly, also  receive  equal  increments.  So  that  /  = 
hs-\-  q\  and  if  ^,  the  pressure  at  the  upper  surface, 
which  is  usually  the  pressure  of  the  atmosphere,  be- 
comes =  0,  we  have,  more  simply,  pz=  hs,  that  is,  the 
pressure  is  proportional  to  the  depth  beneath  the  sur- 
face. If  we  imagine  the  liquid  to  be  pouring  into  a  ves- 
sel, and  this  condition  of  affairs  not  yet  attained,  every 
liquid  particle  will  then  sink  until  the  compressed  par- 
ticle beneath  balances  by  the  elasticity  developed  in  it 
the  weight  of  the  particle  above. 

From  the  view  we  have  here  presented  it  will  be  fur-  Different 
ther  apparent,  that  the  increase  of  pressure  in  a  liquid  tionrezist 
takes  place  solely  in  the  direction  in  which  gravity  Sneo? the* 
acts.     Only  at  the  lower  surface,  at  the  base,  of  the  ImSy! 
parallelepipedon,  is  an  excess  of  elastic  pressure  on  the 
part  of  the  liquid  beneath  required  to  balance  the 
weight  of  the  parallelepipedon.  Along  the  two  sides  of 
the  vertical  containing  surfaces  of  the  parallelepipedon, 


98  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

the  liquid  is  in  a  state  of  equal  compression,  since  no 
force  acts  in  the  vertical  containing  surfaces  that  would 
determine  a  greater  compression  on  the  one  side  than 
on  the  other. 
Level  sur-  If  we  picture  to  ourselves  the  totality  of  all  the 
points  of  the  liquid  at  which  the  same  pressure  /  acts, 
we  shall  obtain  a  surface — a  so-called  level  surface.  If 
we  displace  a  particle  in  the  direction  of  the  action  of 
gravity,  it  undergoes  a  change  of  pressure.  If  we  dis- 
place it  at  right  angles  to  the  direction  of  the  action  of 
gravity,  no  alteration  of  pressure  takes  place.  In  the 
latter  case  it  remains  on  the  same  level  surface,  and 
the  element  of  the  level  surface,  accordingly,  stands  at 
right  angles  to  the  direction  of  the  force  of  gravity. 

Imagining  the  earth  to  be  fluid  and  spherical,  the 
level  surfaces  are  concentric  spheres,  and  the  directions 
of  the  forces  of  gravity  (the  radii)  stand  at  right  angles 
to  the  elements  of  the  spherical  surfaces.  Similar  ob- 
servations are  admissible  if  the  liquid  particles  be  acted 
on  by  other  forces  than  gravity,  magnetic  forces,  for 
example. 
Their  fano-  The  level  surfaces  afford,  in  a  certain  sense,  a  dia- 
thought,  gram  of  the  force-relations  to  which  a  fluid  is  subjected; 
a  view  further  elaborated  by  analytical  hydrostatics. 

12.  The  increase  of  the  pressure  with  the  depth  be- 
low the  surface  of  a  heavy  liquid  may  be  illustrated  by 
a  series  of  experiments  which  we  chiefly  owe  to  Pas- 
cal. These  experiments  also  well  illustrate  the  fact, 
that  the  pressure  is  independent  of  the  direction.  In 
Fig.  68,  I,  is  an  empty  glass  tube  g  ground  off  at  the 
bottom  and  closed  by  a  metal  disc  //,  to  which  a 
string  is  attached,  and  the  whole  plunged  into  a  vessel 
of  water.  When  immersed  to  a  sufficient  depth  we 
may  let  the  string  go,  without  the  metal  disc,  which  is 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STA  TICS. 


99 


& 


n 


supported  by  the  pressure  of  the  liquid,  falling.    In  2,  Pascal's  ez- 
the  metal  disc  is  replaced  by  a  tiny  column  of  mer-  on  the 
cury.     If  (3)  we  dip  an  open  siphon  tube  filled  with  Fiqufdi. 
quicksilver   into   the  water,   we 
shall  see  the  quicksilver,  in  conse- 
quence of  the  pressure  at  a^  rise 
into  the  longer  arm.  In  4,  we  see 
a  tube,  at  the  lower  extremity  of 
which  a  leather  bag  filled  with 
quicksilver    is    tied :    continued 
immersion  forces  the  quicksilver 
higher  and  higher  into  tube.    In 
5,  a  piece  of  wood  h  is  driven  by 
the  pressure  of  the  water  into  the 
small  arm  of  an  empty  siphon  ^ 
tube.  A  piece  of  wood  H  (6)  im- 
mersed in  mercury  adheres  to  the  h  ■''■'''•"i-iiiiiiiii    o^ 

bottom  of  the  vessel,  and  is 
pressed  firmly  against  it  for  as 
long  a  time  as  the  mercury  is 
kept  from  working  its  way  be- 
neath it. 

13.  Once  we  have  made  quite 
clear  to  ourselves  that  the  pres- 
sure in  the  interior  of  a  heavy 
liquid  increases  proportionally  to 
the  depth  below  the  surface,  the 
law  that  the  pressure  at  the  base 
of  a  vessel  is  independent  of  its 
form  will  be  readily  perceived. 
The  pressure  increases  as  we  de- 
scend at  an  equal  rate,  whether  the  vessel  (Fig.  69) 
has  the  form  abed  ox  ebcf.  In  both  cases  the  walls 
of  the  vessel  where  they  meet  the  liquid,  go  on  deforming 


C 


n 


m 


^1 


The  pres- 
sure at  the 
base  of  a 
vessel  inde- 
endent  of 


ts 


fotm. 


lOO 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 


Elucida- 
tion of  this 
fact. 


Fig.  69. 


The  princi' 
pie  ox  vir- 
tual dis- 
placements 
applied  to 
the  consid- 
eration of 
problems  of 
this  class. 


till  the  point  is  reached  at  which  they  equilibrate  by  the 
elasticity  developed  in  them  the  pressure  exerted  by  the 
fluid,  that  is,  take  the  place  as  regards  pressure  of  the 

fluid  adjoining.  This  fact  is 
a  direct  justification  of  Ste- 
vinus's  fiction  of  the  solidi- 
fied fluid  supplying  the  place 
of  the  walls  of  the  vessel. 
The  pressure  on  the  base 
always  remains  P  ■=.  Ahs, 
where  A  denotes  the  area  of  the  base,  h  the  depth  of 
the  horizontal  plane  base  below  the  level,  and  s  the 
specific  gravity  of  the  liquid. 

The  fact  that,  the  walls  of  the  vessel  being  neg- 
lected, the  vessels  i,  2,  3  of  Fig.  70  of  equal  base- 
area  and  equal  pressure-height  weigh  differently  in  the 

balance,  of  course 
in  no  wise  con- 
'  tradicts  the  laws 
of  pressure  men- 
tioned. If  we  take 
Fig.  70.  into    account     the 

lateral  pressure,  we  shall  see  that  in  the  case  of  i  we 
have  left  an  extra  component  downwards,  and  in  the 
case  of  3  an  extra  component  upwards,  so  that  on  the 
whole  the  resultant  superficial  pressure  is  always  equal 
to  the  weight. 

14.  The  principle  of  virtual  displacements  is  ad- 
mirably adapted  to  the  acquisition  of  clearness  and 
comprehensiveness  in  cases  of  this  character,  and  we 
shall  accordingly  make  use  of  it.  To  begin  with,  how- 
ever, let  the  following  be  noted.  If  the  weight  q  (Fig. 
71)  descend  from  position  i  to  position  2,  and  a  weight 
of  exactly  the  same  size  move  at  the  same  time  from 


a      • 

«      • 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS. 


lOI 


2  to  3,  the  work  performed  in  this  operation  is  qh^  +  nary "?»■ 
qh^  z=q  {h^  +  ^g),  the  same,  that  is,  as  if  the  weight™*'*^*- 
q  passed  directly  from  i  to  3  and  the  weight  at  2  re- 
mained in  its  original  position.     The  observation  is 
easily  generalised. 


2 


3 


« 


y////////y///Mh 


\(ik 


^  V/y/y////////Adh 


Fig.  71. 


Fig.  72. 


Let  us  consider  a  heavy  homogeneous  rectangular 
parallelepipedon,  with  vertical  edges  of  the  length  A, 
base  Ay  and  the  specific  gravity  s  (Fig.  72).  Let  this 
parallelepipedon  (or,  what  is  the  same  thing,  its  centre 
of  gravity)  descend  a  distance  dh.  The  work  done  is 
then  Ahs.dhy  or,  also,  A  dhs.h.  In  the  first  expres- 
sion we  conceive  the  whole  weight  Ahs  displaced  the 
vertical  distance  dh ;  in  the  second  we  conceive  the 
weight  Adhs  as  having  descended  from  the  upper 
shaded  space  to  the  lower  shaded  space  the  distance  h^ 

and  leave  out  of  account  1 T 

the  rest  of  the  body. 
Both  methods  of  concep- 
tion are  admissible  and 
equivalent. 

15.  With  the  aid  of 
this  observation  we  shall  ____^^__ 
obtain  a  clear  insight  into  p»8  73. 

the  paradox  of  Pascal,  which  consists  of  the  following. 
The  vessel  g  (Fig.  73),  fixed  to  a  separate  support  and 
consisting  of  a  narrow  upper  and  a  very  broad  lower 
cylinder,  is  closed  at  the  bottom  by  a  movable  piston, 


Pascal's 
paradox. 


I02 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 


0 


which,  by  means  of  a  string  passing  through  the  axis 
of  the  cylinders,  is  independently  suspended  from  the 
extremity  of  one  arm  of  a  balance.  If  g  be  filled  with 
water,  then,  despite  the  smallness  of  the  quantity  of 
water  used,  there  will  have  to  be  placed  on  the  other 
scale-pan,  to  balance  it,  several  considerable  weights, 
the  sum  of  which  will  he:  Ahs^  where  A  is  the  piston- 
area,  //  the  height  of  the  liquid,  and  s  its  specific  grav- 
ity. But  if  the  liquid  be  frozen  and  the  mass  loosened 
from  the  walls  of  the  vessel,  a  very  small  weight  will  be 
sufficient  to  preserve  equilibrium. 
The  ezpia-  Let  US  look  to  the  virtual  displacements  of  the  two 
the  paradox  cases  (Fig.  74).  In  the  first  case,  supposing  the  pis* 
ton  to  be  lifted  a  distance  dh,  the  virtual  moment  is 

A(ihs,h  ox  Ahs.dh,    It  thus 
comes    to    the   same  thing, 
dk  whether  we  consider  the  mass 

that  the  motion  of  the  piston 
'^=^^k     displaces  to  be  lifted  to  the 
upper  surface  of   the  fluid 
through  the  entire  pressure- 
height,  or  consider  the  entire  weight  Ahs  lifted  the 
distance  of  the  piston-displacement  dh.    In  the  second 
case,  the  mass  that  the  piston  displaces  is  not  lifted  to 
the  upper  surface  of  the  fluid,  but  suffers  a  displace- 
ment which  is  much  smaller— the  displacement,  namely, 
of  the  piston.     If  A,  a  are  the  sectional  areas  respect- 
ively of  the  greater  and  the  less  cylinder,  and  k  and  / 
their  respective  heights,  then  the  virtual  moment  of  the 
present  case  is  Adhs.  k  +  ddhs ,  I  =  {Ak  +  «^)  -f-  d/i; 
which  is  equivalent  to  the  lifting  of  a  much  smaller 
weight  (^Ak  -\-  a/)  s,  the  distance  dA, 

16.  The  laws  relating  to  the  lateral  pressure  of 
liquids  are  but  slight  modifications  of  the  laws  of  basal 


dM 


Mh 


Fig.  74. 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS. 


103 


pressure.  If  we  have,  for  example,  a  cubical  vessel  The  Uwa  of 
of  I  decimetre  on  the  side,  which  is  a  vessel  of  litre  pressure, 
capacity,  the  pressure  on  any  one  of  the  vertical  lateral 
walls  ABCDy  when  the  vessel  is  filled  with  water^  is 
easily  determinable.  The  deeper  the  migratory  element 
considered  descends  beneath  the  surface,  the  greater 
the  pressure  will  be  to  which  it  is  subjected.  We  easily 
perceive,  thus,  that  the  pressure  on  a  lateral  wall  is  rep- 
resented by  a  wedge  of  water  A  BCD  HI  resting  upon 
the  wall  horizontally 
placed,  where  ID  is  at 
right  angles  to  BD  and 
ID  =  HC=Aa  The 
lateral  pressure  accor-  ^^ 
dingly  is  equal  to  half 
a  kilogramme. 

To  determine  the 
point  of  application  of  the  resultant  pressure,  conceive 
ABCD  again  horizontal  with  the  water-wedge  resting 
upon  it.  We  cut  off  AK  =  BL  =  lACy  draw  the 
straight  line  KL  and  bisect  itzi  M\  Mis  the  point  of 
application  sought,  for  through  this  point  the  vertical 
line  cutting  the  centre  of  gravity  of  the  wedge  passes. 

A  plane  inclined  figure  forming  the  base  of  a  vessel  The  pres- 
filled  with  a  liquid,  is  divided  into  the  elements  a,  a\  plane  in- 
a"  .  .  .  with  the  depths  h,  h\  A"  .  .  .  below  the  level  of ^  *°*    "  " 
the  liquid.     The  pressure  on  the  base  is 

If  we  call  the  total  base-area  A,  and  the  depth  of  its 
centre  of  gravity  below  the  surface  H,  then 


F»g-  75. 


a+  a'+  a"  +  .  ,  .  A 

whence  the  pressure  on  the  base  is  AHs. 


=  H, 


104 


7'HE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 


The  deduc- 
tion  of  the 
principle  of 
Archime- 
des may  be 
effected  in 
various 
ways. 


One  meth- 
od. 


Another 
method  in- 
volving the 
principle  of 
virtual  dis- 
placementa 


17.  The  principle  of  Archimedes  can  be  deduced  in 
various  ways.  After  the  manner  of  Stevinus,  let  us 
conceive  in  the  interior  of  the  liquid  a  portion  of  it 
solidified.  This  portion  now,  as  before,  will  be  sup- 
ported by  the  circumnatant  liquid.  The  resultant  of 
the  forces  of  pressure  acting  on  the  surfaces  is  accor- 
dingly applied  at  the  centre  of  gravity  of  the  liquid  dis- 
placed by  the  solidified  body,  and  is  equal  and  opposite 
to  its  weight.  If  now  we  put  in  the  place  of  the  solid- 
ified liquid  another  different  body  of  the  same  form,  but 
of  a  different  specific  gravity,  the  forces  of  pressure  at 
the  surfaces  will  remain  the  same.  Accordingly,  there 
now  act  on  the  body  two  forces,  the  weight  of  the  body, 
applied  at  the  centre  of  gravity  of  the  body,  and  the  up- 
ward buoyancy,  the  resultant  of  the  surface-pressures, 
applied  at  the  centre  of  gravity  of  the  displaced  liquid. 
The  two  centres  of  gravity  in  question  coincide  only  in 
the  case  of  homogeneous  solid  bodies. 

If  we  immerse  a  rectangular  parallelepipedon  of  al- 
titude h  and  base  a,  with  edges  vertically  placed,  in  a 
liquid  of  specific  gravity  s,  then  the  pressure  on  the 
upper  basal  surface,  when  at  a  depth  k  below  the  level 
of  the  liquid  is  aks,  while  the  pressure  on  the  lower 
surface  is  a  (k  -\-  h)  s.  As  the  lateral  pressures  destroy 
each  other,  an  excess  of  pressure  ahs  upwards  re- 
mains ;  or,  where  v  denotes  the  volume  of  the  paral- 
lelepipedon, an  excess  v .  s. 

We  shall  approach  nearest  the  fundamental  con- 
ception from  which  Archimedes  started,  by  recourse  to 
the  principle  of  virtual  displacements.  Let  a  paral- 
lelepipedon (Fig.  76)  of  the  specific  gravity  <r,  base  a, 
and  height  h  sink  the  distance  dh.  The  virtual  mo- 
ment of  the  transference  from  the  upper  into  the  lower 
shaded  space  of  the  figure  will  be  adh .  (T//.   But  while 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS. 


105 


this  is  done,  the  liquid  rises  from  the  lower  into  the  up- 
per space,  and  its  moment  is  adhsh.  The  total  vir- 
tual moment  is  therefore  ah{p  —  s)dh  =  (^p  —  ^)  dhy 
where  p  denotes  the  weight  of  the  body  and  q  the  weight 
of  the  displaced  liquid. 


Fig.  76. 


FlR.  77. 


18.  The  question  might  occur  to  us,  whether  the 
upward  pressure  of  a  body  in  a  liquid  is  affected  by  the 
immersion  of  the  latter  in  another  liquid.  As  a  fact, 
this  very  question  has  been  proposed.  Let  therefore 
(Fig.  77)  a  body  K  be  submerged  in  a  liquid  A  and  the 
liquid  with  the  containing  vessel  in  turn  submerged  in 
another  liquid  B,  If  in  the  determination  of  the  loss 
of  weight  in  A  it  were  proper  to  take  account  of  the 
loss  of  weight  of  A  in  B,  then  K*s  loss  of  weight  would 
necessarily  vanish  when  the  fluid  B  became  identical 
with  A.  Therefore,  K  immersed  in  A  would  suffer  a 
loss  of  weight  and  it  would  suffer  none.  Such  a  rule 
would  be  nonsensical. 

With  the  aid  of  the  principle  of  virtual  displace- 
ments, we  easily  comprehend  the  more  complicated 
cases  of  this  character.  If  a  body  be  first  gradually 
immersed  in  By  then  partly  in  B  and  partly  in  A, 
finally  in  A  wholly ;  then,  in  the  second  case,  consider- 
ing the  virtual  moments,  both  liquids  are  to  be  taken 
into  account  in  the  proportion  of  the  volume  of  the 
body  immersed  in  them.  But  as  soon  as  the  body  is 
wholly  immersed  in  A,  the  level  of  A  on  further  dis- 


l8  the  buoy- 
ancy of  a 
body  in  a 
liquid  af- 
fected by 
the  immer- 
sion of  that 
liquid  in  a 
second 
liquid? 


The  eluci- 
dation of 
more  com- 
plicated 
cases  of  this 
class. 


io6 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 


The  Archi- 
medean 
principle  il- 
lustrated by 
an  experi- 
ment. 


The  coun- 
ter-experi- 
ment. 


Remarks  on 
the  experi- 
ment. 


placement  no  longer  rises,  and  therefore  B  is  no  longer 
of  consequence. 

19.  Archimedes*s  principle  may  be  illustrated  by  a 
pretty  experiment.  From  the  one  extremity  of  a  scale- 
beam  (Fig.  78)  we  hang  a  hollow  cube  /T,  and  beneath 

it  a  solid  cube  M^  which  exactly  fits  into 
the  first  cube.  We  put  weights  into  the 
opposite  pan,  until  the  scales  are  in 
equilibrium.  If  now -^  be  submerged 
in  water  by  lifting  a  vessel  which  stands 
beneath  it,  the  equilibrium  will  be  dis- 
turbed ;  but  it  will  be  immediately  re- 
stored if  /T,  the  hollow  cube,  be  filled 
with  water. 

A  counter-experiment  is  the  follow- 
ing. H  is  left  suspended  alone  at  the 
one  extremity  of  the  balance,  and  into 
the  opposite  pan  is  placed  a  vessel  of 
water,  above  which  on  an  independent 
support  J/ hangs  by  a  thin  wire.  The  scales  are  brought 
to  equilibrium.  If  now  M  be  lowered  until  it  is  im- 
mersed in  the  water,  the  equilibrium  of  the  scales  will 
be  disturbed  ;  but  on  filling  H  with  water,  it  will  be 
restored. 

At  first  glance  this  experiment  appears  a  little  para- 
doxical. We  feel,  however,  instinctively,  that  M  can- 
not be  immersed  in  the  water  without  exerting  a  pres- 
sure that  affects  the  scales.  When  we  reflect,  that  the 
level  of  the  water  in  the  vessel  rises,  and  that  the  solid 
body  M  equilibrates  the  surface- pressure  of  the  water 
surrounding  it,  that  is  to  say  represents  and  takes  the 
place  of  an  equal  volume  of  water,  it  will  be  found 
that  the  paradoxical  character  of  the  experiment  van- 
ishes. 


Fig.  78. 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS.  107 

20.  The  most  important  statical  principles  have  The  gene- 
been  reached  in  the  investigation  of  solid  bodies.  This  pies  of  stai- 
course  is  accidentally  the  historical  one,  but  it  is  by  no  have  been 
means  the  only  possible  and  necessary  one.     The  dif-  the  invest!- 
ferent  methods  that  Archimedes,  Stevinus,  Galileo,  and  fluid  bodies 
the  rest,  pursued,  place  this  idea  clearly  enough  before 
the  mind.     As  a  matter  of  fact,  general  statical  princi- 
ples, might,  with  the  assistance  of  some  very  simple 
propositions  from  the  statics  of  rigid  bodies,  have  been 
reached  in  the  investigation  of  liquids.     Stevinus  cer- 
tainly came  very  near  such  a  discovery.  We  shall  stop 
a  moment  to  discuss  the  question. 

Let  us  imagine  a  liquid,  the  weight  of  which  we  neg-  The  dis- 
lect.     Let  this  liquid  be  enclosed  in  a  vessel  and  sub-  illustration 
jected  to  a  definite  pressure.     A  portion  of  the  liquid,  statement, 
let  us  suppose,  solidifies.     On  the  closed  surface  nor- 
mal forces  act  proportional  to  the  elements  of  the  area, 
and  we  see  without  difficulty  that  their  resultant  will 
always  be  =  0. 

If  we  mark  off  by  a  closed  curve  a.  portion  of  the 
closed  surface,  we  obtain,  on  either  side  of  it,  a  non- 
closed  surface.  All  surfaces  which  are  bounded  by  the 
same  curve  (of  double  curvature)  and  on  which  forces 
act  normally  (in  the  same  sense)  pro- 
portional to  the  elements  of  the  area, 
have  lines  coincident  in  position  for 
the  resultants  of  these  forces. 

Let  us  suppose,  now,  that  a  fluid 
cylinder,  determined  by  any  closed 
plane  curve  as  the  perimeter  of  its  Fig.  79. 

base,  solidifies.  We  may  neglect  the  two  basal  sur- 
faces, perpendicular  to  the  axis.  And  instead  of  the 
cylindrical  surface  the  closed  curve  simply  may  be  con- 
sidered.    From  this  method  follow  quite  analogous 


io8  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

The  dis-      propositions  for  normal  forces  proportional  to  the  ele- 

cussion  and  .  . 

illustration  ments  of  a  plane  curve. 

statement.         If  the  closed  curve  pass  into  a  triangle,  the  con- 
sideration will  shape  itself  thus.   The  resultant  normal 
forces  applied  at  the  middle  points  of  the  sides  of  the 
triangle,  we  represent  in  direction,  sense,  and   magni- 
tude by  straight  lines  (Fig.  80).     The 
lines  mentioned  intersect  at  a  point — 
the  centre  of  the  circle  described  about 
the  triangle.     It  will  further  be  noted, 
Fig.  80.  ^Yi^^  by  the  simple  parallel  displace- 

ment of  the  lines  representing  the  forces  a  triangle  is 
constructive  which  is  similar  and  congruent  to  the 
original  triangle. 
Thededac-        Thence  foUows  this  proposition  : 

tion  of  the  *  ■•  r  i  •    i  ,  • 

triangle  of  Any  three  forces,  which,  actmg  at  a  pomt,  are  pro- 
this  method  portional  and  parallel  in  direction  to  the  sides  of  a  tri- 
angle, and  which  on  meeting  by  parallel  displacement 
form  a  congruent  triangle,  are  in  equilibrium.  We  see 
at  once  that  this  proposition  is  simply  a  different  form 
of  the  principle  of  the  parallelogram  of  forces. 

If  instead  of  a  triangle  we  imagine  a  polygon,  we 
shall  arrive  at  the  familiar  proposition  of  the  polygon 
of  forces. 

We  conceive  now  in  a  heavy  liquid  of  specific  gravity 
K  a  portion  solidified.    On  the  element  a  of  the  closed 
encompassing  surface  there  acts  a  normal  force  axz, 
where  sis  the  distance  of  the  element  from  the  level  of 
the  liquid.     We  know  from  the  outset  the  result. 
Similar de-        If  normal  forces  which  are  determined  by  axzy 
another  im-  where  a  denotes  an  element  of  area  and  z  its  perpen- 
position.     dicular  distance  from  a  given  plane  E,  act  on  a  closed 
surface  inwards,  the  resultant  will  be  V,  x,  in  which  ex- 
pression   F  represents    the   enclosed   volume.      The 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STA  TICS,  109 

resultant  acts  at  the  centre  of  gravity  of  the  volume, 

is  perpendicular  to  the  plane  mentioned,  and  is  directed 

towards  this  plane. 

Under  the  same  conditions  let  a  rigid  curved  surface  The  propo- 
sition here 
be  bounded  by  a  plane  curve,  which  encloses  on  the  deduced,  a 

special  case 

plane  the  area  A.     The  resultant  of  the  forces  acting  of  Greens 

,  Theorem. 

on  the  curved  surface  is  R,  where 

^2  =  {AZxy  +  (  Vxy  —  AZVk^  cos  V, 

in  which  expression  Z  denotes  the  distance  of  the 
centre  of  gravity  of  the  surface  A  from  E^  and  v  the 
normal  angle  of  E  and  A. 

In  the  proposition  of  the  last  paragraph  mathe- 
matically practised  readers  will  have  recognised  a  par- 
ticular case  of  Green's  Theorem,  which  consists  in  the 
reduction  of  surface-integrations  to  volume-integra- 
tions or  vice  versa. 

We  may,  accordingly,  see  into  the  force-system  of  a  The  impii- 

n    •*  *  *i'i.    *  'r  1  J     c  '.  cations  of 

fluid  in  equilibrium,  or,  if  you  please,  see  out  of  it,  sys-  the  view 
tems  of  forces  of  greater  or  less  complexity,  and  thus  *^"* 
reach  by  a  short  path  propositions  a  posteriori.  It  is  a 
mere  accident  that  Stevinus  did  not  light  on  these 
propositions.  The  method  here  pursued  corresponds 
exactly  to  his.  In  this  manner  new  discoveries  can 
still  be  made. 

2 1 .  The  paradoxical  results  that  were  reached  in  Fruitful  re- 
the  investigation  of  liquids,  supplied  a  stimulus  to  fur-  investiga- 
ther  reflection  and  research.     It  should  also  not  be  left  domain, 
unnoticed,  that  the  conception  of  a  physico-mechanical 
continuum  was  first  formed  on  the  occasion  of  the  in- 
vestigation of  liquids.     A  much  freer  and  much  more 
fruitful   mathematical  mode  of  view  was  developed 
thereby,  than  was  possible  through  the  study  even  of 


no  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS 

systems  of  several  solid  bodies.  The  origin,  in  fact, 
of  important  modern  mechanical  ideas,  as  for  instance 
that  of  the  potential,  is  traceable  to  this  source. 


vn. 

THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS  IN  THEIR  APPLICATION  TO 

GASEOUS  BODIES. 

Character  I .  The  Same  views  that  subserve  the  ends  of  science 

of  this  de- 
partment of  in  the  investigation  of  liquids  are  applicable  with  but 

slight  modifications  to  the  investigation  of  gaseous 
bodies.  To  this  extent,  therefore,  the  investigation  of 
gases  does  not  afford  mechanics  any  very  rich  returns. 
Nevertheless,  the  first  steps  that  were  taken  in  this 
province  possess  considerable  significance  from  the 
point  of  view  of  the  progress  of  civilisation  and  high 
import  for  science  generally. 
Theeius-  Although  the  ordinary  man  has  abundant  oppor* 

iu  subject-  t unity,  by  his  experience  of  the  resistance  of  the  air,  by 
"*  "■       the  action  of  the  wind,  and  the  confinement  of  air  in 
bladders,  to  perceive  that  air  is  of  the  nature  of  a  body, 
yet  this  fact  manifests  itself  infrequently,  and  never  in 
the  obvious  and  unmistakable  way  that  it  does  in  the 
case  of  solid  bodies  and  fluids.   It  is  known,  to  be  sure, 
but  is  not  sufficiently  familiar  to  be  prominent  in  popu- 
lar thought.    In  ordinary  life  the  presence  of  the  air  is 
scarcely  ever  thought  of. 
The  effect         Although  the  ancients,  as  we  may  learn  from  the 
disclosures  accouuts  of  Vitruvius,  possessed  instruments  which, 
ince*  ^^^^  like  the  so-called  hydraulic  organs,  were  based  on  the 
condensation  of  air,  although  the  invention  of  the  air- 
gun  is  traced  back  to  Ctesibius,  and  this  instrument 
was  also  known  to  Guericke,  the  notions  which  people 
held  with  regard  to  the  nature  of  the  air  as  late  even 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STA  TICS. 


112  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

as  the  seventeenth  century  were  exceedingly  curious 
and  loose.  We  must  not  be  surprised,  therefore,  at  the 
intellectual  commotion  which  the  first  more  important 
experiments  in  this  direction  evoked.  The  enthusiastic 
description  which  Pascal  gives  of  Boyle's  air-pump  ex- 
periments is  readily  comprehended,  if  we  transport  our- 
selves back  into  the  epoch  of  these  discoveries.  What 
indeed  could  be  more  wonderful  than  the  sudden  dis- 
covery that  a  thing  which  we  do  not  see,  hardly  feel, 
and  take  scarcely  any  notice  of,  constantly  envelopes 
us  on  all  sides,  penetrates  all  things ;  that  it  is  the  most 
important  condition  of  life,  of  combustion,  and  of  gi- 
gantic mechanical  phenomena.  It  was  on  this  occa- 
sion, perhaps,  first  made  manifest  by  a  great  and  strik- 
ing disclosure,  that  physical  science  is  not  restricted 
to  the  investigation  of  palpable  and  grossly  sensible 
processes. 
The  views         2.   In  Galileo's  time   philosophers   explained   the 

entertained     -i  /  ^'  ^i_  ^'  r  ■  j 

on  this  sub- phenomenon  of  suction,  the  action  of  syringes  and 
Ico's time.*  pumps  by  the  so-called  horror  vacui — nature's  abhor- 
rence of  a  vacuum.  Nature  was  thought  to  possess 
the  power  of  preventing  the  formation  of  a  vacuum  by 
laying  hold  of  the  first  adjacent  thing,  whatsoever  it 
was,  and  immediately  filling  up  with  it  any  empty  space 
that  arose.  Apart  from  the  ungrounded  speculative 
element  which  this  view  contains,  it  must  be  conceded, 
that  to  a  certain  extent  it  really  represents  the  phe- 
nomenon. The  person  competent  to  enunciate  it  must 
actually  have  discerned  some  principle  in  the  phenom- 
enon. This  principle,  however,  does  not  fit  all  cases. 
Galileo  is  said  to  have  been  greatly  surprised  at  hearing 
of  a  newly  constructed  pump  accidentally  supplied 
with  a  very  long  suction-pipe  which  was  not  able  to 
raise  water  to  ^  height  of  more  than  eighteen  Italiaa 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS,  113 

elJs.  His  first  thought  was  that  the  horror  vacui  (or  the 
resistenza  del  vacuo)  possessed  a  measurable  power.  The 
greatest  height  to  which  water  could  be  raised  by  suc- 
tion he  called  altezza  limitatissima.  He  sought,  more- 
over, to  determine  directly  the  weight  able  to  draw  out 
of  a  closed  pump-barrel  a  tightly  fitting  piston  resting 
on  the  bottom. 

3.  ToRRiCELLi  hit  upon  the  idea  of  measuring  the  Tomceiii'a 
resistance  to  a  vacuum  by  a  column  of  mercury  mstead 
of  a  column  of  water,  and  he  expected  to  obtain  a  col- 
umn of  about  ^  of  the  length  of  the  water  column. 
His  expectation  was  confirmed  by  the  experiment  per- 
formed in  1643  by  Viviani  in  the  well-known  manner, 
and  which  bears  to-day  the  name  of  the  Torricellian 
experiment.  A  glass  tube  somewhat  over  a  metre  in 
length,  sealed  at  one  end  and  filled  with  mercury,  is 
stopped  at  the  open  end  with  the  finger,  inverted  in  a 
dish  of  mercury,  and  placed  in  a  vertical  position.  Re- 
moving the  finger,  the  column  of  mercury  falls  and  re- 
mains stationary  at  a  height  of  about  76  cm.  By  this 
experiment  it  was  rendered  quite  probable,  that  some 
very  definite  pressure  forced  the  fiuids  into  the  vacuum. 
What  pressure  this  was,  Torricelli  very  soon  divined. 

Galileo  had  endeavored,  some  time  before  this,  to  Galileo's 
determine  the  weight  of  the  air,  by  first  weighing  a  wefi^^air? 
glass  bottle  containing  nothing  but  air  and  then  again 
weighing  the  bottle  after  the  air  had  been  partly  ex- 
pelled by  heat.  It  was  known,  accordingly,  that  the 
air  was  heavy.  But  to  the  majority  of  men  the  horror 
vacui  and  the  weight  of  the  air  were  very  distantly 
connected  notions.  It  is  possible  that  in  Torricelli's 
case  the  two  ideas  came  into  sufficient  proximity  to 
lead  him  to  the  conviction  that  all  phenomena  ascribed 
to  the  horror  vacui  were  explicable  in  a  simple  and 


114  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

Atmospher-  logical  manner  by  the  pressure  exerted  by  the  weight 

discovered  of  a  fluid  columu — a  column  of  air.     Torricelli  discov- 

ceiii.  ered,  therefore,  the  pressure  of  the  atmosphere  ;  he  also 

first  observed  by  means  of  his  column  of  mercury  the 

variations  of  the  pressure  of  the  atmosphere. 

4.  The  news  of  Torricelli's  experiment  was  circu- 
lated in  France  by  Mersenne,  and  came  to  the  knowl- 
edge of  Pascal  in  the  year  1644.  The  accounts  of  the 
theory  of  the  experiment  were  presumably  so  imper- 
fect that  Pascal  found  it  necessary  to  reflect  indepen- 
dently thereon.  iJPesanieur  de  Pair.  Paris,  1663.) 
pascars  ex-       He  repeated  the  experiment  with  mercury  and  with 

perimenis. 

a  tube  of  water,  or  rather  of  red  wine,  40  feet  in  length. 
He  soon  convinced  himself  by  inclining  the  tube  that 
the  space  above  the  column  of  fluid  was  really  empty ; 
and  he  found  himself  obliged  to  defend  this  view  against 
the  violent  attacks  of  his  countrymen.  Pascal  pointed 
out  an  easy  way  of  producing  the  vacuum  which  they 
regarded  as  impossible,  by  the  use  of  a  glass  syringe, 
the  nozzle  of  which  was  closed  with  the  finger  under 
water  and  the  piston  then  drawn  back  without  much 
difficulty.  Pascal  showed,  in  addition,  that  a  curved 
siphon  40  feet  high  filled  with  water  does  not  flow,  but 
can  be  made  to  do  so  by  a  sufficient  inclination  to  the 
perpendicular.  The  same  experiment  was  made  on  a 
smaller  scale  with  mercury.  The  same  siphon  flows 
or  does  not  flow  according  as  it  is  placed  in  an  inclined 
or  a  vertical  position. 

In  a  later  performance,  Pascal  refers  expressly  to 
the  fact  of  the  weight  of  the  atmosphere  and  to  the 
pressure  due  to  this  weight.  He  shows,  that  minute 
animals,  like  flies,  are  able,  without  injury  to  them- 
selves, to  stand  a  high  pressure  in  fluids,  provided  only 
the  pressure  is  equal  on  all  sides  ;  and  he  applies  this 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS, 


"5 


at  once  to  the  case  of  fishes  and  of  animals  that  live  in  The  anai- 
the  air.     Pascal's  chief  merit,  indeed,  is  to  have  estab-  Uquid  and 
lished  a  complete  analogy  between  the  phenomena  con-  ic  pressure, 
ditioned  by  liquid  pressure  (water- pressure)  and  those 
conditioned  by  atmospheric  pressure. 

5.  By  a  series  of  experiments  Pascal  shows  that 
mercury  in  consequence  of  atmospheric  pressure  rises 
into  a  space  containing  no  air  in  the  same  way  that, 
in  consequence  of  water-pressure,  it  rises  into  a  space 
containing  no  water.  If  into  a  deep  ves- 
sel filled  with  water  (Fig.  81)  a  tube  be  c^ 
sunk  at  the  lower  end  of  which  a  bag  of 
mercury  is  tied,  but  so  inserted  that  the 
upper  end  of  the  tube  projects  out  of  the 
water  and  thus  contains  only  air;  then 
the  deeper  the  tube  is  sunk  into  the  water 
the  higher  will  the  mercury,  subjected  Fig.  81. 
to  the  constantly  increasing  pressure  of  the  water,  as- 
cend into  the  tube.  The  experiment  can  also  be  made, 
with  a  siphon-tube,  or  with  a  tube  open  at  its  lower  end. 

Undoubtedly  it  was  the  attentive  consideration  of  The  height 

.of  moaii^ 

this  very  phenomenon  that  led  Pascal  to  the  idea  that  tains  deter- 

mined  by 

the  barometer-column  must  necessarily  stand  lower  atthebarom- 
the  summit  of  a  mountain  than  at  its  base,  and  that 
it  could  accordingly  be  employed  to  determine  the 
height  of  mountains.  He  communicated  this  idea  to 
his  brother-in-law,  Perier,  who  forthwith  successfully 
performed  the  experiment  on  the  summit  of  the  Puy 
de  Ddme.     (Sept.  19,  1648.) 

Pascal  referred  the  phenomena  connected  with  ad-  Adhesion 

plates. 

hesion-plates  to  the  pressure  of  the  atmosphere,  and 
gave  as  an  illustration  of  the  principle  involved  the  re- 
sistance experienced  when  a  large  hat  lying  flat  on  a 
table  is  suddenly  lifted.     The  cleaving  of  wood  to  the 


ii6 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 


A  siphon 
which  acts 
by  water- 
pressare. 


Pascal's 
modifica- 
tion of  the 
Torricelli- 
an experi- 
ment. 


Fig.  8a. 


bottom  of  a  vessel  of  quicksilver  is  a  phenomenon  of 
the  same  kind. 

Pascal  imitated  the  flow  produced  in  a  siphon  by 
atmospheric  pressure,  by  the  use  of  water- pressure. 

The  two  open  unequal  arms  a  and 
^  of  a  three-armed  tube ab c  (Fig. 
82)  are  dipped  into  the  vessels  of 
mercury  e  and  d.  If  the  whole 
arrangement  then  be  immersed  in 
a  deep  vessel  of  water,  yet  so  that 
the  long  open  branch  shall  always 
project  above  the  upper  surface, 
the  mercury  will  gradually  rise  in 
the  branches  a  and  3,  the  columns 
finally  unite,  and  a  Stream  begin  to  flow  from  the  vessel 
d  to  the  vessel  e  through  the  siphon-tube  open  above 
to  the  air. 

PI  J  The  Torricellian  experiment  was  modi- 

fied by  Pascal  in  a  very  ingenious  manner. 
A  tube  of  the  form  abed  (Fig.  83),  of 
double  the  length  of  an  ordinary  barom- 
eter-tube, is  filled  with  mercury.  The 
openings  a  and  b  are  closed  with  the  fin- 
gers and  the  tube  placed  in  a  dish  of 
mercury  with  the  end  a  downwards.  If 
now  a  be  opened,  the  mercury  \vi  ed  will 
all  fall  into  the  expanded  portion  at  r,  and 
the  mercury  xn  ab  will  sink  to  the  height 
of  the  ordinary  barometer-column.  A  vac- 
uum is  produced  at  b  which  presses  the 
finger  closing  the  hole  painfully  inwards. 
If  b  also  be  opened  the  column  \n  ab  will 
sink  completely,  while  the  mercury  in  the  expanded 
portion  r,  being  now  exposed  to  the  pressure  of  the 


y 


Fig.  83. 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS.  117 

atmosphere,  will  rise  in  cd  Xo  the  height  of  the  barom- 
eter-column. Without  an  air-pump  it  was  hardly  pos- 
sible to  combine  the  experiment  and  the  counter- 
experiment  in  a  simpler  and  more  ingenious  manner 
than  Pascal  thus  did. 

6.  With  regard  to  Pascal's  mountain-experiment,  Snppie- 

,  mentary  re- 

we  shall  add  the  following  brief  supplementary  remarks,  marks  on 
Let  bf.  be  the  height  of  the  barometer  at  the  level  of  mountain- 

experiment 

the  sea,  and  let  it  fall,  say,  at  an  elevation  of  m  metres, 
to  kb^y  where  >&  is  a  proper  fraction.  At  a  further  eleva- 
tion of  m  metres,  we  must  expect  to  obtain  the  barom- 
eter-height k  ,kb^^  since  we  here  pass  through  a  stratum 
of  air  the  density  of  which  bears  to  that  of  the  first  the 
proportion  oi  k  \\.  If  we  pass  upwards  to  the  altitude 
h  =  n ,  m  metres,  the  barometer-height  corresponding 
thereto  will  be 

h        kn    hr.T^      log /^— log ^ 

Of.-=:  RT  .  o^ox  n-=. . — or 

\ogk 

The  principle  of  the  method  is,  we  see,  a  very  simple 
one ;  its  difficulty  arises  solely  from  the  multifarious 
collateral  conditions  and  corrections  that  have  to  be 
looked  to. 

7.  The  most  original  and  fruitful  achievements  in  The  expert- 
the  domain  of  aerostatics  we  owe  to  Otto  von  GuE-SSovon 
RiCKE.  His  experiments  appear  to  have  been  suggested 
in  the  main  by  philosophical  speculations.  He  pro- 
ceeded entirely  in  his  own  way ;  for  he  first  heard  of 
the  Torricellian  experiment  from  Valerianus  Magnus 
at  the  Imperial  Diet  of  Ratisbon  in  1654,  where  he  dem- 
onstrated the  experimental  discoveries  made  by  him 
about  1650.  This  statement  is  confirmed  by  his  method 


ii8  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

of  constructing  a  water-barometer  which  was  entirely 
different  from  that  of  Torricelli. 
Thehistori-        Guericke's  book  {Experimenta  nova,   ut  vocantur, 
Guericke'8  Magdeburgica,     Amsterdam.      1672)  makes  us  realise 
the  narrow  views*  men  took  in  his  time.    The  fact  that 
he  was  able  gradually  to  abandon  these  views  and  to 
acquire  broader  ones  by  his  individual  endeavor  speaks 
favorably  for  his  intellectual  powers.     We  perceive 
with  astonishment  how  short  a  space  of  time  separates 
us  from  the  era  of  scientific  barbarism,  and  can  no  lon- 
ger marvel  that  the  barbarism  of  the  social  order  still 
so  oppresses  us. 
Its  specula-       In  the  introduction  to  this  book  and  in  various  other 
ter.  places,  Guericke,  in  the  midst  of  his  experimental  in- 

vestigations, speaks  of  the  various  objections  to  the 
Copernican  system  which  had  been  drawn  from  the 
Bible,  (objections  which  he  seeks  to  invalidate,)  and 
discusses  such  subjects  as  the  locality  of  heaven,  the 
locality  of  hell,  and  the  day  of  judgment.  Philoso- 
phemes  on  empty  space  occupy  a  considerable  portion 
of  the  work. 
Guericke'8  Guericke  regards  the  air  as  the  exhalation  or  odor 
the  air.  of  bodies,  which  we  do  not  perceive  because  we  have 
been  accustomed  to  it  from  childhood.  Air,  to  him, 
is  not  an  element.  He  knows  that  through  the  effects  of 
heat  and  cold  it  changes  its  volume,  and  that  it  is 
compressible  in  Hero's  Ball,  or  Pila  Heronis\  on  the 
basis  of  his  own  experiments  he  gives  its  pressure  at 
20  ells  of  water,  and  expressly  speaks  of  its  weight,  by 
which  flames  are  forced  upwards. 

8.  To  produce  a  vacuum,  Guericke  first  employed 
a  wooden  cask  filled  with  water.  The  pump  of  a  fire- 
engine  was  fastened  to  its  lower  end.  The  water,  it 
was  thought,  in  following  the  piston  and  the  action  of 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS. 


ricks'i  Flnl  EipariuwliU.    ifixptrim.  UapUi.y 


I20  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

His  at-       gravity,  would  fall  and  be  pumped  out.     Guericke  ex- 

tcinpts  to 

produce  a   pectcd  that  empty  space  would  remain.  The  fastenmgs 

vacuum.  .  . 

of  the  pump  repeatedly  proved  to  be  too  weak,  since  m 
consequence  of  the  atmospheric  pressure  that  weighed 
on  the  piston  considerable  force  had  to  be  applied  to 
move  it.  On  strengthening  the  fastenings  three  power- 
ful men  finally  accomplished  the  exhaustion.  But, 
meantime  the  air  poured  in  through  the  joints  of  the 
cask  with  a  loud  blast,  and  no  vacuum  was  obtained. 
In  a  subsequent  experiment  the  small  cask  from  which 
the  water  was  to  be  exhausted  was  immersed  in  a  larger 
one,  likewise  filled  with  water.  But  in  this  case,  too,  the 
water  gradually  forced  its  way  into  the  smaller  cask. 
His  6nai  Wood  having  proved  in  this  way  to  be  an  unsuit- 

SQCCOSS  V*     *  ^ 

able  material  for  the  purpose,  and  Guericke  having  re- 
marked in  the  last  experiment  indications  of  success, 
the  philosopher  now  took  a  large  hollow  sphere  of 
copper  and  ventured  to  exhaust  the  air  directly.  At 
the  start  the  exhaustion  was  successfully  and  easily 
conducted.  But  after  a  few  strokes  of  the  piston,  the 
pumping  became  so  difficult  that  four  stalwart  men 
{viri  quadrati),  putting  forth  their  utmost  efforts,  could 
hardly  budge  the  piston.  And  when  the  exhaustion 
had  gone  still  further,  the  sphere  suddenly  collapsed, 
with  a  violent  report.  Finally  by  the  aid  of  a  copper 
vessel  of  perfect  spherical  form,  the  production  of  the 
vacuum  was  successfully  accomplished.  Guericke  de- 
scribes the  great  force  with  which  the  air  rushed  in  on 
the  opening  of  the  cock. 

9.  After  these  experiments  Guericke  constructed 
an  independent  air-pump.  A  great  glass  globular  re- 
ceiver was  mounted  and  closed  by  a  large  detachable 
tap  in  which  was  a  stop-cock.  Through  this  opening 
the  objects  to  be  subjected  to  experiment  were  placed 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS.  iii 

in  the  receiver.     To  secure  more  perfect  closure  the  c 
receiver  was  made  to  stand,  with  its  stop-cock  under 
water,  on  a  tripod,  beneath  which  the  pump  proper  was 


Cuaricte'i  Air-pump.    (Eiftrim.  Magdii.) 

placed.  Subsequently,  separate  receivers,  connected 
with  the  exhausted  sphere,  were  also  employed  in  the 
experiments. 


122  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

ThecarioM  The  phenomena  which  Guericke  observed  with  this 
observed  by  apparatus  are  manifold  and  various.  The  noise  which 
the  air-  Water  in  a  vacuum  makes  on  striking  the  sides  of  the 
glass  receiver,  the  violent  rush  of  air  and  water  into 
exhausted  vessels  suddenly  opened,  the  escape  on  ex- 
haustion of  gases  absorbed  in  liquids,  the  liberation  of 
their  fragrance,  as  Guericke  expresses  it,  were  imme- 
diately remarked.  A  lighted  candle  is  extinguished 
on  exhaustion,  because,  as  Guericke  conjectures,  it 
derives  its  nourishment  from  the  air.  Combustion,  as 
his  striking  remark  is,  is  not  an  annihilation,  but  a 
transformation  of  the  air. 

A  bell  does  not  ring  in  a  vacuum.  Birds  die  in  it. 
Many  fishes  swell  up,  and  finally  burst.  A  grape  is  kept 
fresh  in  vacuo  for  over  half  a  year. 

By  connecting  with  an  exhausted  cylinder  a  long 
tube  dipped  in  water,  a  water- barometer  is  constructed. 
The  column  raised  is  19-20  ells  high;  and  Von  Guericke 
explained  all  the  effects  that  had  been  ascribed  to  the 
horror  vacui  by  the  principle  of  atmospheric  pressure. 
An  important  experiment  consisted  in  the  weighing 
of  a  receiver,  first  when  filled  with  air  and  then  when 
exhausted.  The  weight  of  the  air  was  found  to  vary 
with  the  circumstances ;  namely,  with  the  temperature 
and  the  height  of  the  barometer.  According  to  Gue- 
ricke a  definite  ratio  of  weight  between  air  and  water 
does  not  exist. 
The  experi-       But  the  deepest  impression  on  the  contemporary 

mentsrelat- 

ing  to  at-     world  was  made  by  the  experiments  relating  to  atmos- 

mospheric 

pressure,  pheric  pressure.  An  exhausted  sphere  formed  of  two 
hemispheres  tightly  adjusted  to  one  another  was  rent 
asunder  with  a  violent  report  only  by  the  traction  of 
sixteen  horses.    The  same  sphere  was  suspended  from 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS.  123 

a  beam,  and  a  heavily  laden  scale-pan  was  attached  to 
the  lower  half. 

The  cylinder  of  a  large  pump  is  closed  by  a  piston. 
To  the  piston  a  rope  is  tied  which  leads  over  a  pulley 
and  is  divided  into  numerous  branches  on  which  a 
great  number  of  men  pull.  The  moment  the  cylinder  is 
connected  with  an  exhausted  receiver,  the  men  at  the 
ropes  are  thrown  to  the  ground.  In  a  similar  manner 
a  huge  weight  is  lifted. 

Guericke  mentions  the  compressed-air  gun  as  some-  Guericke's 
thing  already  known,  and  constructs  independently  an 
instrument  that  might  appropriately  be  called  a  rari- 
fied-air  gun.  A  bullet  is  driven  by  the  external  atmos- 
pheric pressure  through  a  suddenly  exhausted  tube, 
forces  aside  at  the  end  of  the  tube  a  leather  valve  which 
closes  it,  and  then  continues  its  flight  with  a  consider- 
able velocity. 

Closed  vessels  carried  to  the  summit  of  a  mountain 
and  opened,  blow  out  air ;  carried  down  again  in  the 
same  manner,  they  suck  in  air.  From  these  and  other 
experiments  Guericke  discovers  that  the  air  is  elastic. 

10.  The  investigations  of  Guericke  were  continued  The  invead- 
by  an  Englishman,  Robert  Boyle.*  The  new  experi-  Robert 
ments  which  Boyle  had  to  supply  were  few.  He  ob- 
serves the  propagation  of  light  in  a  vacuum  and  the 
action  of  a  magnet  through  it ;  lights  tinder  by  means 
of  a  burning  glass ;  brings  the  barometer  under  the  re- 
ceiver of  the  air-pump,  and  was  the  first  to  construct 
a  balance-manometer  ['*the  statical  manometer"]. 
The  ebullition  of  heated  fluids  and  the  freezing  of  water 
on  exhaustion  were  first  observed  by  him. 

Of  the  air-pump  experiments  common  at  the  present 
day  may  also  be  mentioned  that  with  falling  bodies, 

*  And  published  by  him  in  1660,  before  the  work  of  Von  Guericke.— TVaiM. 


124 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 


vacnam. 


Quantita- 
tive data. 


The  fall  of  which  confirms  in  a  simple  manner  the  view  of  Galileo 
that  when  the  resistance  of  the  air  has  been  eliminated 
light  and  heavy  bodies  both  fall  with  the  same  velo- 
city. In  an  exhausted  glass  tube  a  leaden  bullet  and  a 
piece  of  paper  are  placed.  Putting  the  tube  in  a  ver- 
tical position  and  quickly  turning  it  about  a  horizontal 
axis  through  an  angle  of  i8o^,  both  bodies  will  be  seen 
to  arrive  simultaneously  at  the  bottom  of  the  tube. 

Of  the  quantitative  data  we  will  mention  the  fol- 
lowing. The  atmospheric  pressure  that  supports  a 
column  of  mercury  of  76  cm.  is  easily  calculated  from 
the  specific  gravity  13*60  of  mercury  to  be  1-0336  kg. 
to  I  sq.cm.  The  weight  of  1000  cu.cm.  of  pure,  dry 
air  at  0°  C.  and  760  mm.  of  pressure  at  Paris  at  an  ele- 
vation of  6  metres  will  be  found  to  be  i  -293  grams, 
and  the  corresponding  specific  gravity,  referred  to 
water,  to  be  0-001293. 

Thediscov-        1 1.  Guericke  knew  of  only  ^«^  kind  of  air.     We 

ery  of  other 

gaseous      may  imagine  therefore  the  excitement  it  created  when 

'  in  1755  Black  discovered  carbonic  acid  gas  (fixed  air) 

and  Cavendish  in  1766  hydrogen  (inflammable  air), 

discoveries  which  were  soon  followed  by  other  similar 

ones.     The  dissimilar 


physical  properties  of 
gases  are  very  strik- 
ing. Faraday  has  il- 
lustrated their  great 
inequality  ,  of  weight 
by  a  beautiful  lecture- 
experiment.  If  from 
a  balance  in  equilib- 
rium, we  suspend  (Fig.  84)  two  beakers  A^  B,  the  one 
in  an  upright  position  and  the  other  with  its  opening 
downwards,  we  may  pour  heavy  carbonic  acid  gas  from 


Fig.  84. 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS.  125 

above  into  the  one  and  light  hydrogen  from  beneath 
into  the  other.  In  both  instances  the  balance  turns  in 
the  direction  of  the  arrow.  To-day,  as  we  know,  the 
decanting  of  gases  can  be  made  directly  visible  by  the 
optical  method  of  Foucault  and  Toeppler. 

12.  Soon  after  Torricelli's  discovery,  attempts  were  The  merco- 
made  to  employ  practically  the  vacuum  thus  produced,  pump. 
The  so-called  mercurial  air-pumps  were  tried.    But  no 

such  instrument  was  successful  until  the  present  cen- 
tury. The  mercurial  air-pumps  now  in  common  use 
are  really  barometers  of  which  the  extremities  are  sup- 
plied with  large  expansions  and  so  connected  that  their 
difference  of  level  may  be  easily  varied.  The  mercury 
takes  the  place  of  the  pistop  of  the  ordinary  air-pump. 

13.  The  expansive  force  of  the  air,  a  property  ob- Boyle's  law. 
served  by  Guericke,  was  more  accurately  investigated 

by  Boyle,  and,  later,  by  Mariotte.  The  law  which 
both  found  is  as  follows.  If  Fbe  called  the  volume  of 
a  given  quantity  of  air  and  P  its  pressure  on  unit  area 
of  the  containing  vessel,  then  the  product  V,  P  is 
always  =  a  constant  quantity.  If  the  volume  of  the 
enclosed  air  be  reduced  one-half,  the  air  will  exert 
double  the  pressure  on  unit  of  area ;  if  the  volume  of 
the  enclosed  quantity  be  doubled,  the  pressure  will 
sink  to  one-half ;  and  so  on.  It  is  quite  correct — as  a 
number  of  English  writers  have  maintained  in  recent 
times — that  Boyle  and  not  Mariotte  is  to  be  regarded 
as  the  discoverer  of  the  law  that  usually  goes  by 
Mariotte's  name.  Not  only  is  this  true,  but  it  must 
also  be  added  that  Boyle  knew  that  the  law  did  not 
hold  exactly,  whereas  this  fact  appears  to  have  escaped 
Mariotte. 

The  method  pursued  by  Mariotte  in  the  ascertain- 
ment of  the  law  was  very  simple.     He  partially  filled 


126 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 


His  appa 
ratus. 


Mariotte's  Torricellian  tubes  with  mercury,  measured  the  volume 

expert- 

ments.  of  the  air  remaining,  and  then  performed  the  Torricel- 
lian experiment.  The  new  volume  of 
air  was  thus  obtained,  and  by  subtract- 
ing the  height  of  the  column  of  mer- 
cury from  the  barometer-height,  also 
the  new  pressure  to  which  the  same 
quantity  of  air  was  now  subjected. 
To  condense  the  air  Mariotte  em- 
^^  ployed    a    siphon-tube  with    vertical 

Fig.  85.  arms.     The  smaller  arm  in  which  the 

air  was  contained  was  sealed  at  the 
upper  end  j  the  longer,  into  which  the 
mercury  was  poured,  was  open  at  the 
y,  upper  end.  The  volume  of  the  air 
was  read  off  on  the  graduated  tube, 
and  to  the  difference  of  level  of  the 
mercury  in  the  two  arms  the  barometer- 
height  was  added.  At  the  present  day 
both  sets  of  experiments  are  performed 
in  the  simplest  manner  by  fastening  a 
cylindrical  glass  tube  (Fig.  86)  rr, 
closed  at  the  top,  to  a  vertical  scale 
and  connecting  it  by  a  caoutchouc 
tube  k  k  with  a  second  open  glass  tube 
r*  r\  which  is  movable  up  and  down 
the  scale.  If  the  tubes  be  partly  filled 
with  mercury,  any  difference  of  level 
whatsoever  of  the  two  surfaces  of  mer- 
Fig.  86.  cury  may  be  produced  by  displacing 

r*  r\  and  the  corresponding  variations  of  volume  of  the 
air  enclosed  in  r  r  observed. 

It  struck  Mariotte  on  the  occasion  of  his  investiga- 
tions that  any  small  quantity  of  air  cut  off  completely 


?\ 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  STATICS.  127 

from  the  rest  of  the  atmosphere  and   therefore   notTheexpan- 

sive  force  of 

directly  affected  by  the  latter*s  weight,  also  supported  isolated 

.  .  portions  of 

the  barometer- colum n  :  as  where,  to  give  an  instance,  theatmos- 

.        ,     phere. 

the  open  arm  of  a  barometer- tube  is  closed.  The  simple 
explanation  of  this  phenomenon,  which,  of  course, 
Mariotte  immediately  found,  is  this,  that  the  air  before 
enclosure  must  have  been  compressed  to  a  point  at 
which  its  tension  balanced  the  gravitational  pressure 
of  the  atmosphere  ;  that  is  to  say,  to  a  poini  at  which 
it  exerted  an  equivalent  elastic  pressure. 

We  shall  not  enter  here  into  the  details  of  the  ar- 
rangement and  use  of  air-pumps,  which  are  readily 
understood  from  the  law  of  Boyle  and  Mariotte. 

14.  It  simply  remains  for  us  to  remark,  that  the  dis- 
coveries of  aerostatics  furnished  so  much  that  was  new 
and  wonderful  that  a  valuable  intellectual  stimulus  pro- 
ceeded from  the  science. 


CHAPTER  II. 


Dvni 
whol 


kamics 
lolly  a 
modern 
science. 


THE  DEVELOPMENT  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES  OF 

DYNAMICS. 


I. 


Galileo's  achievements. 

I.  We  now  pass  to  the  discussion  of  the  funda- 
mental principles  of  dynamics.  This  is  entirely  a  mod- 
ern science.  The  mechanical  speculations  of  the  an- 
cients, particularly  of  the  Greeks,  related  wholly  to 
statics.  Dynamics  was  founded  by  Galileo.  We  shall 
readily  recognise  the  correctness  of  this  assertion  if  we 
but  consider  a  moment  a  few  propositions  held  by  the 
Aristotelians  of  Galileo's  time.  To  explain  the  descent 
of  heavy  bodies  and  the  rising  of  light  bodies,  (in  li- 
quids for  instance, )  it  was  assumed  that  every  thing  and 
object  sought  its  place :  the  place  of  heavy  bodies  was 
below,  the  place  of  light  bodies  was  above.  Motions 
were  divided  into  natural  motions,  as  that  of  descent, 
and  violent  motions,  as,  for  example,  that  of  a  pro- 
jectile. From  some  few  superficial  experiments  and 
observations,  philosophers  had  concluded  that  heavy 
bodies  fall  more  quickly  and  lighter  bodies  more  slowly, 
or,  more  precisely,  that  bodies  of  greater  weight  fall 
more  quickly  and  those  of  less  weight  more  slowly.  It 
is  sufficiently  obvious  from  this  that  the  dynamical 
knowledge  of  the  ancients,  particularly  of  the  Greeks, 
was  very  insignificant,  and  that  it  was  left  to  modern 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OP  DYNAMICS.  129 

times  to  lay  the  true  foundations  of  this  department  of 

inquiry. 


2.   The  treatise  Discorsi  e  dimostrazioni  maUmatiche, 
in  which  Galileo  communicated  to  the  world  the  &rst 


I30  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

Galileo's     dynamical  investigation  of  the  laws  of  falling  bodies, 
tionof  the  appeared  in  1638.    The  modern  spirit  that  Galileo  dis- 

laws  of  fall- 

ing  bodies,  covers  is  evidenced  here,  at  the  very  outset,  by  the  fact 
that  he  does  not  ask  why  heavy  bodies  fall,  but  pro- 
pounds the  question,  Hoiv  do  heavy  bodies  fall  ?  in 
agreement  with  what  law  do  freely  falling  bodies  move? 
The  method  he  employs  to  ascertain  this  law  is  this. 
He  makes  certain  assumptions.  He  does  not,  however, 
like  Aristotle,  rest  there,  but  endeavors  to  ascertain  by 
trial  whether  they  are  correct  or  not. 

His  first.  The  first  theory  on  which  he  lights  is  the  following. 

theory.  *  It  seems  in  his  eyes  plausible  that  a  freely  falling  body, 
inasmuch  as  it  is  plain  that  its  velocity  is  constantly 
on  the  increase,  so  moves  that  its  velocity  is  double 
after  traversing  double  the  distance,  and  triple  after 
traversing  triple  the  distance  ;  in  short,  that  the  veloci- 
ties acquired  in  the  descent  increase  proportionally 
to  the  distances  descended  through.  Before  he  pro- 
ceeds to  test  experimentally  this  hypothesis,  he  reasons 
on  it  logically,  implicates  himself,  however,  in  so  doing, 
in  a  fallacy.  He  says,  if  a  body  has  acquired  a  certain 
velocity  in  the  first  distance  descended  through,  double 
the  velocity  in  double  such  distance  descended  through, 
and  so  on  ;  that  is  to  say,  if  the  velocity  in  the  second 
instance  is  double  what  it  is  in  the  first,  then  the  double 
distance  will  be  traversed  in  the  same  time  as  the  origi- 
nal simple  distance.  If,  accordingly,  in  the  case  of 
the  double  distance  we  conceive  the  first  half  trav- 
ersed, no  time  will,  it  would  seem,  fall  to  the  account 
of  the  second  half.  The  motion  of  a  falling  body  ap- 
pears, therefore,  to  take  place  instantaneously ;  which 
not  only  contradicts  the  hypothesis  but  also  ocular  evi- 
dence. We  shall  revert  to  this  peculiar  fallacy  of 
Galileo's  later  on. 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  DYNAMICS, 


131 


3.  After  Galileo  fancied  he  had  discovered  this  as- His  second, 
sumption  to  be  untenable,  he  made  a  second  one,  ac-  sumption. 
cording  to  which  the  velocity  acquired  is  proportional 
to  the  time  of  the  descent.  That  is,  if  a  body  fall  once, 
and  then  fall  again  during  twice  as  long  an  interval  of 
time  as  it  first  fell,  it  will  attain  in  the  second  instance 
double  the  velocity  it  acquired  in  the  first.  He  found 
no  self-contradiction  in  this  theory,  and  he  accordingly 
proceeded  to  investigate  by  experiment  whether  the 
assumption  accorded  with  observed  facts.  It  was  dif- 
ficult to  prove  by  any  direct  means  that  the  velocity 
acquired  was  proportional  to  the  time  of  descent.  It 
was  easier,  however,  to  investigate  by  what  law  the 
distance  increased  with  the  time ;  and  he  consequently 
deduced  from  his  assumption  the  relation  that  obtained 
between  the  distance  and  the  time,  and  tested  this  by 
experiment.     The  deduction  ^ 

is  simple,  distinct,  and  per-  ^^ 

fectly    correct.      He    draws 
(Fig.  87)  a  straight  line,  and 
on  it  cuts  off  successive  por-  Ca- 
tions that  represent  to  him  Fig.  87. 
the  times  elapsed.     At  the  extremities  of  these  por- 
tions he  erects  perpendiculars  (ordinates),  and  these 
represent  the  velocities  acquired.     Any  portion  OGoi 
the  line   OA  denotes,  therefore,  the  time  of  descent 
elapsed,  and  the  corresponding  perpendicular  GIf  the 
velocity  acquired  in  such  time. 

If,  now,  we  fix  our  attention  on  the  progress  of  the 
velocities,  we  shall  observe  with  Galileo  the  following 
fact :  namely,  that  at  the  instant  C,  at  which  one-half 
OC  of  the  time  of  descent  OA  has  elapsed,  the  velocity 
CD  is  also  one-half  of  the  final  velocity  AB. 

If  now  we  examine  two  instants  of  time,  £  and  G, 


Discassion 
and  eluci- 
dation of 
the  true 
theory. 


132  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

Uniformly  equally  distant  in  opposite  directions  from  the  instant 

accelerated 

motion.  C,  we  shall  observe  that  the  velocity  HG  exceeds  the 
mean  velocity  CD  by  the  same  amount  that  EF  falls 
short  of  it.  For  every  instant  antecedent  to  C  there 
exists  a  corresponding  one  equally  distant  from  it  sub- 
sequent to  C,  Whatever  loss,  therefore,  as  compared 
with  uniform  motion  with  half  the  final  velocity,  is  suf- 
fered in  the  first  half  of  the  motion,  such  loss  is  made 
up  in  the  second  half.  The  distance  fallen  through  we 
may  consequently  regard  as  having  been  uniformly  de- 
scribed with  half  the  final  velocity.  If,  accordingly, 
we  make  the  final  velocity  v  proportional  to  the  time 
of  descent  /,  we  shall  obtain  7*  =  gt,  where  g  denotes 
the  final  velocity  acquired  in  unit  of  time — the  so-called 
acceleration.  The  space  s  descended  through  is  there- 
fore given  by  the  equation  s  =  (^//2)  /  or  s  =zg/^/2. 
Motion  of  this  sort,  in  which,  agreeably  to  the  assump- 
tion, equal  velocities  constantly  accrue  in  equal  inter- 
vals of  time,  we  call  uniformly  accelerated  motion. 
Table  of  the  If  we  collect  the  times  of  descent,  the  final  veloci- 
iocities.and  ties,  and  the  distances  traversed,  we  shall  obtain  the 

distances  of  ^    , ,  ,  , 

descent,      followmg  table : 


1. 

1^- 

1  X  1  .  f 

2. 

2g. 

2X2.'^- 

3. 

3^. 

3  X  3  .  1 

4. 

4^. 

4X4.  f 

• 
• 
• 

• 
• 
• 

• 
• 
« 

fg- 

'X'l 

THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  DYNAMICS.  133 

4.   The. relation  obtaining  between  /  and  s  admits Experimen- 

t&l  verifies* 

of  experimental  proof ;  and  this  Galileo  accomplished  tion  of  the 
in  the  manner  which  we  shall  now  describe. 

We  must  first  remark  that  no  part  of  the  knowledge 
and  ideas  on  this  subject  with  which  we  are  now  so 
familiar,  existed  in  Galileo's  time^  but  that  Galileo  had 
to  create  these  ideas  and  means  for  us.  Accordingly, 
it  was  impossible  for  him  to  proceed  as  we  should  do 
to-day,  and  he  was  obliged,  therefore,  to  pursue  a  dif- 
ferent method.  He  first  sought  to  retard  the  motion 
of  descent,  that  it  might  be  more  accurately  observed. 
He  made  observations  on  balls,  which  he  caused  to 
roll  down  inclined  planes  (grooves);  assuming  that  only 
the  velocity  of  the  motion  would  be  lessened  here,  but 
that  the  form  of  the  law  of  desert  would  remain  un- 
modified. If,  beginning  from  the  upper  extremity,  the  Jhe  arti- 
fices em- 
distances  I,  4,  9,  16  ...  be  notched  off  on  the  groove,  ployed. 

the  respective  times  of  descent  will  be  representable, 
it  was  assumed,  by  the  numbers  i,  2,  3,  4  .  .  .  ;  a  result 
which  was,  be  it  added,  confirmed.  The  observation  of 
the  times  involved,  Galileo  accomplished  in  a  very  in- 
genious manner.  There  were  no  clocks  of  the  modern 
kind  in  his  day :  such  were  first  rendered  possible  by 
the  dynamical  knowledge  of  which  Galileo  laid  the 
foundations.  The  mechanical  clocks  which  were  used 
were  very  inaccurate,  and  were  available  only  for  the 
measurement  of  great  spaces  of  time.  Moreover,  it 
was  chiefly  water-clocks  and  sand-glasses  that  were  in 
use — in  the  form  in  which  they  had  been  handed  down 
from  the  ancients.  Galileo,  now,  constructed  a  very 
simple  clock  of  this  kind,  which  he  especially  adjusted 
to  the  measurement  of  small  spaces  of  time  ;  a  thing 
not  customary  in  those  days.  It  consisted  of  a  vessel  of 
water  of  very  large  transverse  dimensions,  having  in 


134  TW:^  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

Galileo's     the  bottom  a  minute  orifice  which  was  closed  with  the 

clock. 

finger.  As  soon  as  the  ball  began  to  roll  down  the  in- 
clined plane  Galileo  removed  his  finger  and  allowed  the 
water  to  flow  out  on  a  balance  ;  when  the  ball  had  ar- 
rived at  the  terminus  of  its  path  he  closed  the  orifice. 
As  the  pressure-height  of  the  fluid  did  not,  owing  to 
the  great  transverse  dimensions  of  the  vessel,  percept- 
ibly change,  the  weights  of  the  water  discharged  from 
the  orifice  were  proportional  to  the  times.  It  was  in 
this  way  actually  shown  that  the  times  increased  simply, 
while  the  spaces  fallen  through  increased  quadratically. 
The  inference  from  Galileo's  assumption  was  thus  con- 
firmed by  experiment,  and  with  it  the  assumption  itself. 
The  reia-  c.  To  form  some  notion  of  the  relation  which  sub- 

tion  of  mo-      , 

tion  on  an   sists  between  motiqp  on  an  inclined  plane  and  that  of 

inclined  . 

plane  to  free  descent,  Galileo  made  the  assumption,  that  a  body 
descent,  which  falls  through  the  height  of  an  inclined  plane 
attains  the  same  final  velocity  as  a  body  which  falls 
through  its  length.  This  is  an  assumption  that  will 
strike  us  as  rather  a  bold  one ;  but  in  the  manner  in 
which  it  was  enunciated  and  employed  by  Galileo,  it  is 
quite  natural.  We  shall  endeavor  to  explain  the  way  by 
which  he  was  led  to  it.  He  says :  If  a  body  fall  freely 
downwards,  its  velocity  increases  proportionally  to  the 
time.  When,  then,  the  body  has  arrived  at  a  point  be- 
low, let  us  imagine  its  velocity  reversed  and  directed 
upwards  ;  the  body  then,  it  is  clear,  will  rise.  We  make 
the  observation  that  its  motion  in  this  case  is  a  reflection, 
so  to  speak,  of  its  motion  in  the  first  case.  As  then  its 
velocity  increased  proportionally  to  the  time  of  descent, 
it  will  now,  conversely,  diminish  in  that  proportion. 
When  the  body  has  continued  to  rise  for  as  long  a 
time  as  it  descended,  and  has  reached  the  height  from 
which  it  originally  fell,  its  velocity  will  be  reduced  to 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  DYNAMICS,  135 

zero.  We  perceive,  therefore,  that  a  body  will  rise,  justifica- 
in  virtue  of  the  velocity  acquired  in  its  descent,  just  as  assumption 
high  as  it  has  fallen.  If,  accordingly,  a  body  falling  final  veioc- 
down  an  inclined  plane  could  acquire  a  velocity  which  motions  are 
would  enable  it,  when  placed  on  a  differently  inclined 
plane,  to  rise  higher  than  the  point  from  which  it  had 
fallen,  we  should  be  able  to  effect  the  elevation  of 
bodies  by  gravity  alone.  There  is  contained,  accord- 
ingly, in  this  assumption,  that  the  velocity  acquired  by 
a  body  in  descent  depends  solely  on  the  vertical  height 
fallen  through  and  is  independent  of  the  inclination  of 
the  path,  nothing  more  than  the  uncontradictory  ap- 
prehension and  recognition  of  the/ar/  that  heavy  bodies 
do  not  possess  the  tendency  to  rise,  but  only  the  ten- 
dency to  fall.  If  we  should  assume  that  a  body  fall- 
ing down  the  length  of  an  inclined  plane  in  some  way 
or  other  attained  a  greater  velocity  than  a  body  that 
fell  through  its  height,  we  should  only  have  to  let  the 
body  pass  with  the  acquired  velocity  to  another  in- 
clined or  vertical  plane  to  make  it  rise  to  a  greater  ver- 
tical height  than  it  had  fallen  from.  And  if  the  velo- 
city attained  on  the  inclined  plane  were  less,  we  should 
only  have  to  reverse  the  process  to  obtain  the  same  re- 
sult. In  both  instances  a  heavy  body  could,  by  an  ap- 
propriate arrangement  of  inclined  planes,  be  forced 
continually  upwards  solely  by  its  own  weight — a  state 
of  things  which  wholly  contradicts  our  instinctive 
knowledge  of  the  nature  of  heavy  bodies. 

6.  Galileo,  in  this  case,  again,  did  not  stop  with 
the  mere  philosophical  and  logical  discussion  of  his 
assumption,  but  tested  it  by  comparison  with  expe- 
rience. 

He  took  a  simple  filar  pendulum  (Fig.  88)  with  a 
heavy  ball  attached.     Lifting   the   pendulum,  while 


136 


THE  SC/E^/CE  OF  MECHANICS, 


Galileo's     elongated  its  full  length,  to  the  level  of  a  given  altitude, 

tai  verifica-  and  then  letting  it  fall,  it  ascended  to  the  same  level 

assumption  on  the  Opposite  side.     If  it  does  not  do  so  exactly ^ 

Galileo  said,  the  resistance  of  the  air  must  be  the  cause 

of  the  deficit.     This  is  inferrible  from  the  fact  that  the 

deficiency  is  greater  in  the  case  of  a  cork  ball  than  it  is 


Effected  by  in  the  case  of  a  heavy  metal  one.  However,  this  neg- 
fmpeding  lected,  the  body  ascends  to  the  same  altitude  on  the 
of  apendu-  Opposite  side.  Now  it  is  permissible  to  regard  the  mo- 
nm  s  nng.  ^.^^  ^^  ^  pendulum  in  the  arc  of  a  circle  as  a  motion 

of  descent  along  a  series  of  inclined  planes  of  different 
inclinations.  This  seen,  we  can,  with  Galileo,  easily 
cause  the  body  to  rise  on  a  different  arc — on  a  different 
series  of  inclined  planes.  This  we  accomplish  by  driv- 
ing in  at  one  side  of  the  thread,  as  it  vertically  hangs, 
a  nail  /  or  ^,  which  will  prevent  any  given  portion  of 
the  thread  from  taking  part  in  the  second  half  of  the 
motion.  The  moment  the  thread  arrives  at  the  line  of 
equilibrium  and  strikes  the  nail,  the  ball,  which  has 
fallen  through  ba,  will  begin  to  ascend  by  a  different 
series  of  inclined  planes,  and  describe  the  arc  am  ox  an. 
Now  if  the  inclination  of  the  planes  had  any  influence 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  D  YNAMICS,  137 

on  the  velocity  of  descent,  the  body  could  not  rise  to 
the  same  horizontal  level  from  which  it  had  fallen. 
But  it  does.  By  driving  the  nail  sufficiently  low  down, 
we  may  shorten  the  pendulum  for  half  of  an  oscillation 
as  much  as  we  please ;  the  phenomenon,  however,  al- 
ways remains  the  same.  If  the  nail  h  be  driven  so  low 
down  that  the  remainder  of  the  string  cannot  reach  to 
the  plane  E^  the  ball  will  turn  completely  over  and 
wind  the  thread  round  the  nail ;  because  when  it  has 
attained  the  greatest  height  it  can  reach  it  still  has  a 
residual  velocity  left, 

7.   If  we  assume  thus,  that  the  same  final  velocity  is  The  as- 
sumption 

attained  on  an  inclined  plane  whether  the  body  fall  leads  to  the 

...    »*w  of  rela- 

through  the  height  or  the  length  of  the  plane, — in  which  tive  accei- 
assumption  nothing  more  is  contained  than  that  a  body  sought. 
rises  by  virtue  of  the  velocity  it  has  acquired  in  falling 
just  as  high  as  it  has  fallen, — we  shall  easily  arrive, 
with  Galileo,  at  the  perception  that  the  times  of  the  de- 
scent along  the  height  and  the  length  of  an  inclined 
plane  are  in  the  simple  proportion  of  the  height  and 
the  length  ;  or,  what  is  the  same,  that  the  accelerations 
are  inversely  proportional  to  the  times  of  descent. 
The  acceleration  along  the  height  will  consequently 
bear  to  the  acceleration  along  ^^ 
the  length  the  proportion  of  the 
length  to  the  height.  Let  AB 
(Fig.  89)  be  the  height  and  AC^ 
the  length  of  the  inclined  plane.  Fig.  89. 

Both  will  be  descended  through  in  uniformly  accel- 
erated motion  in  the  times  /  and  /^  with  the  final  ve- 
locity V,     Therefore, 


138 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 


If  the  accelerations  along  the  height  and  the  length  be 
called  respectively  g  and  g^y  we  also  have 

v  =  gi  and  v^=^  g.  /, ,  whence  -^-  =  -  =  -  --  =  sin  a. 

^    ^  g        t^       AC 

In  this  way  we  are  able  to  deduce  from  the  accel- 
eration on  an  inclined  plane  the  acceleration  of  free 
descent. 
A  corollary        From  this  proposition  Galileo  deduces  several  cor- 

of  the  pre-  .  *       '^ 

ceding  law.  ollaries,  some  of  which  have  passed  into  our  elementary 
text-books.  The  accelerations  along  the  height  and 
length  are  in  the  inverse  proportion  of  the  height  and 
length.  If  now  we  cause  one  body  to  fall  along  the 
length  of  an  inclined  plane  and  simultaneously  another 
to  fall  freely  along  its  height,  and  ask  what  the  dis- 
tances are  that  are  traversed  by  the  two  in  equal  inter- 
vals of  time,  the  solution  of  the  problem  will  be  readily 
found  (Fig.  90)  by  simply  letting  fall  from  B  a  perpen- 
dicular on  the  length.  The  part  AD,  thus  cut  off,  will 
be  the  distance  traversed  by  the  one  body  on  the  in- 
clined plane,  while  the  second  body  is  freely  falling 

through  the  height  of  the  plane. 

A 


Fig.  90.  Fig.  91. 

Relative  If  we  describe  (Fig.  91)  a  circle  on  AB  as  diame- 

scription  of  ter,  the  circle  will  pass  through  Z>,  because  Z>  is  a 
anddiame-  right  angle.  It  wiU  be  seen  thus,  that  we  can  imagine 
cies.  any  number  of  inclined  planes,  AE,  AF,  of  any  degree 

of  inclination,  passing  through  A,  and  that  in  every 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  D  YNAMICS, 


139 


circles. 


case  the  chords  A  Gy  AH  drawn  in  this  circle  from  the 
upper  extremity  of  the  diameter  will  be  traversed  in 
the  same  time  by  a  falling  body  as  the  vertical  diame- 
ter itself.  Since,  obviously,  only  the  lengths  and  in- 
clinations are  essential  here,  we  may  also  draw  the 
chords  in  question  from  the  lower  extremity  of  the 
diameter,  and  say  generally  :  The  vertical  diameter 
of  a  circle  is  described  by  a  falling  particle  in  the  same 
time  that  any  chord  through  either  extremity  is  so 
described. 

We  shall  present  another  corollary,  which,  in  the  The  figures 
pretty  form  in  which  Galileo  gave  it,  is  usually  no  bodies  fill- 
longer  incorporated  in  elementary  expositions.  We  chords  of 
imagine  gutters  radiating  in  a  vertical  plane  from  a 
common  point  ^  at  a 
number  of  different 
degrees  of  inclination 
to  the  horizon  (Fig. 
92).  We  place  at  their 
common  extremity  A 
a  like  number  of  heavy 
bodies  and  cause  them 
to  begin  simultaneous- 
ly their  motion  of  des- 
cent. The  bodies  will 
always  form  at  any  one 

instant  of  time  a  circle.  After  the  lapse  of  a  longer  time 
they  will  be  found  in  a  circle  of  larger  radius,  and  the 
radii  increase  proportionally  to  the  squares  of  the 
times.  If  we  imagine  the  gutters  to  radiate  in  a  space 
instead  of  a  plane,  the  falling  bodies  will  always  form 
a  sphere,  and  the  radii  of  the  spheres  will  increase  pro- 
portionally to  the  squares  of  the  times.     This  will  be 


140 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 


ti. 


perceived  by  imagining  the  figure  revolved  about 
perpendicular  A  V. 
Character  8.   We  see  tlius, — as  deserves  again  to  be  briefly 

inquiries,  noticed, — that  Galileo  did  not  supply  us  with  a  theory 
of  the  falling  of  bodies,  but  investigated  and  estab- 
lished, wholly  without  preformed  opinions,  the  actual 
facts  of  falling. 

Gradually  adapting,  on  this  occasion,  his  thoughts 
to  the  facts,  and  everywhere  logically  abiding  by  the 
ideas  he  had  reached,  he  hit  on  a  conception,  which  to 
himself,  perhaps  less  than  to  his  successors,  appeared 
in  tne  light  of  a  new  law.  In  all  his  reasonings,  Galileo 
followed,  to  the  greatest  advantage  of  science,  a  prin- 
ciple which  might  appropriately  be  called  the  principle 
of  continuity.  Once  we  have  reached  a  theory  that  ap- 
plies to  a  particular  case,  we  proceed  gradually  to 
modify  in  thought  the  conditions  of  that  case,  as  far 
as  it  is  at  all  possible,  and  endeavor  in  so  doing  to 
adhere  throughout  as  closely  as  we  can  to  the  concep- 
tion originally  reached.  There  is  no  method  of  pro- 
cedure more  surely  calculated  to  lead  to  that  compre- 
hension of  all  natural  phenomena  which  is  the  simplest 
and  also  attainable  with  the  least  expenditure  of  men- 
tality and  feeling.      (Compare  Appendix,  I.) 

A  particular  instance  will  show  more  clearly  than 
any  general   remarks  what  we  mean.     Galileo   con- 


The  prin- 
ciple of 
continuity. 


Fig.  93- 


siders  (Fig.  93)  a  body  which  is  falling  down   the  in- 
clined plane  AB,  and  which,  being  placed  with  the 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  DYNAMICS,  141 

velocity  thus  acquired  on  a  second  plane  BC,  for  ex-  Galileo's 

discovery 

ample,  ascends  this  second  plane.   On  all  planes  BC,  of  the  so- 

called  law 

BDy  and  so  forth,  it  ascends  to  the  horizontal  plane  of  inertia, 
that  passes  through  A,  But,  just  as  it  falls  on  BD 
with  less  acceleration  than  it  does  on  BC,  so  similarly 
it  will  ascend  on  BD  with  less  retardation  than  it  will 
on  BC.  The  nearer  the  planes  BCy  BD,  BE,  BF  ap- 
proach to  the  horizontal  plane  BH,  the  less  will  the 
retardation  of  the  body  on  those  planes  be,  and  the 
longer  and  further  will  it  move  on  them.  On  the  hori- 
zontal plane  BH  the  retardation  vanishes  entirely  (that 
is,  of  course,  neglecting  friction  and  the  resistance  of 
the  air),  and  the  body  will  continue  to  move  infinitely 
long  and  infinitely  far  with  constant  velocity.  Thus  ad- 
vancing to  the  limiting  case  of  the  problem  presented, 
Galileo  discovers  the  so-called  law  of  inertia,  according 
to  which  a  body  not  under  the  influence  of  forces,  i.  e. 
of  special  circumstances  that  change  motion,  will  re- 
tain forever  its  velocity  (and  direction).  We  shall 
presently  revert  to  this  subject. 

9.  The  motion  of  falling  that  Galileo  found  actually  The  deduc- 
\o  exist,  is,  accordingly,  a  motion  of  which  the  velocity  idea  of  nni- 
increases  proportionally  to  the  time — a  so-called  uni-  ccierated 
formly  accelerated  motion. 

It  would  be  an  anachronism  and  utterly  unhistorical 
to  attempt,  as  is  sometimes  done,  to  derive  the  uniformly 
accelerated  motion  of  falling  bodies  from  the  constant 
action  of  the  force  of  gravity.  **  Gravity  is  a  constant 
force ;  consequently  it  generates  in  equal  elements  of 
time  equal  increments  of  velocity ;  thus,  the  motion 
produced  is  uniformly  accelerated."  Any  exposition 
such  as  this  would  be  unhistorical,  and  would  put  the 
whole  discovery  in  a  false  light,  for  the  reason  that  the 
notion  of  force  as  we  hold  it  to-day  was  first  created 


142  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

Forces  and  bv  Galileo.  Before  Galileo  force  was  known  solely  as 
tions.  pressure.  Now,  no  one  can  know,  who  has  not  learned 
it  from  experience,  that  generally  pressure  produces 
motion,  much  less  in  what  manner  pressure  passes  into 
motion  ;  that  not  position,  nor  velocity,  but  accelera- 
tion, is  determined  by  it.  This  cannot  be  philosophi- 
cally deduced  from  the  conception,  itself.  Conjectures 
may  be  set  up  concerning  it.  But  experience  alone  can 
definitively  inform  us  with  regard  to  it. 

10.  It  is  not  by  any  means  self-evident,  therefore, 
that  the  circumstances  which  determine  motion,  that 
is,  forces,  immediately  produce  accelerations.  A  glance 
at  other  departments  of  physics  will  at  once  make  this 
clear.  The  differences  of  temperature  of  bodies  also 
determine  alterations.  However,  by  differences  of  tem- 
perature not  compensatory  accelerations  are  deter- 
mined, but  compensatory  velocities. 

The  fact  That  it  is  accelerations  which  are  the  immediate  ef- 

determine  fects  of  the  circumstances  that  determine  motion,  that 
tions  is  an  is,  of  the  forces,  is  a  fact  which  Gsilileo  perceived  in  the 
toPfact*"  natural  phenomena.  Others  before  him  had  also  per- 
ceived many  things.  The  assertion  that  everything  seeks 
its  place  also  involves  a  correct  observation.  The  ob- 
servation, however,  does  not  hold  good  in  all  cases, 
and  it  is  not  exhaustive.  If  we  cast  a  stone  into  the 
air,  for  example,  it  no  longer  seeks  its  place ;  since  its 
place  is  below.  But  the  acceleration  towards  the  earth, 
the  retardation  of  the  upward  motion,  the  fact  that  Ga- 
lileo perceived,  is  still  present.  His  observation  always 
remains  correct ;  it  holds  true  more  generally ;  it  em- 
braces in  one  mental  effort  mucA  more, 

11.  We  have  already  remarked  that  Galileo  dis- 
covered the  so-called  law  of  inertia  quite  incidentally. 
A  body  on  which,  as  we  are  wont  to  say,  a  force  acts. 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  DYNAMICS.  143 

preserves  its  direction  and  velocity  unchanged.  The  History  of 
fortunes  of  this  law  of  inertia  have  been  strange.  It  called  law 
appears  never  to  have  played  a  prominent  part  in  Gali- 
leo's thought.  But  Galileo's  successors,  particularly 
Huygens  and  Newton,  formulated  it  as  an  independent 
law.  Nay,  some  have  even  made  of  inertia  a  general 
property  of  matter.  We  shall  readily  perceive,  how- 
ever, that  the  law  of  inertia  is  not  at  all  an  indepen- 
dent law,  but  is  contained  implicitly  in  Galileo's  per- 
ception that  all  circumstances  determinative  of  motion, 
or  forces,  produce  accelerations. 

In  fact,  if  a  force  determine,  not  position,  not  velo-  The  law  a 
city,  but  acceleration,  change  of  velocity,  it  stands  to  ference 
reason  that  where  there  is  no  force  there  will  be  no  leo's  funda 

......  .         mental  ob- 

change  of  velocity.     It  is  not  necessary  to  enunciate  aervation. 
this  in  independent  form.     The  embarrassment  of  the 
neophyte,  which  also  overcame  the  great  investigators 
in  the  face  of  the  great  mass  of  new  material  presented, 

■ 

alone  could  have  led  them  to  conceive  the  same  fact  as 
two  different  facts  and  to  formulate  it  twice. 

In  any  event,  to  represent  inertia  as  self-evident,  or  Erroneous 
to  derive  it  from  the  general  proposition  that  ''the  ef- deducing u 
feet  of  a  cause  persists,"  is  totally  wrong.  Only  a 
mistaken  straining  after  rigid  logic  can  lead  us  so  out 
of  the  way.  Nothing  is  to  be  accomplished  in  the  pres- 
ent domain  with  scholastic  propositions  like  the  one 
just  cited.  We  may  easily  convince  ourselves  that  the 
contrary  proposition,  "cessante  causa  cessat  effectus," 
is  as  well  supported  by  reason.  If  we  call  the  acquired 
velocity  "the  effect,"  then  the  first  proposition  is  cor- 
rect ;  if  we  call  the  acceleration  "effect,"  then  the  sec- 
ond proposition  holds. 

1 2.  We  shall  now  examine  Galileo's  researches  from 
another  side.     He  began  his  investigations  with  the 


144 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 


Notion  of    notions  familiar  to  his  time — notions  developed  mainly 
it  existed  in  in  the  practical  arts.     One  notion  of  this  kind  was  that 
time.         of  velocity,  which  is  very  readily  obtained  from  the  con- 
sideration of  a  uniform  motion.     If  a  body  traverse  in 
every  second  of  time  the  same  distance  ^,  the  distance 
traversed  at  the  end  of  /  seconds  will  be  j  =  r/.     The 
distance  c  traversed  in  a  second  of  time  we  call  the  ve- 
locity, and  obtain  it  from  the  examination  of  any  por- 
tion of  the  distance  and  the  corresponding  time  by  the 
help  of  the  equation  c  =  j//,  that  is,  by  dividing  the 
number  which  is  the  measure  of  the  distance  traversed 
by  the  number  which  is  the  measure  of  the  time  elapsed. 
Now,  Galileo  could  not  complete  his  investigations 
without  tacitly  modifying  and  extending  the  traditional 
idea  of  velocity.   Let  us  represent  for  distinctness  sake 

a 


in  I  (Fig.  94)  a  uniform  motion,  in  2  a  variable  motion, 
by  laying  off  as  abscissae  in  the  direction  OA  the  elapsed 
times,  and  erecting  as  ordinates  in  the  direction  AB  the 
distances  traversed.  Now,  in  i,  whatever  increment 
of  the  distance  we  may  divide  by  the  corresponding  in- 
crement of  the  time,  in  all  cases  we  obtain  for  the  ve- 
locity c  the  same  value.  But  if  we  were  thus  to  proceed 
in  2,  we  should  obtain  widely  differing  values,  and 
therefore  the  word  "velocity  "  as  ordinarily  understood, 
ceases  in  this  case  to  be  unequivocal.  If,  however,  we 
consider  the  incr^asQ  of  the  distance  in  a  sufficiently 


« 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  D  YNAMICS.  145 

small  element  of  time,  where  the  element  of  the  curve  Galileo's 
m  2  approaches  to  a  straight  line,  we  may  regard  the  tion  of  this 
increase  as  uniform.  The  velocity  in  this  element  of 
the  motion  we  may  then  define  as  the  quotient,  J  s/A  /, 
of  the  element  of  the  time  into  the  corresponding  ele- 
ment of  the  distance.  Still  more  precisely,  the  velocity 
at  any  instant  is  defined  as  the  limiting  value  which 
the  ratio  A  sjA  t  assumes  as  the  elements  become  in- 
finitely small — a  value  designated  by  dsjdt.  This  new 
notion  includes  the  old  one  as  a  particular  case,  and  is, 
moreover,  immediately  applicable  to  uniform  motion. 
Although  the  express  formulation  of  this  idea,  as  thus 
extended,  did  not  take  place  till  long  after  Galileo,  we 
see  none  the  less  that  he  made  use  of  it  in  his  reason- 
ings. 

13.  An  entirely  new  notion  to  which  Galileo  was  The  notion 
led  is  the  idea  of  acceleration.  In  uniformly  acceler-  tion. 
ated  motion  the  velocities  increase  with  the  time 
agreeably  to  the  same  law  as  in  uniform  motion  the 
spaces  increase  with  the  times.  If  we  call  v  the  velo- 
city acquired  in  time  /,  then  v  =  gt.  Here  g  denotes 
the  increment  of  the  velocity  in  unit  of  time  or  the  ac- 
celera'tion,  which  we  also  obtain  from  the  equation 
g  =  v/t.  When  the  investigation  of  variably  accel- 
erated motions  was  begun,  this  notion  of  accelera- 
tion had  to  experience  an  extension  similar  to  that  of 
the  notion  of  velocity.  If  in  i  and  2  the  times  be  again 
drawn  as  abscissae,  but  now  the  velocities  as  ordinates, 
we  may  go  through  anew  the  whole  train  of  the  pre- 
ceding reasoning  and  define  the  acceleration  as  dvjdt^ 
where  dv  denotes  an  infinitely  small  increment  of  the 
velocity  and  dt  the  corresponding  increment  of  the 
time.     In  the  notation  of  the  differential  calculus  we 


146 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 


have  for  the  acceleration  of  a  rectilinear  motion,  qt  = 
Graphic  The  ideas  here  developed  are  susceptible,  moreover, 

representa- 

rion  of        of  graphic  representation.     If  we  lay  off  the  times  as 

these  ideas.  . 

abscissae  and  the  distances  as  ordinates,  we  shall  per- 
ceive, that  the  velocity  at  each  instant  is  measured  by 
the  slope  of  the  curve  of  the  distance.  If  in  a  similar 
manner  we  put  times  and  velocities  together,  we  shall 
see  that  the  acceleration  of  the  instant  is  measured  by 
the  slope  of  the  curve  of  the  velocity.  The  course  of 
the  latter  slope  is,  indeed,  also  capable  of  being  traced 
in  the  curve  of  distances,  as  will  be  perceived  from 
the  following  considerations.     Let  us  imagine,  in  the 


Fig.  95- 


Fig.  96. 


Thecurve  usual  manner  (Fig.  95),  a  uniform  motion  represented 

of  distance.  \      ^     ^^n  r 

by  a  straight  Ime  OCD.  Let  us  compare  with  this  a 
motion  OCE  the  velocity  of  which  in  the  second  half 
of  the  time  is  greater,  and  another  motion  OCF  of 
which  the  velocity  is  in  the  same  proportion  smaller. 
In  the  first  case,  accordingly,  we  shall  have  to  erect  for 
the  time  OB  =  2  OA,  an  ordinate  greater  than  BZ>  == 
2  AC;  in  the  second  case,  an  ordinate  less  than  BD, 
We  see  thus,  without  difficulty,  that  a  curve  of  dis- 
tance convex  to  the  axis  of  the  time-abscissae  corre- 
sponds to  accelerated  motion,  and  a  curve  concave 
thereto  to  retarded  motion.  If  we  imagine  a  lead-pen- 
cil to  perform  a  vertical  motion  of  any  kind  and  in 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  DYNAMICS.  147 

front  of  it  during  its  motion  a  piece  of  paper  to  be  uni- 
formly drawn  along  from  right  to  left  and  the  pencil  to 
thus  execute  the  drawing  in  Fig.  96,  we  shall  be  able  to 
read  off  from  the  drawing  the  peculiarities  of  the  mo- 
tion. At  a  the  velocity  of  the  pencil  was  directed  up- 
wardsy  at  b  it  was  greater,  at  c  it  was  =0,  at  </  it  was 
directed  downwards,  at  e  it  was  again  =  0.  At  a^  b^ 
dy  e,  the  acceleration  was  directed  upwards,  at  c  down- 
wards ;  at  c  and  e  it  was  greatest. 

14.  The  summary  representation  of  what  Galileo  Tabular 
discovered  is  best  made  by  a  table  of  times,  acquired  mem  of  ca- 

^  ^  lileo'8dis- 

/.  V,  S.  "'^^ 


1 

g 

>l 

2 

2^ 

'f 

3 

^g 

»f 

/ 

tg 

■               •                ■              • 

2 

velocities,  and  traversed  distances.     But  the  numbers  The  table 

ooav  bo  re~ 

follow  so  simple  a  law, — one  immediately  recognisable,  placed  by, 
— that  there  is  nothing  to  prevent  our  replacing  the  constnic- 
table  by  a  rule  for  its  construction.  If  we  examine  the 
relation  that  connects  the  first  and  second  columns,  we 
shall  find  that  it  is  expressed  by  the  equation  v  =  gt, 
which,  in  its  last  analysis,  is  nothing  but  an  abbrevi- 
ated direction  for  constructing  the  first  two  columns 
of  the  table.  The  relation  connecting  the  first  and  third 
columns  is  given  by  the  equation  s  =.gt^  jo..  The  con- 
nection of  the  second  and  third  columns  is  represented 
by  s=^v^/2g. 


148  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

The  rules.         Of  the  three  relations 

v  =  gt 

rr/2 
i"  =         - 

2 

strictly,  the  first  two  only  were  employed  by  Galileo. 
Huygens  was  the  first  who  evinced  a  higher  apprecia- 
tion of  the  third,  and  laid,  in  thus  doing,  the  founda- 
tions of  important  advances. 
A  remark  1 5.    We  may  add  a   remark  in   connection   with 

tionofthe  this  table  that  is  very  valuable.     It  has  been  stated 
t^elSies.    previously  that  a  body,  by  virtue  of  the  velocity  it  has 
acquired  in  its  fall,  is  able  to  rise  again  to  its  origi- 
nal height,  in  doing  which  its  velocity  diminishes  in 
the  same  way  (with  respect  to  time  and  space)  as  it 
increased  in  falling.     Now  a  freely  falling  body  ac- 
quires in  double  time  of  descent  double  velocity,  but 
falls  in  this  double  time  through  four  times  the  simple 
distance.  A  body,  therefore,  to  which  we  impart  a  ver- 
tically upward  double  velocity  will  ascend  twice  as 
long  a  time,  hxiXfour  times  as  high  as  a  body  to  which 
the  simple  velocity  has  been  imparted. 
The  dispute       It  was  remarked,  very  soon  after  Galileo,  that  there 
tesians  and  is  inherent  in  the  velocity  of  a  body  a  something  that 
ians  on  the  corresponds  to  a  force — a  something,  that  is,  by  which 

measure  of       .  ,  •  rr  •!         •    1 

force.  a  force  can  be  overcome,  a  certam  "  efficacy,  as  it  has 
been  aptly  termed.  The  only  point  that  was  debated 
was,  whether  this  efficacy  was  to  be  reckoned  propor- 
tional to  the  velocity  or  to  the  square  of  the  velocity. 
The  Cartesians  held  the  former,  the  Leibnitzians  the 
latter.  But  it  will  be  perceived  that  the  question  in- 
volves no  dispute  whatever.  The  body  with  the  double 
velocity  overcomes  a  given  force  through  double  the 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  D  YNAMICS.  149 

time,  but  through  four  times  the  distance.  With  re- 
spect to  time,  therefore,  its  efficacy  is  proportional  to 
the  velocity ;  with  respect  to  distance,  to  the  square  of 
the  velocity.  D'Alembert  drew  attention  to  this  mis- 
understanding, although  in  not  very  distinct  terms.  It 
is  to  be  especially  remarked,  however,  that  Huygens's 
thoughts  on  this  question  were  perfectly  clear. 

16.  The  experimental  procedure  by  which,  at  the  The  present 

1      J*  -n    J     •    experimen- 

present  day,  the  laws  of  falling  bodies  are  verified,  istaimeansof 

r         1*1  T«  V     J    venfyinj? 

somewhat  different  from  that  of  Galileo.  Two  methods  the  jawa  of 
may  be  employed.  Either  the  motion  of  falling,  which  ies. 
from  its  rapidity  is  difficult  to  observe  directly,  is  so 
retarded,  without  altering  the  law,  as  to  be  easily  ob- 
served ;  or  the  motion  of  falling  is  not  altered  at  all, 
but  our  means  of  observation  are  improved  in  deli- 
cacy. On  the  first  principle  Galileo's  inclined 
gutter  and  At  wood's  machine  rest.  Atwood's 
machine  consists  (Fig.  97)  of  an  easily  run- 
ning pulley,  over  which  is  thrown  a  thread, 
to  whose  extremities  two  equal  weights  P  are 
attached.  If  upon  one  of  the  weights  P  we 
lay  a  third  small  weight  p^  a  uniformly  accel-  r\P 
erated  motion  will  be  set  up  by  the  over-  p>k-97. 
weight,  having  the  acceleration  {p/'iP-^-  f)  g — a  result 
that  will  be  readily  obtained  when  we  shall  have  dis- 
cussed the  notion  of  **mass."  Now  by  means  of  a 
graduated  vertical  standard  connected  with  the  pulley 
it  may  easily  be  shown  that  in  the  times  i,  2,  3,.  4  ... . 
the  distances  i,  4,  9,  16.  .  .  .  are  traversed.  The  final 
velocity  corresponding  to  any  given  time  of  descent  is 
investigated  by  catching  the  small  additional  weight,/, 
which  is  shaped  so  as  to  project  beyond  the  outline  of 
P,  in  a  ring  through  which  the  falling  body  passes, 
after  which  the  motion  continues  without  acceleration. 


150  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

The  appa-  The  apparatus  of  Morin  is  based  on  a  different  prin- 
Morin,  La-  ciple.  A  body  to  which  a  writing  pencil  is  attached 
pich,  and  describes  on  a  vertical  sheet  of  paper,  which  is  drawn 
uniformly  across  it  by  a  clock-work,  a  horizontal  straight 
line.  If  the  body  fall  while  the  paper  is  not  in  motion, 
it  will  describe  a  vertical  straight  line.  If  the  two 
motions  are  combined,  a  parabola  will  be  produced, 
of  which  the  horizontal  abscissae  correspond  to  the 
elapsed  times  and  the  vertical  ordinates  to  the  dis- 
tances of  descent  described.  For  the  abscissse  i,  2, 
3,  4  ...  .  we  obtain  the  ordinates  i,  4,  9,  16 ...  .  By 
an  unessential  modification,  Morin  employed  instead  of 
a  plane  sheet  of  paper,  a  rapidly  rotating  cylindrical 
drum  with  vertical  axis,  by  the  side  of  which  the  body 
fell  down  a  guiding  wire.  A  different  apparatus,  based 
on  the  same  principle,  was  invented,  independently,  by 
Laborde,  Lippich,  and  Von  Babo.  A  lampblacked 
sheet  of  glass  (Fig.  98^;)  falls  freely,  while  a  horizon- 
tally vibrating  vertical  rod,  which  in  its  first  transit 
through  the  position  of  equilibrium  starts  the  motion 
of  descent,  traces,  by  means  of  a  quill,  a  curve  on  the 
lampblacked  surface.  Owing  to  the  constancy  of  the 
period  of  vibration  of  the  rod  combined  with  the  in- 
creasing velocity  of  the  descent,  the  undulations  traced 
by  the  rod  became  longer  and  longer.  Thus  (Fig.  98) 
bc=i^ab,  cd=i$aif,  de=^']aby  and  so  forth.  The 
law  of  falling  bodies  is  clearly  exhibited  by  this,  since 
ab  -\-  cb  =z  ^abj  ab  -^  be  -\-  cif  =  gab,  and  so  forth. 
The  law  of  the  velocity  is  confirmed  by  the  inclinations 
of  the  tangents  at  the  points  a,  b,  r,  //,  and  so  forth.  If 
the  time  of  oscillation  of  the  rod  be  known,  the  value 
of  g  is  determinable  from  an  experiment  of  this  kind 
with  considerable  exactness. 

Wheatstone  employed  for  the  measurement  of  mi- 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  DYNAMICS.  iji 

□ute  portions  of  time  a  rapidly  operating  clock-work  Tbeds- 
called  a  chronoscope,  which  is  set  in  motion  at  the  be-  whm- 
ginning  of  the  time  to  be  measured  and  stopped  at  the  Hipp.    , 
termination  of  it.     Hipp  has  advantageously  modified 


Fig.9St 

this  method  by  simply  causing  a  light  index-hand  to 
be  thrown  by  means  of  a  clutch  in  and  out  of  gear  with 
a  rapidly  moving  wheel-work  regulated  by  a  vibrating 
reed  of  steel  tuned  to  a  high  note,  and  acting  as  an  es- 


152 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 


Galileo's 
minor  in- 
vestiga- 
tions. 


capement.  The  throwing  in  and  out  of  gear  is  effected 
by  an  electric  current.  Now  if,  as  soon  as  the  body  be- 
gins to  fall,  the  current  be  interrupted,  that  is  the  hand 
thrown  into  gear,  and  as  soon  as  the  body  strikes  the 
platform  below  the  current  is  closed,  that  is  the  hand 
thrown  out  of  gear,  we  can  read  by  the  distance  the 
index-hand  has  travelled  the  time  of  descent. 

17.  Among  the  further  achievements  of  Galileo  we 
have  yet  to  mention  his  ideas  concerning  the  motion 
of  the  pendulum,  and  his  refutation  of  the  view  that 
bodies  of  greater  weight  fall  faster  than  bodies  of  less 
weight.  We  shall  revert  to  both  of  these  points  on  an- 
other occasion.  It  may  be  stated  here,  however,  that 
Galileo,  on  discovering  the  constancy  of  the  period  of 
pendulum-oscillations,  at  once  applied  the  pendulum 
to  pulse-measurements  at  the  sick-bed,  as  well  as  pro- 
posed its  use  in  astronomical  observations  and  to  a  cer- 
tain extent  employed  it  therein  himself. 

18.  Of  still  greater  importance  are  his  investiga- 

of  projec-       , 

tiles.  tions  concerning  the  motion  of  projectiles.  A  free  body, 

according  to  Galileo's  view,  constantly  experiences  a 
vertical  acceleration  g  towards  the  earth.  If  at  the 
beginning  of  its  motion  it  is  affected  with  a  vertical 

velocity  c,  its  velocity  at  the 
end  of  the  time  /  will  be  z^  = 
c  -\-  gt.  An  initial  velocity  up- 
wards would  have  to  be  reck- 
oned negative  here.  The  dis- 
tance described  at  the  end  of 
p»R  99.  time  /  is  represented  by  the 

equation  s=^a-\-  ct  -\  ^gt^y  where  ct  and  ^gt^  are  the 
portions  of  the  traversed  distance  that  correspond  re- 
spectively to  the  uniform  and  the  uniformly  accelerated 
motion.  The  constant  a  is  to  be  put  ==  0  when  we  reckon 


The  motion 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  DYNAMICS,  153 

the  distance  from  the  point  that  the  body  passes  at  time 
/  =  0.  When  Galileo  had  once  reached  his  fundamental 
conception  of  dynamics,  he  easily  recognised  the  case 
of  horizontal  projection  as  a  combination  of  two  inde- 
pendent motions,  a  horizontal  uniform  motion,  and  a 
vertical  uniformly  accelerated  motion.  He  thus  intro- 
duced into  use  the  principle  of  the  parallelogram  of  mo- 
tions. Even  oblique  projection  no  longer  presented  the 
slightest  difficulty. 

If  a  body  receives  a  horizontal  velocity  c,  it  de- The  carve 
scribes  in  the  horizontal  direction  in  time  /  the  distance  tion  a  par- 
y  =:.  ctf  while  simultaneously  it  falls  in  a  vertical  direc- 
tion the  distance  jtr=^/2^2.  Different  motion-deter- 
minative circumstances  exercise  no  mutual  effect  on  one 
another,  and  the  motions  determined  by  them  take 
place  independently  of  each  other,  Galileo  was  led  to 
this  assumption  by  the  attentive  observation  of  the 
phenomena ;  and  the  assumption  proved  itself  true. 

For  the  curve  which  a  body  describes  when  the  two 
motions  in  question  are  compounded,  we  find,  by  em- 
ploying the  two  equations  above  given,  the  expression 
y  =:V\2c  ^ /g)  X,  It  is  the  parabola  of  ApoUonius  hav- 
ing its  parameter  equal  to  c^/gond  its  axis  vertical, 
as  Galileo  knew. 

We  readily  perceive  with  Galileo,  that  oblique  pro-  oblique 
jection  involves  nothing  new.  The  velocity  c  imparted 
to  a  body  at  the  angle  a  with  the  horizon  is  resolvable 
into  the  horizontal  component  c  .  cos  a  and  the  vertical 
component  c  .  sin  a.  With  the  latter  velocity  thfe  body 
ascends  during  the  same  interval  of  time  /  which  it 
would  take  to  acquire  this  velocity  in  falling  vertically 
downwards.  Therefore,  ^.sina=^/.  When  it  has 
reached  its  greatest  height  the  vertical  component  of 
its  initial  velocity  has  vanished,  and  from  the  point  S 


154  ^^^  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

onward  (Fig.  loo)  it  continues  its  motion  as  a  horizon- 
tal projection.  If  we  examine  any  two  epochs  equally 
distant  in  time,  before  and  after  the  transit  through  5, 

we  shall  see  that  the  body  at 
these  two  epochs  is  equally 
distant  from  the  perpendicu 
lar  through  5  and  situated  the 
same  distance  below  the  hori- 
zontal line  through  5.  The 
Fig.  loo.  curve  is  therefore  symmet- 

rical with  respect  to  the  vertical  line  through  5.  It 
is  a  parabola  with  vertical  axis  and  the  parameter 
(r  cosflr)*/^. 
The  range  To  find  the  so-called  range  of  projection,  we  have 
o^projec-  gjjjipiy  to  consider  the  horizontal  motion  during  the 
time  of  the  rising  and  falling  of  the  body.  For  the  ascent 
this  time  is,  according  to  the  equations  above  given, 
/  =  ^  sin  ajgy  and  the  same  for  the  descent.  With  the 
horizontal  velocity  c .  cos  a,  therefore,  the  distance  is 

traversed 

c  sin  oi        c^  c^ 

w  =^  c  cos  a  .  2 =  —  2  sin  a  cos  a  =       sin  2  a, 

g  g  g 

The  range  of   projection   is  greatest  accordingly 
when  a  =  45°,  and  equally  great  for  any  two  angles 

The  mutual        1 9.  The  recognition  of  the  Tdutwdl  independence  oi 
dence  of     the  forccs,  or  motion -determinative  circumstances  oc- 

forces.  .  .  ^  1  •    1 

currmg  m  nature,  which  was 
reached  and  found  expression 
in  the  investigations  relating  to 
projection, is  important.  A  body 
Fig.  lox.  jj^^y  move  (Fig.  loi)  in  the  di- 

rection AB,  while  the  space  in  which  this  motion  oc- 
curs is  displaced  in  the  direction  A  C.     The  body  then 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  D  YNAMICS.  155 

goes  from  A  to  D.  Now,  this  also  happens  if  the  two 
circumstances  that  simultaneously  determine  the  mo- 
tions AB  and  A  C,  have  no  influence  on  one  another. 
It  is  easy  to  see  that  we  may  compound  by  the  paral- 
lelogram not  only  displacements  that  have  taken  place 
but  also  velocities  and  accelerations  that  simultane- 
ously take  place. 

II. 

THE  ACHIEVEMENTS  OF  HUVGENS. 

I.  The  next  in  succession  of  the  great  mechanical  in-  Hamns's 
quirers  is  Huvgens,  who  in  every  respect  must  beas\/in- 
ranked  as  Galileo's  peer.   If,  perhaps,  his  philosophical  *'^*"'^' 
endowments  were  less  splendid  than  those  of  Galileo, 
this  deficiency  was  compensated  for  by  the  superiority 
of  his  geometrical  powers.   Huygens  not  only  continued 
the  researches  which  Galileo  had  begun,  but  he  also 
solved   the   first  problems  in  the  dynamics  of  several 
masses^  whereas  Galileo  had  throughout  restricted  him- 
self to  the  dynamics  of  a  single  body. 

The  plenitude  of  Huygens's  achievements  is  best  Enumera- 
seen  in  his  HorologiumOscillaioriuniy  which  appeared  in  gens's 
1673.  The  most  important  subjects  there  treated  of  formems. 
the  first  time,  are  :  the  theory  of  the  centre  of  oscilla- 
tion, the  invention  and  construction  of  the  pendulum- 
clock,  the  invention  of  the  escapement,  the  determina- 
tion of   the  acceleration  of  gravity,  gy  by  pendulum- 
observations,  a  proposition  regarding  the  employment 
of  the  length  of  the  seconds  pendulum  as  the  unit  of 
length,  the  theorems  respecting  centrifugal  force,  the 
mechanical  and  geometrical  properties  of  cycloids,  the 
doctrine  of  evolutes,  and  the  theory  of  the  circle  of 
curvature. 


156  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

2.  With  respect  to  the  form  of  presentation  of  his 
work,  it  is  to  be  remarked  that  Huygens  shares  with 


Galileo,  in  all  its  perfection,  the  latter's  exalted  and 
inimitable  candor.  He  is  frank  without  reserve  in  the 
presentment  of  the  methods  that  led  him  to  his  dis- 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  D  YA'AMICS. 


coveries,  and  thus  always 
conducts  his  reader  into  the 
full  comprehension  of  his 
performances.  Nor  had  he 
cause  to  conceal  these 
methods.  If,  some  thou- 
sand years  hence,  it  will  be 
found  that  he  was  a  man,  it 
will  likewise  be  seen  what 
manner  of  man  he  was. 
In  our  discussion  of  the 
achievements  of  Huygens, 
however,  we  shall  have  to 
proceed  in  a  somewhat  dif- 
ferent manner  from  that 
which  we  pursued  in  the 
case  of  Galileo.  Galileo's 
views,  in  their  classical  sim- 
plicity, could  be  given  in  an 
almost  unmodified  form. 
With  Huygens  this  is  not 
possible.  The  latter  deals 
with  more  complicated 
problems;  his  mathematical 
methods  and  notations  be- 
come inadequate  and  cum- 
brous. For  reasons  of  brev- 
ity, therefore,  we  shall  re- 
produce all  the  conceptions 
of  which  we  treat,  in  mod- 
em form,  retaining,  how- 
ever, Huygens's  essential 
and  characteristic  ideas. 


'i  Psadulnin  Clock. 


X58  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

CentrifuKai  3.  We  begin  with  the  investigations  concerning 
petal  force,  centrifugal  force.  When  once  we  have  recognised  with 
Galileo  that  force  determines  acceleration,  we  are  im- 
pelled, unavoidably,  to  ascribe  every  change  of  velocity 
and  consequently  also  every  change  in  the  direction  of 
a  motion  (since  the  direction  is  determined  by  three 
velocity-components  perpendicular  to  one  another)  to 
a  force.  If,  therefore,  any  body  attached  to  a  string, 
say  a  stone,  is  swung  uniformly  round  in  a  circle,  the 
curvilinear  motion  which  it  performs  is  intelligible  only 
on  the  supposition  of  a  constant  force  that  deflects  the 
body  from  the  rectilinear  path.  The  tension  of  the 
string  is  this  force ;  by  it  the  body  is  constantly  deflected 
from  the  rectilinear  path  and  made  to  move  towards 
the  centre  of  the  circle.  This  tension,  accordingly,  rep- 
resents a  centripetal  force.  On  the  other  hand,  the  axis 
also,  or  the  fixed  centre,  is  acted  on  by  the  tension  of 
the  string,  and  in  this  aspect  the  tension  of  the  string 
appears  as  a  centrifugal  force. 


iQ- 


Fig.  xoa.  Fig.  103. 

Let  US  suppose  that  we  have  a  body  to  which  a  ve- 
locity has  been  imparted  and  which  is  maintained  in 
uniform  motion  in  a  circle  by  an  acceleration  constantly 
directed  towards  the  centre.  The  conditions  on  which 
this  acceleration  depends,  it  is  our  purpose  to  investi- 
gate.    We  imagine  (Fig.  102)  two  equal  circles  uni- 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  D  YNAMICS.  159 

formly  travelled  round  by  two  bodies ;  the  velocities  in  uniform 
the  circles  I  and  II  bear  to  each  other  the  proportion  e^uai 

circles 

1:2.  If  in  the  two  circles  we  consider  any  same  arc- 
element  corresponding  to  some  very  small  angle  at,  then 
the  corresponding  element  s  of  the  distance  that  the 
bodies  in  consequence  of  the  centripetal  acceleration 
have  departed  from  the  rectilinear  path  (the  tangent), 
will  also  be  the  same.  If  we  call  q)^  and  q)^  the  re- 
spective accelerations,  and  r  and  r/2  the  time-elements 
for  the  angle  or,  we  find  by  Galileo's  law 

<Py  =  :^y  92  =  ^  -^»  ^^^^  's  to  say  (p^  =  4(p^, 

Therefore,  by  generalisation,  in  equal  circles  the 
centripetal  acceleration  is  proportional  to  the  square  of 
the  velocity  of  the  motion. 

Let  us  now  consider  the  motion  in  the  circles  I  and  Uniform 

xx-r-i'  1  fri't  1         \  molion  in 

II  (Fig.  103),  the  radii  of  which  are  to  each  other  as  unequal 
I  :  2,  and  let  us  take  for  the  ratio  of  the  velocities  of 
the  motions  also  1:2,  so  that  like  arc-elements  are 
travelled  through  in  equal  times,  (p^,  (p^,  s,  is  denote 
the  accelerations  and  the  elements  of  the  distance  trav- 
ersed ;  r  is  the  element  of  the  time,  equal  for  both 
cases.     Then 

9x  =  yi>  ^2  =  ^2'  ^^^^  ^s  *°  ^^y  ^2  =  2^1- 

If  now  we  reduce  the  velocity  of  the  motion  in  II 
one-half,  so  that  the  velocities  in  I  and  II  become 
equal,  (p^  will  thereby  be  reduced  one-fourth,  that  is 
to  say  to  ^1/2.  Generalising,  we  get  this  rule :  when 
the  velocity  of  the  circular  motion  is  the  same^  the  cen- 
tripetal acceleration  is  inversely  proportional  to  the 
radius  of  the  circle  described. 

4.  The  early  investigators,  owing  to  their  following 


i6o 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 


Deduction   the  conceptions  of  the  ancients,  generally  obtained  their 
era!  law  of  propositions  in  the  cumbersome  form  of  proportions. 

circular 

motion.  We  shall  pursue  a  different  method.  On  a  movable 
object  having  the  velocity  v  let  a  force  act  during  the 
element  of  time  r  which  imparts  to  the  object  perpen- 
dicularly to  the  direction  of  its  motion  the  acceleration 
<p.  The  new  velocity-component  thus  becomes  ^r, 
and  its  composition  with  the  first  velocity  produces  a 
new  direction  of  the  motion,  making  the  angle  a  with 
the  original  direction.  From  this  results,  by  conceiving 
the  motion  to  take  place  in  a  circle  of  radius  r,  and  on 
account  of  the  smallness  of  the  angular  element  putting 


Fir.  104.  Fig.  105. 

tan  n'  =  nr,  the  following,  as  the  complete  expression 
for  the  centripetal  acceleration  of  a  uniform  motion  in 
a  circle. 


q}T 


vr 


The  para- 
doxical 
character 
of  this 
problem. 


7>2 

=  tan  nr  ==  fl' ^     -or<z;=:     . 
V  r  r 

The  idea  of  uniform  motion  in  a  circle  conditioned 
by  a  constant  centripetal  acceleration  is  a  little  para- 
doxical. The  paradox  lies  in  the  assumption  of  a  con- 
stant acceleration  towards  the  centre  without  actual 
approach  thereto  and  without  increase  of  velocity.  This 
is  lessened  when  we  reflect  that  without  this  centripetal 
acceleration  the  body  would  be  continually  moving 
away  from  the  centre  ;  that  the  direction  of  the  accel- 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  DYNAMICS.  x6i 

eration  is  constantly  changing ;  and  that  a  change  of 
velocity  (as  will  appear  in  the  discussion  of  the  prin- 
ciple of  vis  viva)  is  connected  with  an  approach  of  the 
bodies  that  accelerate  each  other,  which  doe's  not  take 
place  here.  The  more  complex  case  of  elliptical  cen- 
tral motion  is  elucidative  in  this  direction. 

5.  The  expression  for  the  centripetal  or  centrifugal  a  different 

expression 

acceleration,  (p  =  r/^/r,  can  easily  be  put  in  a  somewhat  of  the  Uw. 
different  form.  If  T  denote  the  periodic  time  of  the 
circular  motion,  the  time  occupied  in  describing  the 
circumference,  then  vT^=^^rn^  and  consequently  q)  = 
\rn^ jT^y  in  which  form  we  shall  employ  the  expres- 
sion later  on.  If  several  bodies  moving  in  circles  have 
the  same  periodic  times,  the  respective  centripetal  ac- 
celerations by  which  they  are  held  in  their  paths,  as  is 
apparent  from  the  last  expression,  are  proportional  to 
the  radii. 

6.  We  shall  take  it  for  granted  that  the  reader  is  Some  phe- 
familiar  with  the  phenomena  that  illustrate  the  con-  which  the 

Ibw  ex~ 

siderations  here  presented  :  as  the  rupture  of  strings  of  plains, 
insufficient  strength  on  which  bodies  are  whirled  about, 
the  flattening  of  soft  rotating  spheres,  and  so  on.  Huy- 
gens  was  able,  by  the  aid  of  his  conception,  to  explain 
at  once  whole  series  of  phenomena.  When  a  pendulum- 
clock,  for  example,  which  had  been  taken  from  Paris 
to  Cayenne  by  Richer  (1 671-1673),  showed  a  retarda- 
tion of  its  motion,  Huygens  deduced  the  apparent 
diminution  of  the  acceleration  of  gravity  g  thus  estab- 
lished, from  the  greater  centrifugal  acceleration  of  the 
rotating  earth  at  the  equator ;  an  explanation  that  at 
once  rendered  the  observation  intelligible. 

An  experiment  instituted  by  Huygens  may  here  be 
noticed,  on  account  of  its  historical  interest.  When 
Newton  brought  out  his  theory  of  universal  gravitation, 


f6i  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

An  interest-  Huygcns  belonged  to  the  great  number  of  those  who 
ment  of  Were  unable  to  reconcile  themselves  to  the  idea  of  action 
uygens.  ^^  ^  distance.  He  was  of  the  opinion  that  gi^avitation 
could  be  explained  by  a  vortical  medium.  If  we  enclose 
in  a  vessel  filled  with  a  liquid  a  number  of  lighter  bod- 
ies, say  wooden  balls  in  water,  and  set  the  vessel  ro- 
tating about  its  axis,  the  balls  will  at  once  rapidly  move 
towards  the  axis.  If  for  instance  (Fig.  io6),  we  place 
the  glass  cylinders  RR  containing  the  wooden  balls  KK 
by  means  of  a  pivot  Z  on  a  rotatory  apparatus,  and  ro- 
tate the  latter  about  its  ver- 
R  .  R^<\     tical  axis,  the  balls  will  im- 

mediately run  up  the  cyl- 
I    I  -  inders  in  the  direction  away 

M  from  the  axis.     But  if  the 

a\  tubes  be  filled  with  water, 

Fig.  106.  each  rotation  will  force  the 

balls  floating  at  the  extremities  EE  towards  the  axis. 
The  phenomenon  is  easily  explicable  by  analogy  with 
the  principle  of  Archimedes.  The  wooden  balls  receive 
a  centripetal  impulsion,  comparable  to  buoyancy, 
which  is  equal  and  opposite  to  the  centrifugal  force 
acting  on  the  displaced  liquid. 
Oscillatory        7.   Before  we  proceed  to  Huygens*s  investigations 

motion.  .         . 

on  the  centre  of  oscillation,  we  shall  present  to  the 
reader  a  few  considerations  concerning  pendulous  and 
oscillatory  motion  generally,  which  will  make  up  in  ob- 
viousness for  what  they  lack  in  rigor. 

Many  of  the  properties  of  pendulum  motion  were 
known  to  Galileo.  That  he  had  formed  the  concep- 
tion which  we  shall  now  give,  or  that  at  least  he  was 
on  the  verge  of  so  doing,  may  be  inferred  from  many 
scattered  allusions  to  the  subject  in  his  Dialogues,  The 
bob  of  a  simple  pendulum  of  length  /  moves  in  a  circle 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  D  YNAMICS, 


163 


Fig.  107. 


(Fig.  107)  of  radius  /.   If  we  give  the  pendulum  a  very  Gauieps 

small  excursion,  it  will  travel  in  its  oscillations  over  ationofthe 

very  small  arc  which  coincides  approximately  with  the  pendaium. 

chord  belonging  to  it.    But  this 

chord  is  described  by  a  falling 

particle,  moving  oq  it  as  on  an 

inclined  plane  (see  Sect,  i  of  this 

Chapter,  §  7),  in  the  same  time 

as  the  vertical  diameter  BD  = 

2/.     If  the  time  of  descent  be 

called   /,  we   shall    have  2/  = 

\gt  2,  that  is  /  =  2  VTJg^     But 

since  the  continued  movement 

from  B  up  the  line  BC*  occupies  an  equal  interval  of 

time,  we  have  to  put  for  the  time  T  of  an  oscillation 

from  Cto  C\  T^=  \V Ijg^   It  will  be  seen  that  even  from 

so  crude  a  conception  as  this  the  correct  form  of  the 

pendulum-laws  is  obtainable.     The  exact  expression 

for  the  time  of  very  small  oscillations  is,  as  we  know, 

T=nvJlJ. 

Again,  the  motion  of  a  pendulum  bob  may  be  viewed  pendaium 
as  a  motion  of  descent  on  a  succession  of  inclined  wewed  as  a 
planes.   If  the  string  of  the  pendulum  makes  the  angle  SoUn  Ui- 
a  with  the  perpendicular,  the  pendulum  bob  receives  pi^iCTes. 
in  the  direction  of  the  position  of  equilibrium  the  accel- 
eration g,  sin  a.    When  a  is  small,  ^.  or  is  the  expres- 
sion of  this  acceleration  ;  in  other  words,  the  accelera- 
tion is  always  proportional  and  oppositely  directed  to 
the  excursion.     When  the  excursions  are  small  the 
curvature  of  the  path  may  be  neglected. 

8.  From  these  preliminaries,  we  may  proceed  to 
the  study  of  oscillatory  motion  in  a  simpler  manner.  A 
body  is  free  to  move  on  a  straight  line  OA  (Fig.  108), 
and  constantly  receives  in  the  direction  towards  the 


164 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 


A 

f^    '   y^ 

eye 

y 

y' 

A', 

II       y^ 

y 

y 

y 

y^o' 

B'A 

Fig.  108. 


A  simpler    point  O  an  acceleration  proportional  to  its  distance  from 

view  of  OS-  O,    We  will  represent  these  accelerations  by  ordinates 

motion.      erected  at  the  positions  considered.  Ordinates  upwards 

denote  accelerations  towards  the  left ;  ordinates  down- 

wards  represent  accel- 
erations towards  the 
right.  The  body,  left 
to  itself  at  A,  will 
move  towards  O  with 
varied  acceleration, 
"B^A'  P^ss  through  OioA^^ 
where  OA^  =  OA^ 
come  back  to  O,  and 
so  again  continue  its 
motion.  It  is  in  the 
The  period  first  place  easily  demonstrable  that  the  period  of  os- 
tioninde-  cillatiou  (the  time  of  the  motion  through  AOA^)  is  in- 
the  ampii-  dependent  of  the  amplitude  of  the  oscillation  (the  dis- 
tance OA).  To  show  this,  let  us  imagine  in  I  and 
II  the  same  oscillation  performed,  with  single  and 
double  amplitudes  of  oscillation.  As  the  acceleration 
varies  from  point  to  point,  we  must  divide  OA  and 
CA'  :=20A  into  a  very  large  equal  number  of  ele- 
ments. Each  element  A'B'  of  CyA'  is  then  twice  as 
large  as  the  corresponding  element  AB  of  OA.  The 
initial  accelerations  (p  and  (p'  stand  in  the  relation 
(p'  =  2^}.  Accordingly,  the  elements  AB  and  A'B*  = 
2  AB  are  described  with  their  respective  accelerations 
(p  and  2(p  im,  the  same  time  r.  The  final  velocities  v 
and  v'  in  I  and  II,  for  the  first  element,  will  bev  =  (pr 
and  v'  =  2(pXy  that  is  z/'  =  2  v.  The  accelerations  and 
the  initial  velocities  at  B  and  B'  are  therefore  again  as 
1 : 2.  Accordingly,  the  corresponding  elements  that 
next  succeed  will  be  described  in  the  same  time.    And 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  D  YNAMICS. 


165 


of  every  succeeding  pair  of  elements  the  same  asser- 
tion also  holds  true.  Therefore,  generalising,  it  will 
be  readily  perceived  that  the  period  of  oscillation  is 
independent  of  its  amplitude  or  breadth. 

Next,  let  us  conceive  two  oscillatory  motions,  I  and  The  time  of 

.  .  oscillation 

II,  that  have  equal  excursions  (Fig.  log);  but  in  II  let  inversely 

,  proportion- 

a  fourfold  acceleration  correspond  to  the  same  distance  ai  to  the 

sauare  root 
of  the  ac- 
celeration. 


I 


^-r^ 


\^^o 

BA 

A 

II     / 

/ 

/O' 

BA' 

Fig.  X09. 


from  O,  We  divide  the  amplitudes  of 
the  oscillations  AO  and  OA*  =  OA 
into  a  very  large  equal  number  of 
parts.  These  parts  are  then  equal  in 
I  and  II.  The  initial  accelerations  at 
A  and  A*  are  <p  and  4  (p ;  the  ele- 
ments of  the  distance  described  are 
AB  =  A'B*  =  j;  and  the  times  are 
respectively  r  and  r*.  We  obtain,  then, 
r  =  \/2s/<p,  T*  =  1/2  j/4  (p  =  t/2. 
The  element  A'B*  is  accordingly  trav- 
elled through  in  one-half  the  time 
the  element  AB  is.  The  final  velocities  v  and  v'  at 
B  and  B  are  found  by  the  equations  v  ^=  <pr  and 
z;'  =  4  q}(j/2)  =:2v.  Since,  therefore,  the  initial  velo- 
cities at  B  and  B  are  to  one  another  as  i :  2,  and  the 
accelerations  are  again  as  1:4,  the  element  of  II  suc- 
ceeding the  first  will  again  be  traversed  in  half  the 
time  of  the  corresponding  one  in  I.  Generalising,  we 
get :  For  equal  excursions  the  time  of  oscillation  is  in- 
versely proportional  to  the  square  root  of  the  accelera- 
tions. 

9.  The  considerations  last  presented  may  be  put  in 
a  very  much  abbreviated  and  very  obvious  form  by  a 
method  of  conception  first  employed  by  Newton.  New; 
ton  calls  those  material  systems  similar  that  have  geo- 
metrically similar  configurations  and  whose  homolo- 


i66  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

The  Diinci-  gous  masses  bear  to  one  another  the  same  ratio.  He 
Uude.  says  further  that  systems  of  this  kind  execute  similar 
movements  when  the  homologous  points  describe  simi- 
lar paths  in  proportional  times.  Conformably  to  the 
geometrical  terminology  of  the  present  day  we  should 
not  be  permitted  to  call  mechanical  structures  of  this 
kind  (of  five  dimensions)  similar  unless  their  homolo- 
gous linear  dimensions  as  well  as  the  times  and  the 
masses  bore  to  one  another  the  same  ratio.  The  struc- 
tures might  more  appropriately  be  termed  affined  to 
one  another. 

We  shall  retain,  however,  the  name  phoronomically 
similar  structures,  and  in  the  consideration  that  is  to 
follow  leave  entirely  out  of  account  the  masses. 
In  two  such  similar  motions,  then,  let 

the  homologous  paths  be  s  and  as^ 

the  homologous  times  be  /  and  ftt\  whence 

the  homologous  velo- 


cities are   z/  =  -  and  yz;  =  —  — , 

/  at 


the  homologous  accel-  ^  « 

erations y,  =  ^_  and  £^  =  — — . 

Thededac-  Now  all  oscillations  which  a  body  performs  under 
laws  of  o^  the  conditions  above  set  forth  with  any  two  different 
this^metho^  amplitudes  I  and  a,  will  be  readily  recognised  as  sim- 
ilar  motions.  Noting  that  the  ratio  of  the  homologous 
accelerations  in  this  case  is  f  =  at,  we  have  a  =  a/ft^. 
Wherefore  the  ratio  of  the  homologous  times,  that  is 
to  say  of  the  times  of  oscillation,  is  )5  =  zfc  i.  We  ob- 
tain thus  the  law,  that  the  period  of  oscillation  is  inde- 
pendent of  the  amplitude. 

If  in  two  oscillatory  motions  we  put  for  the  ratio 
between  the  amplitudes  i  :  a,  and  for  the  ratio  between 
the  accelerations  i :  a/i,  we  shall  obtain  for  this  case 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  D  YNAMICS. 


167 


£==  ar;i=  a/fi^y  and  therefore  )5=  i/zt  ^/  /i ;  where- 
with the  second  law  of  oscillating  motion  is  obtained. 

Two  uniform  circular  motions  are  always  phoronom- 
ically  similar.  Let  the  ratio  of  their  radii  be  i  :  a  and 
the  ratio  of  their  velocities  i  :  y.  The  ratio  of  their 
accelerations  is  then  £=  flf//?*,  and  since  y=a/fi, 
3\so€=i  y^/a ;  whence  the  theorems  relative  to  cen- 
tripetal acceleration  are  obtained. 

It  is  a  pity  that  investigations  of  this  kind  respect- 
ing mechanical  and  phoronomical  affinity  are  not  more 
extensively  cultivated,  since  they  promise  the  most 
beautiful  and  most  elucidative  extensions  of  insight 
imaginable. 

10.  Between  uniform  motion  in  a  circle  and  oscil- 
latory motion  of  the  kind  just  discussed  an  important 
relation  exists  which  we  shall  now  consider.  We  as- 
sume a  system  of  rectangular  co- 
ordinates, having  its  origin  at  the 
centre,  Oy  of  the  circle  of  Fig.  no, 
about  the  circumference  of  which 
we  conceive  a  body  to  move  uni- 
formly. The  centripetal  accelera- 
tion q>  which  conditions  this  mo- 
tion, we  resolve  in  the  directions 
of  X  and  Y\  and  observe  that  the  -Y-components  of  the 
motion  are  affected  only  by  the  A'-components  of  the 
acceleration.  We  may  regard  both  the  motions  and 
both  the  accelerations  as  independent  of  each  other. 

Now,  the  two  components  of  the  motion .  are  os- 
cillatory motions  to  and  fro  about  O.  To  the  excur- 
sion X  the  acceleration-component  q)  (jx/r)  or  (^<pfr)  x 
in  the  direction  O,  corresponds.  The  acceleration  is 
proportionaly  therefore,  to  the  excursion.  And  accord- 
ingly the  motion  is  of  the  kind  just  investigated.    The 


The  con- 
nection be- 
tween oscil- 
latory mo- 
tion of  this 
kind  and 
nniform 
motion  in  a 
circle. 


The  iden- 
tity of  the 
two. 


i68  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

time  7*  of  a  complete  to  and  fro  movement  is  also  the 
periodic  time  of  the  circular  motion.     With  respect  to 
the  latter,  however,  we  know  that  ^=  ^rn^ /T^,  or, 
what  is  the  same,  that  T^=iin  \^r/(p.     Now  <p/r  is 
the  acceleration  for  j:=  i,  the  acceleration  that  corre- 
sponds to  unit  of  excursion,  which  we  shall  briefly 
designate  by  /.     For  the  oscillatory  motion  we  may 
put,  therefore,  T=z  2n\/i//,  For  a  single  movement 
to,  or  a  single  movement  fro, — the  common  method  of 
reckoning  the  time  of  oscillation, «— we  get,  then,  Tz=z 
nVTif, 
The  appu-         1 1  •   Now  this  result  is  directly  applicable  to  pen- 
the  lasfre-  dulum  vibratious  of  very  small  excursions,  where,  ne- 
duium^"  glecting  the  curvature  of  the  path,  it  is  possible  to  ad- 
ra  ions,     j^^^.^  ^^  ^^  conception  developed.     For  the  angle  of 

elongation  a  we  obtain  as  the  distance  of  the  pendulum 
bob  from  the  position  of  equilibrium,  la ;  and  as  the 
corresponding  acceleration,  ga\  whence 

/=^-^  =  -5andr=;rJ-^. 
''        la       I  \  g 

This  formula  tells  us,  that  the  time  of  vibration  is 
directly  proportional  to  the  square  root  of  the  length 
of  the  pendulum,  and  inversely  proportional  to  the 
square  root  of  the  acceleration  of  gravity.  A  pendulum 
that  is  four  times  as  long  as  the  seconds  pendulum, 
therefore,  will  perform  its  oscillation  in  two  seconds. 
A  seconds  pendulum  removed  a  distance  equal  to  the 
earth's  radius  from  the  surface  of  the  earth,  and  sub- 
jected therefore  to  the  acceleration  gl\^  will  likewise 
perform  its  oscillation  in  two  seconds. 

12.  The  dependence  of  the  time  of  oscillation  on 
the  length  of  the  pendulum  is  very  easily  verifiable  by 
experiment.     If   (Fig.    iii)   the   pendulums  a,   ^,  r, 


THE  PRIKCIPLES  OF  DYNAMICS.  169 

.  which  to  maintain  the  plane  of  oscillation  invariable  Sipninen- 
are  suspended  by  double  threads,  have  the  lengths  i,  tiaaoftbe 
4,  9,  then  a  will  execute  two  oscillations  to  one  oscil-  penduiam. 
lation  of  b,  and  three  to  one  of  c. 


The  verification  of  the  dependence  of  the  time  of 
oscillation  on  the  acceleration  of  gravity  g  is  some- 
what more  difficult ;  since  the  latter  cannot  be  arbi- 
trarily altered.  But  the  demonstration  can  be  effected 
by  allowing  one  component  only  of  g  to  act  on  the 
pendulum.      If  we  imagine  the  axis  of  oscillation  of 


I70  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

a-  the  pendulum  A  A  fixed  in  the  vertically  placed  plaae 

I  of  the  paper,  EE  will  be  the  intersection  of  the  plane 

A^p         of  oscillation  with  the  plane  of  the  paper 


y  ~~~^  and  likewise  the  position  of  equilibrium 

L  of  the  pendulum.      The  axis  makes  with 

/  the  horizontal  plane,  and  the  plane  of  os- 

/  cillation  makes  with  the  vertical  plane,  the 

^  angle /S;  wherefore  the  acceleration  ^.cos^ 

Fig.  III.       js  {hg  acceleration  which  acts  in  this  plane. 

!f  the  pendulum  receive  in  the  plane  of  its  oscillation 

the  small  elongation  a,  the  corresponding  acceleration 


■will  be  {g  cos  p)  a ;  whence  the  time  of  oscillation  ii 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  D  YNAMICS, 


171 


We  see  from  this  result,  that  as  fi  is  increased  the 
acceleration  g  cos  ft  diminishes,  and  consequently  the 
time  of  oscillation  increases.  The  experiment  may  be 
easily  made  with  the  apparatus  represented  in  Fig.  113. 
The  frame  RR  is  free  to  turn  about  a  hinge  at  C;  it  can 
be  inclined  and  placed  on  its  side.  The  angle  of  in- 
clination is  fixed  by  a  graduated  arc  G  held  by  a  set- 
screw.  Every  increase  of  ft  increases  the  time  of  oscil- 
lation. If  the  plane  of  oscillation  be  made  horizontal, 
in  which  position  R  rests  on  the  foot  F^  the  time  of 
oscillation  becomes  infinitely  great.  The  pendulum 
in  this  case  no  longer  returns  to  any  definite  position 
but  describes  several  complete  revolutions  in  the  same 
direction  until  its  entire  velocity  has  been  destroyed 
by  friction. 

13.  If  the  movement  of  the  pendulum  do  not  take  The  conical 
place  in  a  plane,  but  be  performed  in  space,  the  thread 
of  the  pendulum  will  describe  the  surface 
of  a  cone.  The  motion  of  the  conical  pen- 
dulum was  also  investigated  byHuygens. 
We  shall  examine  a  simple  case  of  this 
motion.   We  imagine  (Fig.  114)  a  pen- 
dulum of  length  /  removed  from  the  ver-  ^ 
tical  by  the  angle  or,  a  velocity  «;  imparted 
to  the  bob  of  the  pendulum  at  right 
angles  to  the  plane  of  elongation,  and  the  pendulum  re- 
leased.   The  bob  of  the  pendulum  will  move  in  a  hori- 
zontal circle  if  the  centrifugal  acceleration  cp  developed 
exactly  equilibrates  the  acceleration  of  gravity  g\  that 
is,  if  the  resultant  acceleration  falls  in  the  direction  of 
the  pendulum  thread.     But  in  that  case  <p/g=^  tan  or. 
If  7^  stands  for  the  time  taken  to  describe  one  revolu- 
tion, the  periodic  time,  then  ^  =  4r;r2/7^  or   7^  = 
2  7t  Vr/(p,     Introducing,  now,  in  the  place  of  r/(p  the 


Fig.  114. 


172  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

value  /  sin  ajg  tan  a  z=ii  cos  a/gy  we  get  for  the  periodic 
time  of  the  pendulum,  T:=2  7C  V  i  cos  a/g.   For  the  ve- 
locity V  of  the  revolution  we  find  v  =  l/r<^,  and  since 
(p  =  ^tan  a  it  follows  that  v  =  V^gl  sin  a  Ian  a.     For 
very  small  elongations  of  the  conical  pendulum  we  may 
put  Tz=in  V llg,  which   coincides  with  the  regular 
formula  for  the  pendulum,  when  we  reflect  that  a  single 
revolution  of  the  conical  pendulum  corresponds  to  two 
vibrations  of  the  common  pendulum. 
The  deter-         1 4.   Huygens  was  the  first  to  undertake  the  exact 
the  accei-    determination  of  the  acceleration  of  gravity  g  by  means 
gravity  by   of  pcudulum  observations.     From  the  formula  7*= 
lumf*"  "    n  V Tig  for  a  simple  pendulum  with  small  bob  we  ob- 
tain directly  ^=:  n^  IjT^,     For  latitude  45°  we  obtain 
as  the  value  of  g^  in  metres  and  seconds,  9 .  806.     For 
provisional  mental  calculations  it  is  sufficient  to  re- 
member that  the  acceleration  of  gravity  amounts  in 
round  numbers  to  10  metres  a  second. 
A  remark  1 5.  Every  thinking  beginner  puts  to  himself  the 

pia  express- question  how  it  is  that  the  duration  of  an  oscillation, 

iDflf  thfi  1a.w 

■  that  is  a  time^  can  be  found  by  dividing  a  number  that 
is  the  measure  of  a  length  by  a  number  that  is  the 
measure  of  an  acceleration  and  extracting  the  square 
root  of  the  quotient.  But  the  fact  is  here  to  be  borne  in 
mind  that^=2j//2,  that  is  a  length  divided  by  the 
square  of  a  time.  In  reality  therefore  the  formula  we 
have  is  7^=  n  '\/{l/2s)t^.  And  since  I /2  s  is  the  ratio 
of  two  lengths,  and  therefore  a  number,  what  we  have 
under  the  radical  sign  is  consequently  the  square  of  a 
time.  It  stands  to  reason  that  we  shall  find  T'in  sec- 
onds only  when,  in  determining  g,  we  also  take  the  sec- 
ond as  unit  of  time. 

In  the  formula  gz=zn^  IjT^  we  see  directly  that  g  is 


I 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  DYNAMICS.  173 

a  length  divided  by  the  square  of  a  time,  according  to 

the  nature  of  an  acceleration. 

16.  The  most  important  achievement  of  Huygens  The  prob- 
lem of  the 
is  his  solution  of  the  problem  to  determine  the  centre  centre  of 

oscillation. 

of  oscillation.  So  long  as  we  have  to  deal  with  the  dy- 
namics of  a  single  body,  the  Galilean  principles  amply 
suffice.  But  in  the  problem  just  mentioned  we  have  to 
determine  the  motion  of  several  bodies  that  mutually 
influence  each  other.  This  cannot  be  done  without 
resorting  to  a  new  principle.  Such  a  one  Huygens 
actually  discovered. 

We  know  that  long  pendulums  perform  their  oscil-  statement 

.of  the  prob- 

lations  more  slowly  than  short  ones.   Let  us  imagine  a  lem. 
heavy  body,  free  to  rotate  about  an  axis,  the  centre  of 
gravity  of  which  lies  outside  of  the  axis ;  such 
a  body  will  represent  a  compound  pendulum. 
Every  material  particle  of  a  pendulum  of  this 
kind  would,  if  it  were  situated  alone  at  the 
same  distance  from  the  axis,  have  its  own  pe- 
riod  of  oscillation.     But  owing  to  the  connec-  Fig.  ns. 
tions  of  the  parts  the  whole  body  can  vibrate  with  only 
a  single,  determinate  period  of  oscillation.     If  we  pic- 
ture to  ourselves  several  pendulums  of  unequal  lengths, 
the  shorter  ones  will  swing  quicker,  the  longer  ones 
slower.    If  all  be  joined  together  so  as  to  form  a  single 
pendulum,  it  is  to  be  presumed  that  the  longer  ones 
will  be  accelerated,  the  shorter  ones  retarded,  and  that 
a  sort  of  mean  time  of  oscillation  will  result.     There 
must  exist  therefore  a  simple  pendulum,  intermediate 
in  length  between  the  shortest  and  the  longest,  that 
has  the  same  time  of  oscillation  as  the  compound  pen- 
dulum.    If  we  lay  off  the  length  of  this  pendulum  on 
the  compound  pendulum,  we  shall  find  a  point  that  pre- 
serves the  same  period  of  oscillation  in  its  connection 


174  ^^^^  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

with  the  other  points  as  it  would  have  if  detached  and 
left  to  itself.  This  point  is  the  centre  of  oscillation. 
Mersenne  was  the  first  to  propound  the  problem  of 
determining  the  centre  of  oscillation.  The  solution  of 
Descartes,  who  attempted  it,  was,  however,  precipi- 
tate and  insufficient. 
Huy^ens's         1 7.   Huvgeus  was  the  first  who  gave  a  general  solu- 

SOlutlOn.  -r^         •   1  ▼▼  t  It        t  •  • 

tion.  Besides  Huygens  nearly  ail  the  great  inquirers 
of  that  time  employed  themselves  on  the  problem,  and 
we  may  say  that  the  most  important  principles  of  mod- 
ern mechanics  were  developed  in  connection  with  it. 

The  new  idea  from  which  Huygens  set  out,  and 
which  is  more  important  by  far  than  the  whole  prob- 
lem, is  this.  In  whatsoever  manner  the  material  par- 
ticles of  a  pendulum  may  by  mutual  interaction  modify 
each  other's  motions,  in  every  case  the  velocities  ac- 
quired in  the  descent  of  the  pendulum  can  be  such  only 
that  by  virtue  of  them  the  centre  of  gravity  of  the  par- 
ticles, whether  still  in  connection  or  with  their  connec- 
tions dissolved,  is  able  to  rise  just  as  high  as  the  point 
The  new  from  which  xtfelL  Huygens  found  himself  compelled, 
whfch^Huy-  ^Y  ^^  doubts  of  his  contemporaries  as  to  the  correct- 
Suced?''**^  ness  of  this  principle,  to  remark,  that  the  only  assump- 
tion implied  in  the  principle  is,  that  heavy  bodies  of 
themselves  do  not  move  upwards.  If  it  were  possible 
for  the  centre  of  gravity  of  a  connected  system  of  falling 
material  particles  to  rise  higher  after  the  dissolution 
of  its  connections  than  the  point  from  which  it  had 
fallen,  then  by  repeating  the  process  heavy  bodies 
could,  by  virtue  of  their  own  weights,  be  made  to  rise 
to  any  height  we  wished.  If  after  the  dissolution  of 
the  connections  the  centre  of  gravity  should  rise  to  a 
height  less  than  that  from  which  it  had  fallen,  we 
should  only  have  to  reverse  the  motion  to  produce  the 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  DYNAMICS,  175 

same  result.  What  Huygens  asserted,  therefore,  no 
one  had  ever  really  doubted ;  on  the  contrary,  every 
one  had  instinctively  perceived  it.  Huygens,  however, 
gave  this  instinctive  perception  an  abstract^  conceptual 
form.  He  does  not  omit,  moreover,  to  point  out,  on  the 
ground  of  this  view,  the  fruitlessness  of  endeavors  to 
establish  a  perpetual  motion.  The  principle  just  devel- 
oped will  be  recognised  as  a  generalisation  of  one  of  Ga- 
lileo's ideas, 

18.   Let  us  now  see  what  the  principle  accomplishes  Huygens's 

principle 

in  the  determination  of  the  centre  of  oscillation.     Let  applied- 
OA  (Fig.  116),  for  simplicity's  sake, 
be  a  linear  pendulum,  made  up  of  a 
large  number  of  masses  indicated  in 
the  diagram  by  points.     Set  free  at 
OA^  it  will  swing  through  B  to  0A\ 
where  AB  =  BA',     Its    centre    of 
gravity  S  will  ascend  just  as  high 
on  the  second  side  as  it  fell  on  the 
first.     From  this,  so  far,  nothing  would  follow.     But 
also,  if  we  should  suddenly,  at  the  position  OBy  re- 
lease the  individual  masses  from  their  connections,  the 
masses  could,  by  virtue  of  the  velocities  impressed  on 
them  by  their  connections,  only  attain  the  same  height 
with  respect  to  centre  of  gravity.    If  we  arrest  the  free 
outward-swinging  masses  at  the  greatest  heights  they 
severally  attain,  the  shorter  pendulums  will  be  found 
below  the  line  OA',  the  longer  ones  will  have  passed 
beyond  it,  but  the  centre  of  gravity  of  the  system  will 
be  found  on  OA'  in  its  former  position. 

Now  let  us  note  that  the  enforced  velocities  are 
proportional  to  the  distances  from  the  axis  ;  therefore, 
one  being  given,  all  are  determined,  and  the  height  of 
ascent  of  the  centre  of  gravity  given.     Conversely, 


1/6 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 


therefore,  the  velocity  of  any  material  particle  also  is 
determined  by  the  known  height  of  the  centre  of  grav- 
ity. But  if  we  know  in  a  pendulum  the  velocity  cor- 
responding to  a  given  distance  of  descent,  we  know  its 
whole  motion. 
Thede-  19.   Premising  these  remarks,  we  proceed  to  the 

tailed  reso-  . 

lution  of  the  problem  itself.   On  a  compound  linear  pendulum  (Fig. 

problein. 

117)  we  cut  off,  measuring  from  the  axis,  the 
portion  =1.  If  the  pendulum  move  from  its 
position  of  greatest  excursion  to  the  position 
of  equilibrium,  the  point  at  the  distance  =  i 
from  the  axis  will  fall  through  the  height  k. 
The  masses  m^  tn\  m"  ,  ,  ,  at  the  distances 
r,  r',  r"  .  .  .  will  fall  in  this  case  the  dis- 
tances rky  r'  ky  r'*  k ,  .  . ,  and  the  distance  of 
the  descent  of  the  centre  of  gravity  will  be : 


Fig.  X17. 


mrk  4-  m'r'k  -f  m**r"k  -f  .  .  .  _,^mr 
m  -\-  m'  -\-  m"  ^  .  .  ,  .  ^m 

Let  the  point  at  the  distance  i  from  the  axis  ac- 
quire, on  passing  through  the  position  of  equilibrium, 
the  velocity,  as  yet  unascertained,  v.  The  height  of 
its  ascent,  after  the  dissolution  of  its  connections,  will 
be  v^/2g.  The  corresponding  heights  of  ascent  of 
the  other  material  particles  will  then  be  {fvY/2g, 
(r'  v)  2/2^,  (r"  vy  /2g .  .  .  .  The  height  of  ascent  of  the 
centre  of  gravity  of  the  liberated  masses  will  be 


^g  ^g  ^g 


7^^  2mr^ 
—       2g  2  m 


fft  -\-  fn  -\-  tn   -f-  .  .  . 

By  Huygens's  fundamental  principle,  then^ 

v^  2mr^ 
2g  '2f^ 


2mr 


(«). 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  D  YNAMICS.  177 

From  this  a  relation  is  deducible  between  the  distance  of 
descent  k  and  the  velocity  v.  Since,  however,  all  pen- 
dulum motions  of  the  same  excursion  are  phoronomi- 
cally  similar,  the  motion  here  under  consideration  is, 
in  this  result,  completely  determined. 

To  find  the  length  of  the  simple  pendulum  that  has  The  length 

of  the  siixi' 

the  same  period  of  oscillation  as  the  compound  pen-  pie  iaoch- 

ronoQS 

dulum  considered,  be  it  noted  that  the  same  relation  penduiam. 
must  obtain  between  the  distance  of  its  descent  and  its 
velocity,  as  in  the  case  of  its  unimpeded  fall.     If  y  is 
the  length  of  this  pendulum,  ky  is  the  distance  of  its 
descent,  and  vy  its  velocity ;  wherefore 

y-tg-i^ w- 

Multiplying  equation  {a)  by  equation  (^)  we  obtain 

Js  mr 

Employing  the  principle  of  phoronomic  similitude,  solution  of 
we  may  also  proceed  in  this  way.     From  {a)  we  get     iem^7the 

principle  of 

"^Plf  unulitnde. 

A  simple  pendulum  of  length  i,  under  corresponding 
circumstances,  has  the  velocity 

Calling  the  time  of  oscillation  of  the  compound  pendu- 
lum y,  that  of  the  simple  pendulum  of  length  i  T^  = 
nV'i/gj  we  obtain,  adhering  to  the  supposition  of 
equal  excursions, 

--=:     » ;  wherefore  7^=  tt  a  —v.     -• 
T^        V  \  g2  m  r 


v=Vigk^ 


178  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

Hnygens's         20.  We  scc  without  difficulty  in  the  Huygenian 

principle  ..i,  ••  r  >  i  j--* 

Identical  principle  the  recognition  of  work  as  the  condition  de- 
principle  of  terminative  of  velocity^  or,  more  exactly,  the  condition 
determinative  of  the  so-called  vis  viva.  By  the  vis 
viva  or  living  force  of  a  system  of  masses  m^  m„ 
m,, .  .  .  .,  affected  with  the  velocities  v,  v„  v,, ,  .  ,  .,  we 
understand  the  sum  * 


The  fundamental  principle  of  Huygens  is  identical  with 
the  principle  of  vis  viva.  The  additions  of  later  in- 
quirers were  made  not  so  much  to  the  idea  as  to  the 
form  of  its  expression. 

If  we  picture  to  ourselves  generally  any  system  of 
weights/,/,,/,, .  .  .  .,  which  fall  connected  or  uncon- 
nected through  the  heights  h,  ^„  ^,, .  .  .  .,  and  attain 
thereby  the  velocities  v,  v„  v,, ,  .  .  .,  then,  by  the  Huy- 
genian conception,  a  relation  of  equality  exists  between 
the  distance  of  descent  and  the  distance  of  ascent  of  the 
centre  of  gravity  of  the  system,  and,  consequently,  the 
equation  holds 


V2 

2^ 

7/2 

2^ 

/+/  +  />" 

+  • 

1 

g 

2.  -^  . 

or  2/f/i  ■ 

If  we  have  reached  the  concept  of  "mass,"  which 
Huygens  did  not  yet  possess  in  his  investigations,  we 
may  substitute  iot  pjg  the  mass  m  and  thus  obtain  the 
form  '2ph=  ^2  mv^,  which  is  very  easily  generalised 
for  non-constant  forces. 

*  This  is  not  the  usual  definition  of  English  writers,  who  follow  the  older 
authorities  in  making  the  vis  viva  twice  this  quantity. — Trans. 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  DYNAMICS.  179 

21.  With  the  aid  of  the  principle  of  living  forces  General 

.  .  .  method  of 

we  can  determine  the  duration  of  the  infinitely  small  determin- 
ing the  pe- 

oscillations  of  any  pendulum  whatso-      / s^  nodofpen- 

tf      /  ^""^^       -       dnlnm  os- 

ever.     We  let  fall  from  the  centre  of     (  ^     \  ciUationa. 

gravity  s  (Fig.  1 18)  a  perpendicular  on 
the  axis ;  the  length  of  the  perpendic- 
ular is,  say,  a.  We  lay  off  on  this, 
measuring  from  the  axis,  the  length 
=  I.  Let  the  distance  of  descent  of 
the  point  in  question  to  the  position  of  ^**'  "®- 

equilibrium  be  ky  and  v  the  velocity  acquired.  Since 
the  work  done  in  the  descent  is  determined  by  the 
motion  of  the  centre  of  gravity,  we  have 

work  done  in  descent  =  vis  viva : 

akgM=^~gr-  2mr^, 

M  here  we  call  the  total  mass  of  the  pendulum  and 
anticipate  the  expression  vis  viva.  By  an  inference 
similar  to  that  in  the  preceding  case,  we  obtain  7'= 
n  V^mr^/agM' 

22.  We  see^.  that  the  duration  of  infinitely  small  The  two 

"*  determma- 

oscillations  of  any  pendulum  is  determined  by  two  fac-  tive factors, 
tors — by  the  value  of  the  expression  2mr^,  which 
Euler  called  the  moment  0/  inertia  and  which  Huygens 
had  employed  without  any  particular  designation,  and 
by  the  value  of  agM,  The  latter  expression,  which  we 
shall  briefly  term  the  statical  moment ,  is  the  product 
aP  oi  the  weight  of  the  pendulum  into  the  distance  of 
its  centre  of  gravity  from  the  axis.  If  these  two  values 
be  given,  the  length  of  the  simple  pendulum  of  the 
same  period  of  oscillation  (the  isochronous  pendulum) 
and  the  position  qf  the  centre  of  oscillation  are  deter- 
mined. 


z8o 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 


Fig.  1 19. 


r,  r 


n 


HajrgeoB's         Fof  the  determination  of  the  lengths  of  the  pendu- 

methodBof  lums  referred  to,  Huygens,  in  the  lack  of  the  analytical 

methods  later  discovered,  employed  a  very  ingenious 

geometrical  procedure,  which 
we  shall  illustrate  by  one  or 
two  examples.     Let  the  prob- 
lem be  to  determine  the  time 
of  oscillation  of  a  homogene- 
ous, material,  and  heavy  rec- 
tangle ABCD^   which  swings 
on  the  axis  AB  (Fig.    119). 
Dividing    the    rectangle    into 
minute  elements  of  zr^^ifyf,, 
/„....  having  the  distances 
from  the  axis,  the  expression  for  the 
length  of  the  isochronous  simple  pendulum,  or  the  dis- 
tance of  the  centre  of  oscillation  from  the  axis,  is  given 
by  the  equation 

A+/,  ^+/,^,  + 

Let  us  erect  on  A  BCD  at  C  and  D  the  perpendiculars 
CE'=^  DF^=^AC=^  BD  and  picture  to  ourselves  a 
homogeneous  wedge  ABCDEF,  Now  find  the  distance 
of  the  centre  of  gravity  of  this  wedge  from  the  plane 
through  AB  parallel  to  CDEF.  We  have  to  consider, 
in  so  doing,  the  tiny  columns /r,/,  r^yf^^r,^  .  .  .  .  and 
their  distances  r^r^^  r^^ .  ,  .  .  from  the  plane  referred 
to.  Thus  proceeding,  we  obtain  for  the  required  dis- 
tance of  the  centre  of  gravity  the  expression 

/r.  r+/,r,  .  r,  +/,,r, ,  .  r,,  +  .  ,  ,  . 

that  is,  the  same  expression  as  before.  The  centre  of 
oscillation  of  the  rectangle  and  the  centre  of  gravity  of 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  D  YNAMICS. 


i8i 


the  wedge  are  consequently  at  the  same  distance  from 
the  axis,  \AC. 

Following  out  this  idea,  we  readily  perceive  the  Analogous 
correctness  of  the  following  assertions.     For  a  homo-  tions  or  the 
geneous  rectangle  of  height  h  swinging  about  one  of  methods, 
its  sides,  the  distance  of  the  centre  of  gravity  from  the 
axis  is  h/2f  the  distance  of  the  centre  of  oscillation  |  h» 
For  a  homogeneous  triangle  of  height  h,  the  axis  of 
which  passes  through  the  vertex  parallel  to  the  base, 
the  distance  of  the  centre  of  gravity  from  the  axis  is 
\hf  the  distance  of  the  centre  of  oscillation  ^h.     Call- 
ing the  moments  of  inertia  of  the  rectangle  and  of  the 
triangle  J^,  J^'  ^^^  their  respective  masses  Af^^  J/^, 
we  get 


3 


2^» 
Consequently  ^  j  =  — -„-^ 


.   ^,  =  "2  '- 


By  this  pretty  geometrical  conception  many  prob- 
lems can  be  solved  that  are  to-day  treated — more  con- 
veniently it  is  true — by  routine  forms. 


Fig.  120.  Fig.  121. 

23.  We  shall  now  discuss  a  proposition  relating  to 
moments  of  inertia,  that  Huygens  made  use  of  in  a 
somewhat  different  form.  Let  O  (Fig.  121)  be  the 
centre  of  gravity  of  any  given  body.     Make  this  the 


i82  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

The  reia-    origin  of  a  system  of  rectangular  coordinates,  and  sup- 

tion  of  ino~ 

ments  of  in- pose  the  moment  of  inertia  with  reference  to  the  Z-axis 

ertia  re- 
ferred to     determined.    If  m  is  the  element  of  mass  and  r  its  dis- 

parallel 

axes.  tance  from  the  Z-axis,  then  this  moment  of  inertia  is 

^  =  2mr^,  We  now  displace  the  axis  of  rotation 
parallel  to  itself  to  (7,  the  distance  a  in  the  Jf-direction. 
The  distance  r  is  transformed,  by  this  displacement, 
into  the  new  distance  p,  and  the  new  moment  of 
inertia  is  ' 

0  =  2mp^  =  2m  [(^  —  ay  +y^']  =  2m  (jc*  +  y^)  — 
2a2mX'\'a^2m,  or,  since  2 m  (^x^ -\-y^)  ^  2 m r^  =^, 
calling  the  total  mass  M=  2m,  and  remembering  the 
property  of  the  centre  of  gravity  2mx  =  0, 

From  the  moment  of  inertia  for  one  axis  through  the 
centre  of  gravity,  therefore,   that  for  any  other  axis 
parallel  to  the  first  is  easily  derivable. 
Anappii-  24.  An  additional  observation  presents  itself  here. 

cation  of  ^  ■"^■^ 

thispropo-  The  distance  of  the  centre  of  oscillation  is  given  by 

sition.  ^  -^ 

the  equation  lz=,A-\-  a^M/aMy  where  z^.  My  and  a 
have  their  previous  significance.  The  quantitiess^  and 
M  are  invariable  for  any  one  given  body.  So  long 
therefore  as  a  retains  the  same  value,  /  will  also  remain 
invariable.  For  all  parallel  axes  situated  at  the  same 
distance  from  the  centre  of  gravity,  the  same  body  as 
pendulum  has  the  same  period  of  oscillation.  If  we 
put  ^/M=^  Xy  then 

/^ \-  a. 

a 

Now  since  /  denotes  the  distance  of  the  centre  of 
oscillation,  and  a  the  distance  of  the  centre  of  gravity 
from  the  axis,  therefore  the  centre  of  oscillation  is 
always  farther  away  from  the  axis  than  the  centre  of 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  D  YNAMICS.  183 

gravity  by  the  distance  x/a.  Therefore  x/a  is  the  dis- 
tance of  the  centre  of  oscillation  from  the  centre  of 
gravity.  If  through  the  centre  of  oscillation  we  place 
a  second  axis  parallel  to  the  original  axis,  a  passes 
thereby  into  x/a,  and  we  obtain  the  new  pendulum 
length 

X         a  a 

a 

The  time  of  oscillation  remains  the  same  therefore 
for  the  second  parallel  axis  through  the  centre  of  oscil- 
lation, and  consequently  the  same  also  for  every  par- 
allel axis  that  is  at  the  same  distance  x/a  from  the 
centre  of  gravity  as  the  centre  of  oscillation. 

The  totality  of  all  parallel  axes  corresponding  to 
the  same  period  of  oscillation  and  having  the  distances  a 
and  x/a  from  the  centre  of  gravity,  is  consequently  re- 
alised in  two  coaxial  cylinders.  Each  generating  line 
is  interchangeable  as  axis  with  every  other  generating 
line  without  affecting  the  period  of  oscillation. 

25.  To  obtain  a  clear  view  of  the  relations  subsist-  The  axial 
ing  between  the  two  axial  cylinders,  as  we  shall  briefly 
call  them,  let  us  institute  the  following  considerations^ 
We  put  A  z=k^M,  and  then 

a 
If  we  seek  the  a  that  corresponds  to  a  given  /,  and 
therefore  to  a  given  time  of  oscillation,  we  obtain 


=  i^^1-''- 


Generally  therefore  to  one  value  of  /  there  correspond 
two  values  of  a.  Only  where  V l^  /\  —  ^2  __  q^  that  is 
in  cases  in  which  1=  ik,  do  both  values  coincide  in 
a  =  k. 


184 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 


If  we  designate  the  two  values  of  a  that  correspond 
to  every  /,  by  a  and  /?,  then 

/= =    —  -  -  ,or 

flt  p 

The  deter-  If,  therefore,  in  any  pendulous  body  we  know  two  par- 

mmation  of  , 

the  preced- allel  axes  that  have  the  same  time  of  oscillation  and 

ing  factors  ,    z»  r 

by  a  geo-     different  distances  a  and  p  from  the  centre  of  gravity, 

metrical  .  .  '  ,  ,  •  / 

method,  as  IS  the  case  for  instance  where  we  are  able  to  give  the 
centre  of  oscillation  for  any  point  of  suspension,  we 
can  construct  k.     We  lay  off  (Fig.  122)  a  and  P  con- 


secutively on  a  straight  line,  describe  a  semicircle  on 
a  -\-  p  ^s  diameter,  and  erect  a  perpendicular  at  the 
point  of  junction  of  the  two  divisions  a  and  p.  On  this 
perpendicular  the  semicircle  cuts  oH  k.  If  on  the  other 
hand  we  know  k,  then  for  every  value  of  a,  say  A,  a 
value  fx  is  obtainable  that  will  give  the  same  period 
of  oscillation  as  X,  We  construct  (Fig.  123)  with  \ 
and  k  as  sides  a  right  angle,  join  their  extremities  by  a 
straight  line  on  which  we  erect  at  the  extremity  of  /&  a 
perpendicular  which  cuts  off  on  X  produced  the  por- 
tion jU. 

Now  let  us  imagine  any  body  whatsoever  (Fig.  124) 
with  the  centre  of  gravity  O,  We  place  it  in  the  plane 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  DYNAMICS.  185 

of  the  drawing,  and  make  it  swine  about  all  possible  An  iiiaitn- 
parallel  axes  at  right  angles  to  the  plane  of  the  paper,  idn. 
All  the  axes  that  pass  through  the  circle  tx  are,  we 
find,  with  respect  to  period  of  oscillation,  interchange- 
able with  each  other  and  also  with  those  that  pass 
through  the  circle  ji.  If  instead  of  a  we  take  a  smaller 
circle  X,  then  in  the  place  of  /?  we  shall  get  a  larger 


Fig.  Ill, 

circle.  }i.     Continuing  in  this  manner,  both  circles  ul- 
timately meet  in  one  with  the  radius  k. 

26.  We  have  dwelt  at  such  length  on  the  foregoing  Bec»pi«oi»- 
matters  for  good  reasons.  In  the  first  place,  they  have 
served  our  purpose  of  displaying  in  a  clear  light  the 
splendid  results  of  the  investigations  of  Huygens.  For 
all  that  we  have  given  is  virtually  contained,  though 
in  somewhat  different  form,  in  the  writings  of  Huygens, 


i86  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

or  is 'at  least  so  approximately  presented  in  them  that 
it  can  be  supplied  without  the  slightest  difficulty.  Only 
a  very  small  portion  of  it  has  found  its  way  into  our 
modern  elementary  text-books.  One  of  the  proposi- 
tions that  has  thus  been  incorporated  in  our  elemen- 
tary treatises  is  that  referring  to  the  convertibility  of 
the  point  of  suspension  and  the  centre  of  oscillation. 
The  usual  presentation,  however,  is  not  exhaustive. 
Captain  Kater,  as  we  know,  employed  this  principle 
for  determining  the  exact  length  of  the  seconds  pen- 
dulum. 
Function  of       The  points  raised  in  the  preceding  paragraphs  have 

the  nioniont 

of  inertia,  also  rendered  us  the  service  of  supplying  enlighten- 
ment as  to  the  nature  of  the  conception  '^ moment  of 
inertia."  This  notion  affords  us  no  insight,  in  point 
of  principle,  that  we  could  not  have  obtained  without 
it.  But  since  we  save  by  its  aid  the  individual  con- 
sideration of  the  particles  that  make  up  a  system,  or 
dispose  of  them  once  for  all,  we  arrive  by  a  shorter 
and  easier  way  at  our  goal.  This  idea,  therefore,  has 
a  high  import  in  the  economy  of  mechanics.  Poinsot, 
after  Euler  and  Segner  had  attempted  a  similar  object 
with  less  success,  further  developed  the  ideas  that  be- 
long to  this  subject,  and  by  his  ellipsoid  of  inertia  and 
central  ellipsoid  introduced  further  simplifications. 
The  lesser  27.  The  investigations  of  Huygens  concerning  the 
tfoM  of*  geometrical  and  mechanical  properties  of  cycloids  are 
of  less  importance.  The  cycloidal  pendulum,  a  contriv- 
ance in  which  Huygens  realised,  not  an  approximate, 
but  an  exact  independence  of  the  time  and  amplitude 
of  oscillation,  has  been  dropt  from  the  practice  of  mod- 
ern horology  as  unnecessary.  We  shall  not,  therefore, 
enter  into  these  investigations  here,  however  much  of 
the  geometrically  beautiful  they  may  present. 


Huygens. 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  D  YNAMICS.  187 

% 

Great  as  the  merits  of  Huygens  are  with  respect  to  Hnygens's 
the  most  different  physical  theories,  the  art  of  horology,  achieve- 
practical  dioptrics,  and  mechanics  in  particular,  his 
chief  performance,  the  one  that  demanded  the  greatest 
intellectual  courage,  and  that  was  also  accompanied 
with  the  greatest  results,  remains  his  enunciation  of  the 
principle  by  which  he  solved  the  problem  of  the  centre 
of  oscillation.  This  very  principle,  however,  was  the 
only  one  he  enunciated  that  was  not  adequately  appre- 
ciated by  his  contemporaries ;  nor  was  it  for  a  long 
period  thereafter.  We  hope  to  have  placed  this  prin- 
ciple here  in  its  right  light  as  identical  with  the  prin- 
ciple of  vis  viva, 

III. 

THE  ACHIEVEMENTS  OF  NEWTON. 

1.  The  merits  of  Newton  with  respect  to  our  sub-  Newton's 
ject  were  twofold.  First,  he  greatly  extended  the  range 

of  mechanical  physics  by  his  discovery  of  universal 
gravitation.  Second,  he  completed  the  formal  enunciation 
of  the  mechanical  principles  now  generally  accepted.  Since 
his  time  no  essentially  new  principle  has  been  stated. 
All  that  has  been  accomplished  in  mechanics  since  his 
day,  has  been  a  deductive,  formal,  and  mathematical 
development  of  mechanics  on  the  basis  of  Newton's 
laws. 

2.  Let  us  first  cast  a  glance  at  Newton's  achieve-  His  ^eat 
ment  in  the  domain  of  physics,  Kepler  had  deduced  discovery, 
from  the  observations  of  Tycho  Brahe  and  his  own, 

three  empirical  laws  for  the  motion  of  the  planets 
about  the  sun,  which  Newton  by  his  new  view  rendered 
intelligible.     The  laws  of  Kepler  are  as  follows  : 
i)  The  planets  move  about  the  sun  in  ellipses,  in 
one  focus  of  which  the  sun  is  situated. 


i88  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

Kepler's  2)  The  radius  vector  joining  each  planet  with  the 

law..  Their  ^  ,  ..  ,  •  w 

part inthe  sun  describes  equal  areas  m  equal  times. 

3)  The  cubes  of  the  mean  distances  of  the  planets 
from  the  sun  are  proportional  to  the  squares  of 
their  times  of  revolution. 
He  ivho  clearly  understands  the  doctrine  of  Galileo 
and  HuygenSy  must  see  that  a  curvilinear  motion  im- 
plies deflective  acceleration.   Hence,  to  explain  the  phe- 
nomena of  planetary  motion,  an  acceleration  must  be 
supposed  constantly  directed  towards  the  concave  side 
of  the  planetary  orbits. 
Central  ac-        Now  Kepler's  second  law,  the  law  of  areas,  is  ex- 

celeration        ,    .        ,  ,        ,  .  -  , 

explains     plained  at  once  by  the  assumption  of  a  constant  plane- 

Kepler's       ^  ,  •  j        ,  ,  ,  • 

aecond  law.  tary  acceleration  towards  the  sun  ;  or  rather,  this  ac- 
celeration is  another  form  of  expression  for  the  same 

fact.  If  a  radius  vector  describes 
in  an  element  of  time  the  area 
ABS  (Fig.  125),  then  in  the  next 
equal  element  of  time,  assuming 
no  acceleration,  the  area  BCS 
will  be  described,  where  BC  = 
AB  and  lies  in  the  prolongation 
Fig.  us.  of  AB,    But  if  the  central  accel- 

eration during  the  first  element  of  time  produces  a 
velocity  by  virtue  of  which  the  distance  BD  will  be 
traversed  in  the  same  interval,  the  next-succeeding 
area  swept  out  is  not  BCS^  but  BES,  where  CE  is  par- 
allel and  equal  to  BD,  But  it  is  evident  that  BES  = 
BCS  =  ABS,  Consequently,  the  law  of  the  areas  con- 
stitutes, in  another  aspect,  a  central  acceleration. 

Having  thus  ascertained  the  fact  of  a  central  accel- 
eration, the  third  law  leads  us  to  the  discovery  of  its 
character.  Since  the  planets  move  in  ellipses  slightly 
different  from  circles,  we  may  assume,  for  the  sake  of 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  DYNAMICS.  189 

simplicity,  that  their  orbits  actually  are  circles.    If  ^1,  The  formal 
R^y  R^  are  the  radii  and   T^^  T^^    T^  the  respective  of  this ac- 
times  of  revolution  of  the  planets,  Kepler's  third  law  deducibie 

,  .  -   ,,  from  Kep- 

may  be  written  as  follows  :  ler's  third 

law. 

R  ^       R  ^       R  ^ 

^=  7^  =  -^=..  =a  constant. 

But  we  know  that  the  expression  for  the  central  accel- 
eration of  motion  in  a  circle  is  (p=  \R7t^ /T^,  or 
7^  =  4  TT^  R/(p.     Substituting  this  value  we  get 

(p^R^^  ^=  (p^R^^  =  <^3 ^3^  =  constant ;  or 

<p  =  constant  /R"^  ; 

that  is  to  say,  on  the  assumption  of  a  central  accelera- 
tion inversely  proportional  to  the  square  of  the  distance, 
we  get,  from  the  known  laws  of  central  motion,  Kep- 
ler's third  law  ;  and  vice  versa. 

Moreover,  though  the  demonstration  is  not  easily 
put  in  an  elementary  form,  when  the  idea  of  a  central 
acceleration  inversely  proportional  to  the  square  of  the 
distance  has  been  reached,  the  demonstration  that  this 
acceleration  is  another  expression  for  the  motion  in 
conic  sections,  of  which  the  planetary  motion  in  ellipses 
is  a  particular  case,  is  a  mere  affair  of  mathematical 
analysis. 

3.   But  in  addition  to  the  intellectual  performance  The  qaes- 
just  discussed,  the  way  to  which  was  fully  prepared  by  physical 

character  of 

Kepler,  Galileo,  and  Huygens,  still  another  achieve- this  accei- 
ment  of  Newton  remains  to  be  estimated  which  in  no 
respect  should  be  underrated.  This  is  an  achievement 
of  the  imagination.  We  have,  indeed,  no  hesitation 
in  saying  that  this  last  is  the  most  important  of  all. 
Of  what  nature  is  the  acceleration  that  conditions  the 
curvilinear  motion  of  the  planets  about  the  sun,  and 
of  the  satellites  about  the  planets  ? 


I90  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

The  steps  Newton  oerceived,  with  great  audacity  of  thought, 

which  orig-  . 

inaiiy  led    and  first  in  the  instance  of  the  moon,  that  this  accel- 
the  idea  of  eration  differed  in  no  substantial  respect  from  the  ac- 

universal  ..-.-.,.  ,  , 

gravitation,  celeration  of  gravity  so  familiar  to  us.  It  was  prob- 
ably the  principle  of  continuity,  which  accomplished 
so  much  in  Galileo's  case,  that  led  him  to  his  dis- 
covery. He  was  wont — and  this  habit  appears  to  be 
common  to  all  truly  great  investigators — to  adhere  as 
closely  as  possible,  even  in  cases  presenting  altered 
conditions,  to  a  conception  once  formed,  to  preserve 
the  same  uniformity  in  his  conceptions  that  nature 
teaches  us  to  see  in  her  processes.  That  which  is  a 
property  of  nature  at  any  one  time  and  in  any  one 
place,  constantly  and  everywhere  recurs,  though  it 
may  not  be  with  the  same  prominence.  If  the  attrac- 
tion of  gravity  is  observed  to  prevail,  not  only  on  the 
surface  of  the  earth,  but  also  on  high  mountains  and  in 
deep  mines,  the  physical  inquirer,  accustomed  to  con- 
tinuity in  his  beliefs,  conceives  this  attraction  as  also 
operative  at  greater  heights  and  depths  than  those  ac- 
cessible to  us.  He  asks  himself.  Where  lies  the  limit 
of  this  action  of  terrestrial  gravity  ?  Should  its  action 
not  extend  to  the  moon  ?  With  this  question  the  great 
flight  of  fancy  was  taken,  of  which,  with  Newton's  in- 
tellectual genius,  the  great  scientific  achievement  was 
but  a  necessary  consequence. 
The  appii-  Newtou  discovered  first  in  the  case  of  the  moon  that 
this  idea  to  the  Same  acceleration  that  controls  the  descent  of  a 
of  the  moon,  stone  also  prevented  this  heavenly  body  from  moving 
away  in  a  rectilinear  path  from  the  earth,  and  that,  on 
the  other  hand,  its  tangential  velocity  prevented  it  from 
falling  towards  the  earth.  The  motion  of  the  moon 
thus  suddenly  appeared  to  him  in  an  entirely  new  light, 
but  withal  under  quite  familiar  points  of  view.     The 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  D  YNAMICS,  igi 

new  conception  was  attractive  in  that  it  embraced  ob- 
jects that  previously  were  very  remote,  and  it  was  con- 
vincing in  that  it  involved  the  most  familiar  elements. 
This  explains  its  prompt  application  in  other  fields  and 
the  sweeping  character  of  its  results. 

Newton  not  only  solved  by  his  new  conception  the  its  univer- 
sal applica- 

thousand  years'  puzzle  of  the  planetary  system,  buttiontoaii 

matter. 

also  furnished  by  it  the  key  to  the  explanation  of  a 
number  of  other  important  phenomena.  In  the  same 
way  that  the  acceleration  due  to  terrestrial  gravity  ex- 
tends to  the  moon  and  to  all  other  parts  of  space,  so  do 
the  accelerations  that  are  due  to  the  other  heavenly 
bodies,  to  which  we  must,  by  the  principle  of  contin- 
uity, ascribe  the  same  properties,  extend  to  all  parts 
of  space,  including  also  the  earth.  But  if  gravitation  is 
not  peculiar  to  the  earth,  its  seat  is  not  exclusively  in  the 
centre  of  the  earth.  Every  portion  of  the  earth,  how- 
ever small,  shares  it.  Every  part  of  the  earth  attracts, 
or  determines  an  acceleration  of,  every  other  part. 
Thus  an  amplitude  and  freedom  of  physical  view  were 
reached  of  which  men  had  no  conception  previously  to 
Newton's  time.  • 

A  long  series  of  propositions  respecting  the  action  The  sweep- 
of  spheres  on  other  bodies  situated  beyond,  upon,  or  ter  of  its  re- 
within  the  spheres ;  inquiries  as  to  the  shape  of  the 
earth,  especially  concerning  its  flattening  by  rotation, 
sprang,  as  it  were,  spontaneously  from  this  view.  The 
riddle  of  the  tides,  the  connection  of  which  with  the 
moon  had  long  before  been  guessed,  was  suddenly  ex- 
plained as  due  to  the  acceleration  of  the  mobile  masses 
of  terrestrial  water  by  the  moon. 

4.  The  reaction  of  the  new  ideas  on  mechanics  was 
a  result  which  speedily  followed.  The  greatly  varying 
accelerations  which  by  the  new  view  the  same  body  be- 


192  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

The  effect  came  affected  with  according  to  its  position  in  space, 
ideas  on  suggested  at  once  the  idea  of  variable  weight,  yet  also 
'  pointed  to  one  characteristic  property  of  bodies  which 
was  constant.  The  notions  of  mass  and  weight  were 
thus  first  clearly  distinguished.  The  recognised  vari- 
ability of  acceleration  led  Newton  to  determine  by  spe- 
cial experiments  the  fact  that  the  acceleration  of  gravity 
is  independent  of  the  chemical  constitution  of  bodies ; 
whereby  new  positions  of  vantage  were  gained  for  the 
elucidation  of  the  relation  of  mass  and  weight,  as  will 
presently  be  shown  more  in  detail.  Finally,  the  uni- 
versal applicability  of  Galileo's  idea  of  force  was  more 
palpably  impressed  on  the  mind  by  Newton's  perform- 
ances than  it  ever  had  been  before.  People  could  •  no 
longer  believe  that  this  idea  was  alone  applicable  to  the 
phenomenon  of  falling  bodies  and  the  processes  most 
immediately  connected  therewith.  The  generalisation 
was  effected  as  of  itself,  and  without  attracting  partic- 
ular attention.  ^ 
Newton's  5.  Let  US  now  discuss,  more  in  detail,  the  achieve- 
ments in  ments  of  Newton  as  they  bear  upon  the  principles  of 
of  mechan-  mechanics.  In  so  doing/  we  shall  first  devote  ourselves 
exclusively  to  Newton's  ideas,  seek  to-  bring  them  for- 
cibly home  to  the  reader's  mind,  and  restrict  our  criti- 
cisms wholly  to  preparatory  remarks,  reserving  the 
criticism  of  details  for  a  subsequent  section.  On  pe- 
rusing Newton's  work  {J^hilosophice  Naturalis  Principia 
Mathematica,  London,  1687),  the  following  things 
strike  us  at  once  as  the  chief  advances  beyond  Galileo 
and  Huygens : 

i)  The  generalisation  of  the  idea  of  force. 

2)  The  introduction  of  the  concept  of  mass. 

3)  The  distinct  and  general  formulation  of  the  prin- 
ciple of  the  parallelogram  of  forces. 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  D  YNAMICS.  193 

4)  The  statement  of  the  law  of  action  and  reaction. 
6.   With  respect  to  the  first  point  little  is  to  beHUattitade 
added  to  what  has  already  been  said.     Newton  con-  to  the  idea 

...  ,  .         .  -  .  offeree. 

ceives  all  circumstances  determinative  of  motion, 
whether  terrestrial  gravity  or  attractions  of  planets,  or 
the  action  of  magnets,  and  so  forth,  as  circumstances 
determinative  of  acceleration.  He  expressly  remarks 
on  this  point  that  by  the  words  attraction  and  the  like 
he  does  not  mean  to  put  forward  any  theory  concern- 
ing the  cause  or  character  of  the  mutual  action  referred 
to,  but  simply  wishes  to  express  (as  modern  writers 
say,  in  a  differential  form)  what  is  otllerwise  expressed 
(that  is,  in  an  integrated  form)  in  the  description  of  the 
motion.  Newton's  reiterated  and  emphatic  protesta- 
tions that  he  is  not  concerned  with  hypotheses  as  to  the 
causes  of  phenomena,  but  has  simply  to  do  with  the 
investigation  and  transformed  statement  of  actual facts^ 
— a  direction  of  thought  that  is  distinctly  and  tersely 
uttered  in  his  words  ** hypotheses  non  fingo,"  *'I  do 
not  frame  hypotheses," — stamps  him  as  a  philosopher 
of  the  highest  rank.  He  is  not  desirous  to  astound  and  The  rcru- 
startle,  or  to  impress  the  imagination  by  the  originality  phandi. 
of  his  ideas :  his  aim  is  to  know  Nature,  * 

*  This  is  conspicacusly  shown  in  the  rules  that  Newton  formed  for  the 
conduct  of  natural  inquiry  (the  Regula  Pkilotopkandi) : 

"  Rule  I.  No  more  causes  of  natural  things  are  to  be  admitted  than  such 
as  truly  exist  and  are  sufficient  to  explain  the  phenomena  of  these  things. 

"  Rule  II.  Therefore,  to  natural  effects  of  the  same  kind  we  must,  as  far 
as  possible,  assign  the  same  causes;  e.  g.,  to  respiration  in  man  and  animals ; 
to  the  descent  of  stones  in  Europe  and  in  America ;  to  the  light  of  our  kitchen 
fire  and  of  the  sun ;  to  the  reflection  of  light  on  the  earth  and  on  the  planets. 

*'  Rnle  III.  Those  qualities  of  bodies  that  can  be  neither  increased  nor 
diminished,  and  which  are  found  to  belong  to  all  bodies  within  the  reach  of 
our  experiments,  are  to  be  regarded  as  the  universal  qualities  of  all  bodies. 
[Here  follows  the  enumeration  of  the  properties  of  bodies  which  has  been  in- 
corporated in  all  text-books.]  * 

**  If  it  universally  appear,  by  experiments  and  astronomical  observations, 
that  all  bodies  in  the  vicinity  of  the  earth  are  heavy  with  respect  to  the  earth, 
and  this  in  proportion  to  the  quantity  of  matter  which  they  severally  contain ; 


194 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 


The  New- 
tonian con- 
cept of 
mass. 


The  expe- 
riences 
which  point 
to  the  exist- 
ence of  such 
a  physical 
property. 


7.  With  regard  to  the  concept  of  '*  mass,"  it  is  to 
be  observed  that  the  formulation  of  Newton,  which  de- 
fines mass  to  be  the  quantity  of  matter  of  a  body  as 
measured  by  the  product  of  its  volume  and  density,  is 
unfortunate.  As  we  can  only  define  density  as  the  mass 
of  unit  of  volume,  the  circle  is  manifest.  Newton  felt 
distinctly  that  in  every  body  there  was  inherent  a  prop- 
erty whereby  the  amount  of  its  motion  was  determined 
and  perceived  that  this  must  be  different  from  weight. 
He  called  it,  as  we  still  do,  mass ;  but  he  did  not  suc- 
ceed in  correctly  stating  this  perception.  We  shall  re- 
vert later  on  to  this  point,  and  shall  stop  here  only  to 
make  the  following  preliminary'remarks. 

8.  Numerous  experiences,  of  which  a  sufficient  num- 
ber stood  at  Newton's  disposal,  point  clearly  to  the  ex- 
istence of  a  property  distinct  from  weight,  whereby  the 

quantity  of  motion  of  the 
body  to  which  it  belongs  is 
determined.  If  (Fig.  126) 
we  tie  a  fly-wheel  to  a  rope 
and  attempt  to  lift  it  by 
means  of  a  pulley,  we  feel 
the  weight  of  the  fly-wheel. 
If  the  wheel  be  placed 
on  a  perfectly  cylindrical  axle  and  well  balanced,  it 
will  no  longer  assume  by  virtue  of  its  weight  any  de- 
terminate position.     Nevertheless,  we  are  sensible  of 

that  the.moon  is  heavy  with  respect  to  the  earth  in  the  proportion  of  its  mass, 
and  our  seas  with  respect  to  the  moon ;  and  all  the  planets  with  respect  to  one 
another,  and  the  comets  also  with  respect  to  the  sun ;  we  must,  in  conformity 
with  this  rule,  declare,  that  all  bodies  are  heavy  with  respect  to  one  another. 

'*  Rule  IV.  In  experimental  phsrsics  pifepositions  collected  by  induction 
from  phenomena  are  to  be  regarded  either  as  accurately  true  or  very  nearly 
true,  notwithstanding  any  contrary  hypotheses,  till  other  phenomena  occur,  by 
which  they  are  made  more  accurate,  or  are  rendered  subject  to  exceptions. 

"This  rule  must  be  adhered  to,  that  the  results  of  induction  may  not  be 
annulled  by  hypotheses." 


d 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  D  YNAMICS.  195 

a  powerful  resistance  the  moment  we  endeavor  to  set  Maaa  dis- 
tinct froin 
the  wheel  in  motion  or  attempt  to  stop  it  when  in  mo-  weight. 

tion.  This  is  the  phenomenon  that  led  to  the  enuncia- 
tion of  a  distinct  property  of  matter  termed  inertia,  or 
'* force"  of  inertia — a  step  which,  as  we  have  already 
seen,  and  shall  further  explain  below  is  unnecessary. 
Two  equal  loads  simultaneously  raised,  offer  resistance 
by  their  weight.  Tied  to  the  extremities  of  a  cord  that 
passes  over  a  pulley,  they  offer  resistance  to  any  mo- 
tion, or  rather  to  any  change  of  velocity  of  the  pulley, 
by  their  mass.  A  large  weight  hung  as  a  pendulum 
on  a  very  long  string  can  be  held  at  an  angle  of  slight 
deviation  from  the  line  of  equilibrium  with  very  little 
effort.  The  weight-component  that  forces  the  pendu- 
lum into  the  position  of  equilibrium,  is  very  small. 
Yet  notwithstanding  this  we  shall  experience  a  con- 
siderable resistance  if  we  suddenly  attempt  to  move  or 
stop  the  weight.  A  weight  that  is  just  supported  by  a 
balloon,  although  we  have  no  longer  to  overcome  its 
gravity,  opposes  a  perceptible  resistance  to  motion. 
Add  to  this  the  fact  that  the  same  body  experiences  in 
different  geographical  latitudes  and  in  different  parts 
of  space  very  unequal  gravitational  accelerations  and 
we  shall  clearly  recognise  that  mass  exists  as  a  property 
wholly  distinct  from  weight  determining  the  amount  of 
acceleration  which  a  given  force  communicates  to  the 
body  to  which  it  belongs. 

9.  Important  is  Newton'^  demonstration  that  the  Mass  meas- 
mass  of  a  body  may,  nevertheless,  under  certain  con-  weight, 
ditions,  be  measured  by  its  weight.  Let  us  suppose  a 
body  to  rest  on  a  support,  on  which  it  exerts  by  its  weight 
a  pressure.  The  obvious  inference  is  that  2  or  3  such 
bodies,  or  one-half  or  one-third  of  such  a  body,  will  pro- 
duce a  corresponding  pressure  2,  3,  ^,  or  \  times  as 


/ 


196 


TlfE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 


The  prere- 
quisites of 
the  meas- 
urement of 
mass  by 
weight. 


Newton's 
establish- 
ment of 
these  pre- 
requisites. 


I    1    I 


a 


Fig.  \vj. 


great.  If  we  imagine  the  acceleration  of  descent  in- 
creased, diminished,  or  wholly  removed,  we  shall  ex- 
pect that  the  pressure  also  will  be  increased,  dimin- 
ished, or  wholly  removed.  We  thus  see^  that  the  pres- 
sure attributable  to  weight  increases,  decreases,  and 

vanishes  along  with  the  **  quan- 
tity of  matter "  and  the  magni- 
tude of  the  acceleration  of  de- 
scent. In  the  simplest  manner 
imaginable  we  conceive  the  pres- 
sure/ as  quantitatively  representable  by  the  product  of 
the  quantity  of  matter  m  into  the  acceleration  of  descent 
g — by  f=zmg.  Suppose  now  we  have  two  bodies  that 
exert  respectively  the  weight-pressures  /,  /',  to  which 
we  ascribe  the  "  quantities  of  matter ' '  «r,  m\  and  which 
are  subjected  to  the  accelerations  of  descent  g,  g'\  then 
/  =  mg  and  p'  =  m  g.  If,  now,  we  were  able  to  prove, 
that,  independently  of  the  material  (chemical)  compo- 
sition of  bodies,  g  =  g'  at  every  same  point  on  the 
earth's  surface,  we  should  obtain  m/m'  =p/p'\  that  is 
to  say,  on  the  same  spot  of  the  earth's  surface,  it  would 
be  possible  to  measure  mass  by  weight. 

Now  Newton  established  this  fact,  that  g  is  inde- 
pendent of  the  chemical  composition  of  bodies,  by 
experiments  with  pendulums  of  equal  lengths  but  dif- 
ferent material,  which  exhibited  equal  times  of  oscilla- 
tion. He  carefully  allowed,  in  these  experiments,  for 
the  disturbances  due  to  the  resistance  of  the  air ;  this 
last  factor  being  eliminated  by  constructing  from  differ- 
ent materials  spherical  pendulum-bobs  of  exactly  the 
same  size,  the  weights  of  which  were  equalised  by  ap- 
propriately hollowing  the  spheres.  Accordingly,  all 
bodies  may  be  regarded  as  affected  with  the  same  gy  and 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  D  YNAMICS.  197 

their  quantity  of  matter  or  mass  can,  as  Newton  pointed 
out,  be  measured  by  their  weight. 

If  we  imagine  a  rigid  partition  placed  between  an  Supp!e- 
assemblage  of  bodies  and  a  magnet,  the  bodies,  if  the  considera- 
magnet  be  powerful  enough,  or  at  least  the  majority 
of  the  bodies,  will  exert  a  pressure  on  the  partition. 
But  it  would  occur  to  no  one  to  employ  this  magnetic 
pressure,  in  the  manner  we  employed  pressure  due  to 
weight,  as  a  measure  of  mass.  The  strikingly  notice- 
able inequality  of  the  accelerations  produced  in  the 
different  bodies  by  the  magnet  excludes  any  such  idea. 
The  reader  will  furthermore  remark  that  this  whole 
argument  possesses  an  additional  dubious  feature,  in 
that  the  concept  of  mass  which  up  to  this  point  has 
simply  been  named  and  feit  as  a  necessity,  but  not  de- 
fined, is  assumed  by  it. 

10.  To  Newton  we  owe  the  distinct  formulation  ofihedoc- 
the  principle  of  the  composition  of  forces.*    If  a  body  composi- 
is  simultaneously  acted  on  by  two  forces  (Fig.  1 28),  forces, 
of  which  one  would  produce  the 
motion  AB  and    the  other    the 
motion  AC  in  the  same  interval 
of  time,  the  body,  since  the  two 
forces  and  the  motions  produced  ^**'  '*^* 

by  them  are  independent  of  each  other,  will  move  in  that 
interval  of  time  to  AD.  This  conception  is  in  every 
respect  natural,  and  distinctly  characterises  the  essen- 
tial point  involved.  It  contains  none  of  the  artificial 
and  forced  characters  that  were  afterwards  imported 
into  the  doctrine  of  the  composition  of  forces. 

We  may  express  the  proposition  in  a  somewhat 

•  Roberval's  (x668)  achievements  with  respect  to  the  doctrine  of  the  com- 
position  of  forces  are  also  to  be  mentioned  here.  Varignon  and  Lami  have  al- 
ready bean  referred  to.    (See  the  text,  page  36.) 


( 


198  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

Diftcusaion  different  manner,  and  thus  bring  it  nearer  its  modem 
trine  of  the  form.     The  accelerations  that  different  forces  impart 

compost-  _  -       ,  ,  .  ,  - 

tion  of        to  the  same  body  are  at  the  same  time  the  measure  of 

forces 

these  forces.  But  the  paths  described  in  equal  times 
are  proportional  to  the  accelerations.  Therefore  the 
latter  also  may  serve  as  the  measure  of  the  forces.  We 
may  say  accordingly  :  If  two  forces,  which  are  propor- 
tional to  the  lines  AB  and  AC^  act  on  a  body  A  in  the 
directions  AB  and  -^  C,  a  motion  will  result  that  could 
also  be  produced  by  a  third  force  acting  alone  in  the 
direction  of  the  diagonal  of  the  parallelogram  con- 
structed on  AB  and  AC  and  proportional  to  that  di- 
agonal. The  latter  force,  therefore,  may  be  substituted 
for  the  other  two.  Thus,  if  q)  and  ^  are  the  two  ac- 
celerations set  up  in  the  directions  AB  and  A  C,  then 
for  any  definite  interval  of  time  /,  AB  =  q)t^ /2,  AC=- 
tl)  t^ /2.  If,  now,  we  imagine-^/?  produced  in  the  same 
interval  of  time  by  a  single  force  determining  the  accel- 
eration Xi  we  get 

AD  =  a:^2/2,  and  AB  :  AC:  AD  =  (p  :  tf^  \  x- 
As  soon  as  we  have  perceived  the  fact  that  the  forces  are 
independent  of  each  other,  the  principle  of  the  paral- 
lelogram of  forces  is  easily  reached  from  Galileo's  no- 
tion of  force.     Without  the  assumption  of  this  inde- 
pendence any  effort  to  arrive  abstractly  and  philosoph- 
ically at  the  principle,  is  in  vain. 
The  law  of         II.   Perhaps  the  most  important  achievement  of 
reaction.     Newton  with  rcspcct  to  the  principles  is  the  distinct 
and  general  formulation  of  the  law  of  the  equality  of 
action  and  reaction,  of  pressure  and  counter-pressure. 
Questions  respecting  the  motions  of  bodies  that  exert 
a  reciprocal  influence  on  each  other,  cannot  be  solved 
by  Galileo's  principles  alone.     A  new  principle  is  ne- 
cessary that  will  define  this  mutual  action.     Such  a 


TFIE  PRINCIPLES  OF  DYNAMICS.  199 

principle  was  that  resorted  to  by  Huygens  in  his  inves- 
tigation of  the  centre  of  oscillation.  Such  a  principle 
also  is  Newton's  law  of  action  and  reaction. 

A  body  that  presses  or  pulls  another  body  is,  ac-  Newton's 

^.  deduction 

cording  to  Newton,  pressed  or  pulled  in  exactly  the  of  the  law 

T  ,        ,  1         ,      ,        ^  1  of  action 

same  degree  by  that  other  body.  Pressure  and  counter-  and  reac- 
pressure,  force  and  counter-force,  are  always  equal  to 
each  other.  As  the  measure  of  force  is  defined  by 
Newton  to  be  the  quantity  of  motion  or  momentum 
(mass  X  velocity)  generated  in  a  unit  of  time,  it  conse- 
quently follows  that  bodies  that  act  on  each  other  com- 
municate to  each  other  in  equal  intervals  of  time  equal 
and  opposite  quantities  of  motion  ( momenta),  or  re- 
ceive contrary  velocities  reciprocally  proportional  to 
their  masses. 

Now,  although  Newton's  law,  in  the  form  here  ex-  The  rela- 
tive imme- 
pressed,  appears  much  more  simple,  more  immediate,  diacy  or^ 

and  at  first  glance  more  admissible  than  that  of  Huy-  and  Huy- 

.„,,,,.,  .       ,         gens's  pria- 

gens,  It  will  be  found  that  it  by  no  means  contains  less  cipies. 
unanalysed  experience  or  fewer  instinctive  elements. 
Unquestionably  the  original  incitation  that  prompted 
the  enunciation  of  the  principle  was  of  a  purely  instinc- 
tive nature.  We  know  that  we  do  not  experience  any 
resistance  from  a  body  until  we  seek  to  set  it  in  motion. 
The  more  swiftly  we  endeavor  to  hurl  a  heavy .  stone 
from  us,  the  more  our  body  is  forced  back  by  it.  Pres- 
sure and  counter-pressure  go  hand  in  hand.  The  as- 
sumption of  the  equality  of  pressure  and  counter- pres- 
sure is  quite  immediate  if,  using  Newton's  own  illus- 
tration, we  imagine  a  rope  stretched  between  two  bod- 
ies, or  a  distended  or  compressed  spiral  spring  between 
them. 

There  exist  in  the  domain  of  statics  very  many  in- 
stinctive perceptions  that  involve  the  equality  of  pres- 


200  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

Statical  ex-  sure  and  counter-pressure.  The  trivial  experience  that 
which  point  one  cauuot  lift  one's  self  by  pulling  on  one's  chair  is 
enceof  the  of  this  character.     In  a  scholium  in  which  he  cites  the 

Irw 

physicists  Wren,  Huygens,  and  Wallis  as  his  prede- 
cessors in  the  employment  of  the  principle,  Newton 
puts  forward  similar  reflections.  He  imagines  the 
earth,  the  single  parts  of  which  gravitate  towards  one 
another,  divided  by  a  plane.  If  the  pressure  of  the 
one  portion  on  the  other  were  not  equal  to  the  counter- 
pressure,  the  earth  would  be  compelled  to  move  in  the 
direction  of  the  greater  pressure.  But  the  motion  of 
a  body  can,  so  far  as  our  experience  goes,  only  be  de- 
termined by  other  bodies  external  to  it.  Moreover, 
we  might  place  the  plane  of  division  referred  to  at  any 
point  we  chose,  and  the  direction  of  the  resulting  mo- 
tion, therefore,  could  not  be  exactly  determined. 
The  con-  12.  The  indistinctness  of  the  concept  of  mass  takes 

cept  of  mass 

in  its  con-    a  Very  palpable  form  when  we  attempt  to  employ  the 

oection 

wi^h  this  principle  of  the  equality  of  action  and  reaction  dynam- 
ically. Pressure  and  counter-pressure  may  be  equal. 
But  whence  do  we  know  that  equal  pressures  generate 
velocities  in  the  inverse  ratio  of  the  masses  ?  Newton, 
indeed,  actually  felt  the  necessity  of  an  experimental 
corroboration  of  this  principle.  He  cites  in  a  scholium, 
in  support  of  his  proposition,  Wren*s  experiments  on 
impact,  and  made  independent  experiments  himself. 
He  enclosed  in  one  sealed  vessel  a  magnet  and  in  an- 
other a  piece  of  iron,  placed  both  in  a  tub  of  water, 
and  left  them  to  their  mutual  action.  The  vessels  ap- 
proached each  other,  collided,  clung  together,  and  af- 
terwards remained  at  rest.  This  result  is  proof  of  the 
equality  of  pressure  and  counter-pressure  and  of  equal 
and  opposite  momenta  (as  we  shall  learn  later  on, 
when  we  come  to  discuss  the  laws  of  impact). 


law. 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  DYNAMICS.  201 

The  reader  has  already  felt  that  the  various  enunci-  The  merits 

.  ^Y  .  ,  11*       ^^^  defects 

ations  of  Newton  with  respect  to  mass  and  the  prm-  of  Newton's 
ciple  of  reaction,  hang  consistently  together,  and  that 
they  support  one  another.  The  experiences  that  lie  at 
their  foundation  are  :  the  instinctive  perception  of  the 
connection  of  pressure  and  counter-pressure ;  the  dis- 
cernment that  bodies  offer  resistance  to  change  of  ve- 
locity independently  of  their  weight,  but  proportion- 
ately thereto ;  and  the  observation  that  bodies  of  greater 
weight  receive  under  equal  pressure  smaller  velocities. 
Newton's  sense  of  ivhat  fundamental  concepts  and  prin- 
ciples were  required  in  mechanics  was  admirable.  The 
form  of  his  enunciations,  however,  as  we  shall  later  in- 
dicate in  detail,  leaves  much  to  be  desired.  But  we  have 
no  right  to  underrate  on  this  account  the  magnitude  of 
his  achievements ;  for  the  difficulties  he  had  to  conquer 
were  of  a  formidable  kind,  and  he  shunned  them  less 
than  any  other  investigator. 

IV. 

DISCUSSION  AND  ILLUSTRATION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLE  OF 

REACTION. 

I.  We  shall  now  devote  ourselves  a  moment  ex- The  princi- 
clusively  to  the  Newtonian  ideas,  and  seek  to  bring  the  Son? 
principle  of  reaction  more  clearly  home  to  our  mind 


m 


m 


0^ 


/  Fig.  109.  Fig.  130. 

and  feeling.  If  two  masses  (Fig.  129)  MsLud  m  act  on 
one  another,  they  impart  to  each  other,  according 
to  Newton,  contrary  velocities  V  and  z/,  which  are  in- 
versely proportional  to  their  masses,  so  that 


202  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

General  The  appearance  of  greater  evidence  may  be  im- 

elucidation 

of  the  orin-  parted  to  this  principle  by  the  following  consideration. 

action.  We  imagine  first  (Fig.  130)  two  absolutely  equal  bodies 
a^  also  absolutely  alike  in  chemical  constitution.  We 
set  these  bodies  opposite  each  other  and  put  them  in 
mutual  action ;  then,  on  the  supposition  that  the  in- 
fluences of  any  third  body  and  of  the  spectator  are  ex- 
cluded, the  communication  of  equal  and  contrary  velo- 
cities in  the  direction  of  the  line  joining  the  bodies  is 
the  sole  uniquely  determined  interaction. 

Now  let  us  group  together  in  A  (Fig.  131)  »«  such 
bodies  a,  and  put  at  B  over  against  them  m'  such 
bodies  a.   We  have  then  before  us  bodies  whose  quan- 


a 


a 


a 


a 


CSX50 


Fig.  131.  Fig.  13a. 

tities  of  matter  or  masses  bear  to  each  other  the  pro- 
portion m :  m'.  The  distance  between  the  groups  we 
assume  to  be  so  great  that  we  may  neglect  the  exten- 
sion of  the  bodies.  Let  us  regard  now  the  accelera- 
tions a,  that  every  two  bodies  a  impart  to  each  other, 
as  independent  of  each  other.  Every  part  of  Ay  then, 
will  receive  in  consequence  of  the  action  of  B  the  ac- 
celeration w'ar,  and  every  part  of  B  in  consequence  of 
the  action  of  A  the  acceleration  n^a — accelerations 
which  will  therefore  be  inversely  proportional  to  the 
masses. 

2.  Let  us  picture  to  ourselves  now  a  mass  M  (Fig. 
132)  joined  by  some  elastic  connection  with  a  mass  m, 
both  masses  made  up  of  bodies  a  equal  in  all  respects. 
Let  the  mass  m  receive  from  some  external  source  an 
acceleration  (p.  At  once  a  distortion  of  the  connection 
is  produced,  by  which  on  the  one  hand  m  is  retarded 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  D  YNAMICS.  203 

and  on  the  other  M  accelerated.     When  both  masses  The  deduc- 
have  begun  to  move  with  the  same  acceleration,  all  notion  of 
further  distortion  of  the  connection  ceases.     If  we  call  force." 
a  the  acceleration  of  M  and  ft  the  diminution  of  the 
acceleration  of  w,  then  a  =  <p  —  /?,  where  agreeably 
to  what  precedes  aM  =2  fim.     From  this  follows 

If  we  were  to  enter  more  exhaustively  into  the  de- 
tails of  this  last  occurrence,  we  should  discover  that 
the  two  masses,  in  addition  to  their  motion  of  progres- 
sion, also  generally  perform  with  respect  to  each  other 
motions  of  oscillation.  If  the  connection  on  slight  dis- 
tortion develop  a  powerful  tension,  it  will  be  impos- 
sible for  any  great  amplitude  of  vibration  to  be  reached, 
and  we  may  entirely  neglect  the  oscillatory  motions, 
as  we  actually  have  done. 

If  the  expression  or  =  « tp/M  +  m,  which  deter- 
mines the  acceleration  of  the  entire  system,  be  ex- 
amined, it  will  be  seen  that  the  product  m  <p  plays  a 
decisive  part  in  its  determination.  Newton  therefore 
invested  this  product  of  the  mass  into  the  acceleration 
imparted  to  it,  with  the  name  of  "moving  force." 
M  -\-  niy  on  the  other  hand,  represents  the  entire  mass 
of  the  rigid  system.  We  obtain,  accordingly,  the  accel- 
eration of  any  mass  m*  on  which  the 
moving  force  /  acts,  from  the  expres- 
sion Plin\ 

3.  To  reach  this  result,  it  is  not  at 


W3 


\m,\    \m 


Fig.  133. 


all  necessary  that  the  two  connected 
masses  should  act  directly  on  each  other  in  all  their 
parts.  We  have,  connected  together,  let  us  say,  the 
three  masses  m^,  m^,  m,,  where  m^  is  supposed  to  act 


204  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

A  condition  only  On  m^,  and  m^  only  on  «r„.     Let  the  mass  m.  re- 

whichdoes        .  ^  8  ^  2  i 

not  affect    ceive  ftom  some  external  source  the  acceleration  a?. 

the  pre-  . 

vioua  re-     In  the  distortion  that  follows,  the 

suit. 

masses  m^         m^         m^ 

receive  the  accelerations     -^  6      -{-ft      -\-  <P 

—  y      —  a. 

Here  all  accelerations  to  the  right  are  reckoned  as 
positive,  those  to  the  left  as  negative,  and  it  is  obvious 
that  the  distortion  ceases  to  increase 

when  6  =  /3  —  y,  d  =  q>  —  a, 
where  Sm^  =  ym^y  am^  =z  ftm^. 

The  resolution  of  these  equations  yields  the  com- 
mon acceleration  that  all  the  masses  receive ;  namely, 


d  = 


m^<p 


— a  result  of  exactly  the  same  form  as  before.  When 
therefore  a  magnet  acts  on  a  piece  of  iron  which  is 
joined  to  a  piece  of  wood,  we  need  not  trouble  our- 
selves about  ascertaining  what  particles  of  the  wood 
are  distorted  directly  or  indirectly  (through  other  par- 
ticles of  the  wood)  by  the  motion  of  the  piece  of  iron. 
The  considerations  advanced  will,  in  some  meas- 
ure, perhaps,  have  contributed  towards  clearly  impress- 
ing on  us  the  great  importance  for  mechanics  of  the 
Newtonian  enunciations.     They  will  also  serve,  in  a 

I  subsequent  place,  to  ren- 

der more  readily  obvious 


^W^//M<^f^fm  the  defects  of  these  enun- 

ciations. 


^/^^&,//^^a.m 


\      f 4.   Let  us  now  turn  to 

Fig.  134.  a  few  illustrative  physical 

examples  of  the  principle  of  reaction.     We  consider, 
say,  a  load  Z  on  a  table  71     The  table  is  pressed  by 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  D  YNAMICS.  205 

the  load  Just  so  much,  and  so  much  only,  as  it  in  return  Some  phys- 
presses  the  load,  that  is  prevents  the  same  from  falling,  pies  of  the 
If  /  is  the  weight,  m  the  mass,  and  g  the  acceleration  of  reaction, 
of  gravity,  then  by  Newton *s  conception /= /«^.     If 
the  table  be  let  fall  vertically  downwards  with  the  ac- 
celeration of  free  descent  g,  all  pressure  on  it  ceases. 
We  discover  thus,  that  the  pressure  on  the  table  is  de- 
termined by  the  relative  acceleration  of  the  load  with 
respect  to  the  table.     If  the  table  fall  or  rise  with  the 
acceleration  y,  the  pressure  on  it  is  respectively  fn(^g  — 
y)  and  tn{g -\-  y).     Be  it  noted,  however,  that  no 
change  of  the  relation  is  produced  by  a  constant  velocity 
of  ascent  or  descent.     The  relative  acceleration  is  de- 
terminative. 

Galileo  knew  this  relation  of  things  very  well.  The  The  pres- 
doctrine  of  the  Aristotelians,  that  bodies  of  greater  parts  off aii- 
weight  fall  faster  than  bodies  of  less  weight,  he  not  only 
refuted  by  experiments,  but  cornered  his  adversaries 
by  logical  arguments.  Heavy  bodies  fall  faster  than 
light  bodies,  the  Aristotelians  said,  because  the  upper 
parts  weigh  down  on  the  under  parts  and  accelerate 
their  descent.  In  that  case,  returned  Galileo,  a  small 
body  tied  to  a  larger  body  must,  if  it  possesses  in  se  the 
property  of  less  rapid  descent,  retard  the  larger.  There- 
fore, a  larger  body  falls  more  slowly  than  a  smaller 
body.  The  entire  fundamental  assumption  is  wrong, 
Galileo  says,  because  one  portion  of  ^falling  body  can- 
not by  its  weight  under  any  circumstances  press  an- 
other portion. 

A  pendulum  with  the  time  of  oscillation  7^=  n  V Ijg^  a  failing 
would  acquire,  if  its  axis  received  the  downward  accel-  p^  °  "™' 

eration  y^   the  time  of  oscillation    7*=  nV  l/g y^ 

and  if  let  fall  freely  would  acquire  an  infinite  time  of 
oscillation,  that  is,  would  cease  to  oscillate. 


2o6 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 


The  sensa- 
tion of  fall' 
ing. 


PogKen- 
dorff's  ap- 
paratus. 


We  ourselves,  when  we  jump  or  fall  from  an  eleva- 
tion, experience  a  peculiar  sensation,  which  must  be 
due  to  the  discontinuance  of  the  gravitational  pressure 
of  the  parts  of  our  body  on  one  another — the  blood,  and 
so  forth.  A  similar  sensation,  as  if  the  ground  were 
sinking  beneath  us,  we  should  have  on  a  smaller  planet, 
to  which  we  were  suddenly  transported.  The  sensation 
of  constant  ascent,  like  that  felt  in  an  earthquake, 
would  be  produced  on  a  larger  planet. 

5.  The  conditions  referred  to  are  very  beautifully 
illustrated  by  an  apparatus  (Fig.  135^)  constructed 
by  Poggendorff.     A  string  loaded  at  both  extremities 


\P-P 


b 


VflP^P  D 


b 


^ 


hP 


/ 


Fig.  135a.  FiR-  X35b. 

by  a  weight  P  (Fig.  i35<j)  is  passed  over  a  pulley  r, 
attached  to  the  end  of  a  scale-beam.  A  weight  /  is 
laid  on  one  of  the  weights  £rst  mentioned  and  tied  by 
a  fine  thread  to  the  axis  of  the  pulley.  The  pulley 
now  supports  the  weight  2  -P  -|-  /.  Burning  away  the 
thread  that  holds  the  over-weight,  a  uniformly  accel- 
erated motion  begins  with  the  acceleration  y,  with 
which  P  -{-  p  descends  and  P  rises.  The  load  on  the 
pulley  is  thus  lessened,  as  the  turning  of  the  scales  in- 
dicates. The  descending  weight  P  is  counterbalanced 
by  the  rising  weight  P,  while  the  added  over-weight, 
instead  of  weighing/,  now  weighs  ip/g)ig  —  y).  And 
since  y  =  (//2  P  -f  /)  g,  we  have  now  to  regard  the 
load  on  the  pulley,  not  as/,  but  as/(2  P/2  P-^-p)-  The 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  DYNAMICS.  207 

descending  weight,  only  partially  impeded  in  its  motion 
of  descent,  exerts  only  a  partial  pressure  on  the  pulley. 

We  may  vary  the  experiment.  We  pass  a  thread  a  vwi 
loaded  at  one  extremity  with  the  weight  P  over  the  «iper 
pulleys  a,  b,  d,  of  the  apparatus  as  indicated  in   Fig. 


135^.,  tie  the  unloaded  extremity  at  m,  and  equilibrate 
the  balance.  If  we  pull  on  the  string  at  m,  this  can- 
not directly  affect  the  balance  since  the  direction  of  the 
string  passes  exactly  through  its  axis.  But  the  side  a 
immediately  falls.  The  slackening  of  the  string  causes 
a  to  rise.    An  unacceleraled  laaXian  of  the  weights  would 


2o8 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 


y -■/■-■■/, 

*  1 
1              I 

•  1 

I              »* 
!             A 

1   / 

Fig.  136. 


not  disturb  the  equilibrium.     But  we  cannot  pass  from 
rest  to  motion  without  acceleration. 
Thesuspen-       6.  A  phenomenon  that  strikes  us  at  first  glance  is, 

sion  of  mi-  .,,.«•  -r 

nute  bodies  that  mmute  bodies  of  greater  or  less  specific  gravity 

different     than  the  liquid  m  which  they  are  immersed,  if  sum- 
specific         . 
gravity.       ciently  small,  remain  suspended  a  very  long  time  in  the 

liquid.     We  perceive  at  once  that 
particles  of  this  kind  have  to  over- 
come the  friction  of  the  liquid.  If  the 
cube  of  Fig.  136  be  divided  into  8 
parts  by  the  3  sections  indicated, 
and  the  parts  be  placed  in  a  row, 
their  mass  and  over-weight  will  re- 
main the  same,  but  their  cross-sec- 
tion and  superficial  area,  with  which  the  friction  goes 
hand  in  hand,  will  be  doubled. 
Do  such  Now,  the  opinion  has  at  times  been  advanced  with 

suspended 

Darticies  af- respect  to  this  phenomenon  that  suspended  particles 
specific  of  the  kind  described  have  no  influence  on  the  specific 
the  support- gravity  indicated  by  an  areometer  immersed  in  the 
liquid,  because  these  particles  are  themselves  areo- 
meters. But  it  will  readily  be  seen  that  if  the  sus- 
pended particles  rise  or  fall  with  constant  velocity,  as 
in  the  case  of  very  small  particles  immediately  occurs, 
the  effect  on  the  balance  and  the  areometer  must  be 
the  same.  If  we  imagine  the  areometer  to  oscillate 
about  its  position  of  equilibrium,  it  will  be  evident 
that  the  liquid  with  all  its  contents  will  be  moved  with 
it.  Applying  the  principle  of  virtual  displacements, 
therefore,  we  can  be  no  longer  in  doubt  that  the  areo- 
meter must  indicate  the  mean  specific  gravity.  We 
may  convince  ourselves  of  the  untenability  of  the  rule 
by  which  the  areometer  is  supposed  to  indicate  only 
the  specific  gravity  of  the  liquid  and  not  that  of  the  sus- 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  D  YNAMICS.  209 

pended  particles,  by  the  following  consideration.  In  a 
liquid  A  a  smaller  quantity  of  a  heavier  liquid  B  is  in- 
troduced and  distributed  in  fine  drops.  The  areometer, 
let  us  assume,  indicates  only  the  specific  gravity  of 
A,  Now,  take  more  and  more  of  the  liquid  B,  finally 
just  as  much  of  it  as  we  have  of  -^:  we  can,  then,  no 
longer  say  which  liquid  is  suspended  in  the  other,  and 
which  specific  gravity,  therefore,  the  areometer  must 
indicate. 

7.  A  phenomenon  of  an  imposing  kind,  in  which  The  phe- 
the  relative  acceleration  of  the  bodies  concerned  is  the  tides, 
seen  to  be  determinative  of  their  mutual  pressure,  is 
that  of  the  tides.  We  will  enter  into  this  subject  here 
only  in  so  far  as  it  may  serve  to  illustrate  the  point  we 
are  considering.  The  connection  of  the  phenomenon 
of  the  tides  with  the  motion  of  the  moon  asserts  itself 
in  the  coincidence  of  the  tidal  and  lunar  periods,  in 
the  augmentation  of  the  tides  at  the  full  and  new 
moons,  in  the  daily  retardation  of  the  tides  (by  about 
50  minutes),  corresponding  to  the  retardation  of  the 
culmination  of  the  moon,  and  so  forth.  As  a  matter 
of  fact,  the  connection  of  the  two  occurrences  was  very 
early  thought  of.  In  Newton's  time  people  imagined 
to  themselves  a  kind  of  wave  of  atmospheric  pressure, 
by  means  of  which  the  moon  in  its  motion  was  sup- 
posed to  create  the  tidal  wave. 

The  phenomenon  of  the  tides  makes,  on  every  one  its  impos- 
that  sees  it  for  the  first  time  in  its  full  proportions,  anle?.^  *'**^ 
overpowering  impression.  We  must  not  be  surprised, 
therefore,  that  it  is  a  subject  that  has  actively  engaged 
the  investigators  of  all  times.  The  warriors  of  Alex- 
ander the  Great  had,  from  their  Mediterranean  homes, 
scarcely  the  faintest  idea  of  the  phenomenon  of  the 
tides,  and  they  were,  therefore,  not  a  little  taken  aback 


2IO 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECIIANTCS. 


Extract 
from  Cur- 
tins  Rufus. 


Describing 
the  effect 
on  the  army 
of  Alexan- 
der the 
Great  of  the 
tides  at  the 
mouth  of 
the  Indus. 


by  the  sight  of  the  powerful  ebb  and  flow  at  the  mouth 
of  the  Indus ;  as  we  learn  from  the  account  of  Curtius 
Rufus  {De  Rebus  Gestis  Alexandri  Magni),  whose 
words  we  here  literally,  quote  : 

*'34.  Proceeding,  now,  somewhat  more  slowly  in 
'  their  course,  owing  to  the  current  of  the  river  being 
'  slackened  by  its  meeting  the  waters  of  the  sea,  they 

<  at  last  reached  a  second  island  in  the  middle  of  the 

*  river.  Here  they  brought  the  vessels  to  the  shore, 
*and,  landing,  dispersed  to  seek  provisions,  wholly 
'unconscious  of  the  great  misfortune  that  awaited 
'  them. 

*'  35.   It  was  about  the  third  hour,  when  the  ocean, 

<  in  its  constant  tidal  flux  and  reflux,  began  to  turn 

*  and  press  back  upon  the  river.     The  latter,  at  first 

*  merely  checked,  but  then  more  vehemently  repelled, 

<  at  last  set  back  in  the  opposite  direction  with  a  force 

<  greater  than  that  of  a  rushing  mountain  torrent. 

*  The  nature  of  the  ocean  was  unknown  to  the  multi- 

*  tude,  and  grave  portents  and  evidences  of  the  wrath 
*of  the  Gods  were  seen  in  what  happened.     With 

*  ever- increasing  vehemence  the  sea  poured  in,  com- 
'  pletely  covering  the  fields  which  shortly  before  were 
'  dry.    The  vessels  were  lifted  and  the  entire  fleet  dis- 

*  persed  before  those  who  had  been  set  on  shore,  ter- 

<  rifled  and  dismayed  at  this  unexpected  calamity, 
'  could  return.  But  the  more  haste,  in  times  of  great 
'  disturbance,  the  less  speed.    Some  pushed  the  ships 

*  to  the  shore  with  poles  ;  others,  not  waiting  to  adjust 
'  their  oars,  ran  aground.  Many,  in  their  great  haste 
'  to  get  away,  had  not  waited  for  their  companions, 

*  and  were  barely  able  to  set  in  motion  the  huge,  un- 

*  manageable  barks ;  while  some  of  the  ships  were  too 

*  crowded  to  receive  the  multitudes  that  struggled  to 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  DYNAMICS.  211 

**get  aboard.  The  unequal  division  impeded  all.  TheThedisaa- 
**  cries  of  some  clamoring  to  be  taken  aboard,  of  others  ander's 
"crying  to  put  off,  and  the  conflicting  commands  of 
"men,  all  desirous  of  different  ends,  deprived  every  one 
*  *  of  the  possibility  of  seeing  or  hearing.  Even  the 
"steersmen  were  powerless;  for  neither  could  their 
"  cries  be  heard  by  the  struggling  masses  nor  were  their 
"orders  noticed  by  the  terrified  and  distracted  crews. 
"The  vessels  collided,  they  broke  off  each  other's  oars, 
"  they  plunged  against  one  another.  One  would  think 
"  it  was  not  the  fleet  of  one  and  the  same  army  that 
"was  here  in  motion,  but  two  hostile  fleets  in  combat. 
"Prow  struck  stern;  those  that  had  thrown  the  fore- 
"most  in  confusion  were  themselves  thrown  into  con- 
" fusion  by  those  that  followed;  and  the  desperation 
"of  the  struggling  mass  sometimes  culminated  in 
"hand-to-hand  combats. 

"36.  Already  the  tide  had  overflown  the  fields  sur- 
"  rounding  the  banks  of  the  river,  till  only  the  hillocks 
"jutted  forth  from  above  the  water,  like  islands. 
"  These  were  the  point  towards  which  all  that  had  given 
"up  hope  of  being  taken  on  the  ships,  swam.  The 
"scattered  vessels  rested  in  part  in  deep  water,  where 
"there  were  depressions  in  the  land,  and  in  part  lay 
"aground  in  shallows,  according  as  the  waves  had 
"covered  the  unequal  surface  of  the  country.  Then, 
"suddenly,  a  new  and  greater  terror  took  possession 
"of  them.  The  sea  began  to  retreat,  and  its  waters 
"flowed  back  in  great  long  swells,  leaving  the  land 
"  which  shortly  before  had  been  immersed  by  the  salt 
"waves,  uncovered  and  clear.  The  ships,  thus  for- 
"saken  by  the  water,  fell,  some  on  their  prows,  some 
"  on  their  sides.  The  fields  were  strewn  with  luggage, 
"arms,  and  pieces  of  broken  planks  and  oars.     The 


ii 

ii 
it 


212  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

The  dismay  "  soldicrs  dared  neither  to  venture  on  the  land  nor  to 

ofthearmy.  •      •        i         i  •  r  i  % 

'  *  remain  m  the  ships,  for  every  moment  they  expected 
'  ''something  new  and  worse  than  had  yet  befallen 
•**them.  They  could  scarcely  believe  that  that  which 
*'  they  saw  had  really  happened — a  shipwreck  on  dry 
"land,  an  ocean  in  a  river.  And  of  their  misfortune 
*'  there  seemed  no  end.  For  wholly  ignorant  that  the 
tide  would  shortly  bring  back  the  sea  and  again  set 
their  vessels  afloat,  they  prophesied  hunger  and  dir- 
est distress.  On  the  fields  horrible  animals  crept 
"about,  which  the  subsiding  floods  had  left  behind. 
The  efforts         "37.  The  night  fell,  and  even  the  king  was  sore 

of  the  king  "^  o  '  o 

and  the  re-  "distressed  at  the  slight  hope  of  rescue.     But  his  so- 
lum of  the  o  X- 

tide.  <«  licitude  could  not  move  his  unconquerable  spirit.   He 

"remained  during  the  whole  night  on  the  watch,  and 
"  despatched  horsemen  to  the  mouth  of  the  river,  that, 
"  as  soon  as  they  saw  the  sea  turn  and  flow  back,  they 
"might  return  and  announce  its  coming.  He  also 
"commanded  that  the  damaged  vessels  should  be  re- 
"  paired  and  that  those  that  had  been  overturned  by 
"the  tide  should  be  set  upright,  and  ordered  all  to  be 
"near  at  hand  when  the  sea  should  again  inundate  the 
"land.  After  he  had  thus  passed  the  entire  night  in 
"watching  and  in  exhortation,  the  horsemen  came 
"back  at  full  speed  and  the  tide  as  quickly  followed. 
"At  first,  the  approaching  waters,  creeping  in  light 
"swells  beneath  the  ships,  gently  raised  them,  and, 
"inundating  the  fields,  soon  set  the  entire  fleet  in  mo- 
"tion.  The  shores  resounded  with  the  cheers  and 
"  clappings  of  the  soldiers  and  sailors,  who  celebrated 
"  with  immoderate  joy  their  unexpected  rescue.  *But 
"  whence, '  they  asked,  in  wonderment,  *had  the  sea 
"  so  suddenly  given  back  these  great  masses  of  water? 
"Whither  had  they,  on  the  day  previous,  retreated? 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  DYNAMICS,  213 

**  And  what  was  the  nature  of  this  element,  which  now 
"opposed  and  now  obeyed  the  dominion  of  the  hours?  * 
*'  As  the  king  concluded  from  what  had  happened  that 
'*the  fixed  time  for  the  return  of  the  tide  was  after 
"sunrise,  he  set  out,  in  order  to  anticipate  it,  at  mid- 
**  night,  and  proceeding  down  the  river  with  a  few 
"ships  he  passed  the  mouth  and,  finding  himself  at 
"last  at  the  goal  of. his  wishes,  sailed  out  400  stadia 
"into  the  ocean.  He  then  offered  a  sacrifice  to  the 
"divinities  of  the  sea,  and  returned  to  his  fleet." 

8.  The  essential  point  to  be  noted  in  the  explication  TheexpU- 
of  the  tides  is,  that  the  earth  as  a  rigid  body  can  re-  the  phe- 
ceive  but  one  determinate   acceleration   towards  the  the  tides, 
moon,  while  the  mobile  particles  of  water  on  the  sides 
nearest  to  and  remotest  from  the  moon  can  acquire 
various  accelerations. 


Fig.  137. 

Let  us  consider  (Fig.  137)  on  the  earth  E^  opposite 
which  stands  the  moon  M^  three  points  A^  B^  C.  The 
accelerations  of  the  three  points  in  the  direction  of  the 
moon,  if  we  regard  them  as  free  points,  are  respect- 
ively (p-\-  /J  <p,  <p,  (p  —  J  q).  The  earth  as  a  whole, 
however,  has,  as  a  rigid  body,  the  acceleration  q).  The 
acceleration  towards  the  centre  of  the  earth  we  will 
call  g.  Designating  now  all  accelerations  to  the  left 
as  negative,  and  all  to  the  right  as  positive,  we  get  the 
following  table : 


'       L        ' 


2x4  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

ABC 

—  (9  +  ^<P)^      —9y      —i.9  —  ^9) 


where  the  symbols  of  the  first  and  second  lines  repre- 
sent the  accelerations  which  the  free  points  that  head 
the  columns  receive,  those  of  the  third  line  the  accel- 
eration of  corresponding  rigid  points  of  the  earth,  and 
those  of  the  fourth  line,  the  difference,  or  the  resultant 
accelerations  of  the  free  points  towards  the  earth.  It 
will  be  seen  from  this  result  that  the  weight  of  the  water 
at  A  and  C  is  diminished  by  exactly  the  same  amount. 
The  water  will  rise  at  A  and  C  (Fig.  137).  A  tidal 
wave  will  be  produced  at  these  points  twice  every 
day. 
A  variation  It  is  a  fact  not  always  sufficiently  emphasised,  that 
nomenon.  the  phenomenon  would  be  an  essentially  different  one 
if  the  moon  and  the  earth  were  not  affected  with  ac- 
celerated motion  towards  each  other  but  were  relatively 
fixed  and  at  rest.  If  we  modify  the  considerations 
presented  to  comprehend  this  case,  we  must  put  for  the 
rigid  earth  in  the  foregoing  computation,  ^  =  0  simply. 
We  then  obtain  for 

the  free  points ....  A  C 

the  accelerations . .  —  (9>  +  ^<p\         —  {<P  —  ^9)y 


or (g—J<p)  —  <p,      _(^^r__  J^)__^ 

or g'  —  <Py  —W+<P)y 

where  g'=g — J  (p.  In  such  case,  therefore,  the 
weight  of  the  water  at  A  would  be  diminished,  and  the 
weight  at  C  increased ;   the  height  of  the  water  at  A 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  D  YNAMICS. 


215 


would  be  increased,  and  the  height  at  C  diminished. 
The  water  would  be  elevated  only  on  the  side  facing 
the  moon.     (Fig.  138.) 


Fig.  138. 

g.  It  would  hardly  be  worth  while  to  illustrate  An  iiiustra- 
propositions  best  reached  deductively,  by  experiments  men"***" 
that  can  only  be  performed  with  difficulty.  But  such 
experiments  are  not  beyond  the  limits  of  possibility. 
If  we  imagine  a  small  iron  sphere  K  to  swing  as  a 
conical  pendulum  about  the  pole  of  a 
magnet  N  (Fig.  139),  and  cover  the 
sphere  with  a  solution  of  magnetic  sul- 
phate .of  iron,  the  fluid  drop  should,  if 
the  magnet  is  sufficiently  powerful,  rep- 
resent the  phenomenon  of  the  tides.  But 
if  we  imagine  the  sphere  to  be  fixed  and 
at  rest  with  respect  to  the  pole  of  the 
magnet,  the  fluid  drop  will  certainly  not 
be  found  tapering  to  a  point  both  on 
the  side  facing  and  the  side  opposite  to 
the  pole  of  the  magnet,  but  will  remain  suspended  only 
on  the  side  of  the  sphere  towards  the  pole  of  the 
magnet. 

10.  We  must   not,   of  course,   imagine,   that  the  some  fur- 
entire  tidal  wave  is  produced  at  once  by  the  action  siderations. 
o'f  the  moon.     We  have  rather  to  conceive  the  tide 
as  an  oscillatory  movement  maintained  by  the  moon. 
If,  for  example,  we  should  sweep  a  fan  uniformly  and 


Fig.  139. 


2i6  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

continuously  along  over  the  surface  of  the  water  of  a 
circular  canal,  a  wave  of  considerable  magnitude  fol- 
lowing in  the  wake  of  the  fan  would  by  this  gentle  and 
constantly  continued  impulsion  soon  be  produced.  In 
like  manner  the  tide  is  produced.  But  in  the  latter 
case  the  occurrence  is  greatly  complicated  by  the  irreg- 
ular formation  of  the  continents,  by  the  periodical 
variation  of  the  disturbance,  and  so  forth. 


V. 

CRITICISM    OF  THE    PRINCIPLE    OF    REACTION    AND    OF   THE 

CONCEPT    OF   MASS.  , 

The  con-  I.  Now  that  the  preceding  discussions  have  made 

massf  us  familiar  with  Newton's  ideas,  we  are  sufficiently 
prepared  to  enter  on  a  critical  examination  of  them. 
We  shall  restrict  ourselves  primarily  in  this,  to  the 
consideration  of  the  concept  of  mass  and  the  principle 
of  reaction.  The  two  cannot,  in  such  an  examination, 
be  separated  ;  in  them  is  contained  the  gist  of  New- 
ton's achievement. 
Theexpres-       2.   In  the  first  place  we  do  not  find  the  expression 

8ion"quan-  .  .  ,,       ,  i  ,    •  %      a       •  •^ 

tityof  mat-  **  quantity  of  matter  '  adapted  to  explam  and  elucidate 
the  concept  ot  mass,  since  that  expression  itself  is  not 
possessed  of  the  requisite  clearness.  And  this  is  so, 
though  we  go  back,  as  many  authors  have  done,  to  an 
enumeration  of  the  hypothetical  atoms.  We  only  com- 
plicate, in  so  doing,  indefensible  conceptions.  If  we 
place  together  a  number  of  equal,  chemically  homo- 
geneous bodies,  we  can,  it  may  be  granted,  connect 
some  clear  idea  with  *' quantity  of  matter,"  and  we  per- 
ceive, also,  that  the  resistance  the  bodies  offer  to  mo- 
tion increases  with  this  quantity.  But  the  moment  we 
suppose  chemical  heterogeneity,  the  assumption  that 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  DYNAMICS.  217 

there  is  still  something  that  is  measurable  by  the  same  Newton's 
standard,  which  something  we  call  quantity  of  matter,  of  the  con- 
may  be  suggested  by  mechanical  experiences,  but  is  an 
assumption  nevertheless  that  needs  to  be  justified. 
When  therefore,  with  Newton,  we  make  the  assump- 
tions, respecting  pressure  due  to  weight,  that/  =  mg^ 
p'  =  m'gy  and  put  in  conformity  with  such  assumptions 
///'  =  mjm'y  we  have  made  actual  use  in  the  operation 
thus  performed  of  the  supfosition,  yet  to  be  justified, 
that  different  bodies  are  measurable  by  the  same  stand- 
ard. 

We  might,  indeed,  arbitrarily  posit  ^  that  m/m'  =ip/p'', 
that  is,  might  define  the  ratio  of  mass  to  be  the  ratio 
of  pressure  due  to  weight  when  g  was  the  same.  But 
we  should  then  have  to  substantiate  the  use  that  is  made 
of  this  notion  of  mass  in  the  principle  of  reaction  and 
in  other  relations. 

<-n — n->    <-^      ^->. 

Pig.  140  a.  Fig.  X40  b. 

3.  When  two  bodies  (Fig.  140  a),  perfectly  equal  a  new  form- 
in  all  respects,  are  placed  opposite  each  other,  we  ex-  the  con- 

cept« 

pect,  agreeably  to  the  principle  of  symmetry,  that  they 
will  produce  in  each  other  in  the  direction  of  their  line 
of  junction  equal  and  opposite  accelerations.  But  if 
these  bodies  exhibit  any  difference,  however  slight,  of 
form,  of  chemical  constitution,  or  are  in  any  other  re- 
spects different,  the  principle  of  symmetry  forsakes  us, 
unless  we  assume  or  know  beforehand  that  sameness  of 
form  or  sameness  of  chemical  constitution,  or  whatever 
else  the  thing  in  question  may  be,  is  not  determina- 
tive. If,  however,  mechanical  experiences  clearly  and 
indubitably  point  to  the  existence  in  bodies  of  a  special 
and  distinct  property  determinative  of  accelerations^ 


2i8  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

nothing  stands  in  the  way  of  our  arbitrarily  establish- 
ing the  following  definition : 
Definition  All  thost  bodies  are  bodies  of  equal  mass,  which^  mu- 

masses.       tually  acting  on  each  other,  produce  in  each  other  equal 
and  opposite  accelerations. 

We  have,  in  this,  simply  designated,  or  named,  an 
actual  relation  of  things.  In  the  general  case  we  pro- 
ceed similarly.  The  bodies  A  and  B  receive  respec- 
tively as  the  result  of  their  mutual  action  (Fig.  140  b) 
the  accelerations  —  q)  and  +  qjl ,  where  the  senses  of 
the  accelerations  are  indicated  by  the  signs.  We  say 
then,  B  has  q>lq>'  times  the  mass  of  A.  If  we  take  A 
as  our  unity  we  assign  to  that  body  the  mass  m  which  im- 
parts to  A  m  times  the  acceleration  that  A  in  the  reaction 
imparts  to  it.  The  ratio  of  the  masses  is  the  negative 
inverse  ratio  of  the  counter-accelerations.  That  these 
accelerations  always  have  opposite  signs,  that  there 
are  therefore,  by  our  definition,  only  positive  masses, 
is  a  point  that  experience  teaches,  and  experience  alone 
Character  cau  teach.  In  our  concept  of  mass  no  theory  is  in- 
nition.  ^  volved  \  **  quantity  of  matter  **  is  wholly  unnecessary  in 
it ;  all  it  contains  is  the  exact  establishment,  designa- 
tion, and  denomination  of  a  fact.   (Compare  Appendix, 

II.) 

4.  One  difficulty  should  not  remain  unmentioned  in 
this  connection,  inasmuch  as  its  removal  is  absolutely 
necessary  to  the  formation  of  a  perfectly  clear  concept 
of  mass.  We  consider  a  set  of  bodies,  A,  B,  C,  £>.  .  ., 
and  compare  them  all  with  A  as  unit. 

A,     B,      c,     A     b:,     F. 

I,         m,       m ,      m  f      m    ,     m 


We  find  thus  the  respective  mass- values,  1,   m,   m\ 
m".  .  .  . ,  and  so  forth.    The  question  now  arises,  If  we 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  DYNAMICS.  219 

select  B  as  our  standard  of  comparison  (as  our  unit),  Discnssion 

of  &  diffi~ 

shall  we  obtain  for  C  the  mass-value  m*  Im^  and  for  D  cuity  in- 

,  *  volved  in 

the  value  m"  jm,  or  will  perhaps  wholly  different  values  the  preced- 
result  ?  More  simply,  the  question  may  be  put  thus :  laOon. 
Will  two  bodies  B^  C,  which  in  mutual  action  with  A 
have  acted  as  equal  masses,  also  act  as  equal  masses 
in  mutual  action  with  each  other?  No  A7^V^/ necessity 
exists  whatsoever,  that  two  masses  that  are  equal  to  a 
third  mass  should  also  be  equal  to  each  other.  For 
we  are  concerned  here,  not  with  a  mathematical,  but 
with  a  physical  question.  This  will  be  rendered  quite 
clear  by  recourse  to  an  analogous  relation.  We  place 
by  the  side  of  each  other  the  bodies  A,  B^  C  in  the 
proportions  of  weight  «,  ^,  c  in  which  they  enter  into 
the  chemical  combinations  AB  and  A  C.  There  exists, 
now,  no  logical  necessity  at  all  for  assuming  that  the 
same  proportions  of  weight  b^  c  of  the  bodies  By  C  will 
also  enter  into  the  chemical  combination  BC,  Expe- 
rience, however,  informs  us  that  they  do.  If  we  place 
by  the  side  of  each  other  any  set  of  bodies  in  the  pro- 
portions of  weight  in  which  they  combine  with  the 
body  Ay  they  will  also  unite  with  each  other  in  the 
same  proportions  of  weight.  But  no  one  can  l^now 
this  who  has  not  tried  it.  And  this  is  precisely  the  case 
with  the  mass-values  of  bodies. 

If  we  were  to  assume  that  the  order  of  combination  The  order 
of  the  bodies,  by  which  their  mass-values  are  deter-  nation  not 
mined,  exerted  any  influence  on  the  mass-values,  the 
consequences  of  such  an  assumption  would,  we  should 
find,  lead  to  conflict  with  experience.  Let  us  suppose, 
for  instance  (Fig.  141),  that  we  have  three  elastic 
bodies.  Ay  By  C,  movable  on  an  absolutely  smooth  and 
rigid  ring.  We  presuppose  that  A  and  B  in  their 
mutual  relations  comport  themselves  like  equal  masses 


220  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

and  that  B  and  C  do  the  same.  We  are  then  also 
obliged  to  assume,  if  we  wish  to  avoid  conflicts  with 
experience,  that  C  and  A  in  their  mutual  relations  act 
like  equal  masses.  If  we  impart  to  ^  a  velocity,  A 
will  transmit  this  velocity  by  impact  to  B,  and  B  to  C 
But  if  C  were  to  act  towards  A,  say,  as  a  greater  mass, 

A  on  impact  would  acquire  a  greater 
velocity  than  it  originally  had  while 
C  would  still  retain  a  residue  of 
what  it  had.  With  every  revolution 
in  the  direction  of  the  hands  of  a 
watch  the  vis  viva  of  the  system 
would  be  increased.  If  C  were  the 
^**'  "*"•  smaller  mass  as  compared  with  A^ 

reversing  the  motion  would  produce  the  same  result. 
But  a  constant  increase  of  vis  viva  of  this  kind  is  at 
decided  variance  with  our  experience. 
The  new  5-  The  Concept  of  mass  when  reached  in  the  man- 

ma!»Jm-°  ner  just  developed  renders  unnecessary  the  special 
pHdtfy  the  enunciation  of  the  principle  of  reaction.  In  the  con* 
reacdon?  °  cept  of  mass  and  the  principle  of  reaction,  as  we  have 
stated  in  a  preceding  page,  the  same  fact  is  twice  form- 
ulated; which  is  redundant.  If  two  masses  i  and  2 
act  on  each  other,  our  very  definition  of  mass  asserts 
that  they  impart  to  each  other  contrary  accelerations 
which  are  to  each  other  respectively  as  2:1. 

6.  The  fact  that  mass  can  be  measured  by  weighty 
where  the  acceleration  of  gravity  is  invariable,  can  also 
be  deduced  from  our  definition  of  mass.  We  are' 
sensible  at  once  of  any  increase  or  diminution  of  a  pres- 
sure, but  this  feeling  affords  us  only  a  very  inexact  and 
indefinite  measure  of  magnitudes  of  pressure.  An 
exact,  serviceable  measure  of  pressure  springs  from 
the  observation  that  every  pressure  is  replaceable  by 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  D  YATAMICS,  Z2t 

the  pressure  of  a  number  of  like  and  commensurable  it  also  in- 

1     1  J    1      volves  the 

weights.     Every  pressure  can  be  counterbalanced  by  fact  that 

.  mass  can  be 

the  pressure  of  weights  of  this  kind.     Let  two  bodies  measured 

.  ....  by  weight. 

m  and  m'  be  respectively  affected  in  opposite  directions 
with  the  accelerations  ^  and  q/,  determined  by  exter- 
nal circumstances.  And  let  the  bodies  be  joined  by  a 
string.  If  equilibrium  prevails,  the  acceleration  ^  in . 
M  and  the  acceleration  q/  in  pi'  are  exactly  balanced 
by  inUraction,  For  this  case,  ac- 
cordingly, m(p  =  tn'<p'.     When,    < — 1^ VffA — > 

therefore,  <p  =  <p'f  as  is  the  case    ^  ^ 

when  the  bodies  are  abandoned 

to  the  acceleration  of  gravity,  we  have,  in  the  case 
of  equilibrium,  also  ///  =:  m\  It  is  obviously  imma- 
terial whether  we  make  the  bodies  act  on  each  other 
directly  by  means  of  a  string,  or  by  means  of  a  string 
passed  over  a  pulley,  or  by  placing  them  on  the  two 
pans  of  a  balance.  The  fact  that  mass  can  be  meas- 
ured by  weight  is  evident  from  our  definition  without 
recourse  or  reference  to  ''quantity  of  matter.*' 

7.  As  soon  therefore  as  we,  our  attention  being  The Kenerai 
drawn  to  the  fact  by  experience,  have  perceived  in  bod-  this  view, 
ies  the  existence  of  a  special  property  determinative  of 
accelerations,  our  task  with  regard  to  it  ends  with  the 
recognition  and  unequivocal  designation  of  this  fad. 
Beyond  the  recognition  of  this  fact  we  shall  not  get, 
and  every  venture  beyond  it  will  only  be  productive  of 
obscurity.  All  uneasiness  will  vanish  when  once  we 
have  made  clear  to  ourselves  that  in  the  concept  of 
mass  no  theory  of  any  kind  whatever  is  contained,  but 
simply  a  fact  of  experience.  The  concept  has  hitherto 
held  good.  It  is  very  improbable,  but  not  impossible, 
^diat  it  will  be  shaken  in  the  future,  just  as  the  concep- 


222  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

tion  of  a  constant  quantity  of  heat,  which  also  rested 
on  experience,  was  modified  by  new  experiences. 

VI. 
NEWTON'S  VIEWS  OF  TIME,   SPACE,  AND  MOTION. 

I.  In  a  scholium  which  he  appends  immediately  to 
his  definitions,  Newton  presents  his  views  regarding 
time  and  space — views  which  we  shall  now  proceed  to 
examine  more  in  detail.  We  shall  literally  cite,  to  this 
end,  only  the  passages  that  are  absolutely  necessary 
to  the  characterisation  of  Newton's  views. 
Newton'8  <«So  far,  my  object  has  been  to  explain  the  senses 

views  of 

time,  space,  <<in  which  Certain  words  little  known  are  to  be  used  in 

and  motion.  .  - 

**the  sequel.  Time,  space,  place,  and  motion,  being 
'*  words  well  known  to  everybody,  I  do  not  define.  Yet 
**it  is  to  be  remarked,  that  the  vulgar  conceive  these 
•  **  quantities  only  in  their  relation  to  sensible  objects. 
''And  hence  certain  prejudices  with  respect  to  them 
*'  have  arisen,  to  remove  which  it  will  be  convenient  to 
'<  distinguish  them  into  absolute  and  relative,  true  and 
''apparent,  mathematical  and  common,  respectively. 
Absolute,  "  I.  Absolute,  true,  and  mathematical  time,  of  it- 

time.  "  self,  and  by  its  own  nature,  flows  uniformly  on,  with- 

"out  regard  to  anything  external.     It  is  also  called 
* '  duration. 

"Relative,  apparent,  and  common  time,  is  some 
"sensible  and  external  measure  of  absolute  time  (dura- 
tion), estimated  by  the  motions  of  bodies,  whether 
accurate  or  inequable,  and  is  commonly  employed 
in  place  of  true  time ;  as  an  hour,  a  day,  a  month, 
'a  year.  .  . 

"The  natural  days,  which,  commonly,  for  the  pur- 
' '  pose  of  the  measurement  of  time,  are  held  as  equal. 
' '  are  in  reality  unequal.     Astronomers  correct  this  in- 


a 
n 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  D  YNAMICS.  223 

"equality,  in  order  that  they  may  measure  by  a  truer 
"time  the  celestial  motions.  It  may  be  that  there  is 
"no  equable  motion,  by  which  time  can  accurately  be 
"measured.  All  motions  can  be  accelerated  and  re- 
"tarded.  But  the  flow  of  absolute  time  cannot  be 
"changed.  Duration,  or  the  persistent  existence  of 
"  things,  is  always  the  same,  whether  motions  be  swift 
"or  slow  or  null." 

2.   It  would  appear  as  though  Newton  in  the  re-  Discussion 
marks  here  cited  still  stood  under  the  influence  of  the  view  of 

time. 

mediaeval  philosophy,  as  though  he  had  grown  unfaith- 
ful to  his  resolve  to  investigate  only  actual  facts.  When 
we  say  a  thing  A  changes  with  the  time,  we  mean  sim- 
ply that  the  conditions  that  determine  a  thing  A  depend 
on  the  conditions  that  determine  another  thing  B,  The 
vibrations  of  a  pendulum  take  place  in  time  when  its 
excursion  depends  on  the  position  of  the  earth.  Since, 
however,  in  the  observation  of  the  pendulum,  we  are 
not  under  the  necessity  of  taking  into  account  its  de- 
pendence on  the  position  of  the  earth,  but  may  com- 
pare it  with  any  other  thing  (the  conditions  of  which 
of  course  also  depend  on  the  position  of  the  earth),  the 
illusory  notion  easily  arises  that  ail  the  things  with 
which  we  compare  it  are  unessential.  Nay,  we  may, 
in  attending  to  the  motion  of  a  pendulum,  neglect  en- 
tirely other  external  things,  and  find  that  for  every  po- 
sition of  it  our  thoughts  and  sensations  are  different. 
Time,  accordingly,  appears  to  be  some  particular  and 
independent  thing,  on  the  progress  of  which  the  posi- 
tion of  the  pendulum  depends,  while  the  things  that 
we  resort  to  for  comparison  and  choose  at  random  ap- 
pear to  play  a  wholly  collateral  part.  But  we  must 
not  forget  that  all  things  in  the  world  are  connected 
with  one  another  and  depend  on  one  another,  and  that 


224  ^^^  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

9 

General  we  ourselves  and  all  our  thoughts  are  also  a  part  of 
of  Uie'con-  nature.  It  is  utterly  beyond  our  power  to  measure  the 
time°  changes  of  things  by  time.  Quite  the  contrary,  time 
is  an  abstraction,  at  which  we  arrive  by  means  of  the 
changes  of  things  ;  made  because  we  are  not  restricted 
to  any  one  definite  measure,  all  being  interconnected. 
A  motion  is  termed  uniform  in  which  equal  increments 
of  space  described  correspond  to  equal  increments  of 
space  described  by  some  motion  with  which  we  form  a 
comparison,  as  the  rotation  of  the  earth.  A  motion 
may,  with  respect  to  another  motion,  be  uniform.  But 
the  question  whether  a  motion  is  in  itself  uniform,  is 
senseless.  With  just  as  little  justice,  also,  may  we 
speak  of  an  *' absolute  time" — of  a  time  independent  of 
change.  This  absolute  time  can  be  measured  by  com- 
parison with  no  motion ;  it  has  therefore  neither  a 
practical  nor  a  scientific  value  ;  and  no  one  is  justified 
in  saying  that  he  knows  aught  about  it.  It  is  an  idle 
metaphysical  conception. 
Further  eiu-  It  would  uot  be  difficult  to  show  from  the  points  of 
the  idea,  view  of  psychology,  history,  and  the  science  of  lan- 
guage (by  the  names  of  the  chronological  divisions), 
that  we  reach  our  ideas  of  time  in  and  through  the  in- 
terdependence of  things  on  one  another.  In  these  ideas 
the  profoundest  and  most  universal  connection  of  things 
.  is  expressed.  When  a  motion  takes  place  in  time,  it 
depends  on  the  motion  of  the  earth.  This  is  not  refuted 
by  the  fact  that  mechanical  motions  can  be  reversed. 
A  number  of  variable  quantities  may  be  so  related  that 
one  set  can  suffer  a  change  without  the  others  being 
affected  by  it.  Nature  behaves  like  a  machine.  The 
individual  parts  reciprocally  determine  one  another. 
But  while  in  a  machine  the  position  of  one  part  de- 
termines the  position  of  all  the  other  parts,  in  nature 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  DYNAMICS.  225 

more  complicated  relations  obtain.  These  relations  are 
best  represented  under  the  conception  of  a  number, 
«,  of  quantities  that  satisfy  a  lesser  number,  n\  of  equa- 
tions. Were  n  =  n\  nature  would  be  invariable.  Were 
n'  =  n  —  1,  then  with  one  quantity  all  the  rest  would 
be  controlled.  If  this  latter  relation  obtained  in  na- 
ture, time  could  be  reversed  the  moment  this  had  been 
accomplished  with  any  one  single  motion.  But  the 
true  state  of  things  is  represented  by  a  different  rela- 
tion between  n  and  n'.  The  quantities  in  question  are 
partially  determined  by  one  another  ;  but  they  retain 
a  greater  indeterminateness,  or  freedom,  than  in  the 
case  last  cited.  We  ourselves  feel  that  we  are  such  a 
partially  determined,  partially  undetermined  element 
of  nature.  In  so  far  as  a  portion  only  of  the  changes 
of  nature  depends  on  us  and  can  be  reversed  by  us, 
does  time  appear  to  us  irreversible,  and  the  time  that 
is  past  as  irrevocably  gone. 

We  arrive  at  the  idea  of  time, — to  express  it  briefly  Some  psy- 
and  popularly, — by  the  connection  of  that  which  isconaiSera- 
contained  in  the  province  of  our  memory  with  that 
which  is  contained  in  the  province  of  our  sense-percep- 
tion. When  we  say  that  time  flows  on  in  a  definite  di- 
rection or  sense,  we  mean  that  physical  events  gene- 
rally (and  therefore  also  physiological  events)  take 
place  only  in  a  definite  sense.*  Differences  of  tem- 
perature, electrical  differences,  differences  of  level  gen- 
erally, if  left  to  themselves,  all  grow  less  and  not 
greater.  If  we  contemplate  two  bodies  of  different 
temperatures,  put  in  contact  and  left  wholly  to  them- 
selves, we  shall  find  that  it  is  possible  only  for  greater 
differences  of  temperature  in  the  field  of  memory  to 

*  Investigations  concerning  the  physiological  nature  of  the  sensations  of 
dme  and  space  are  here  excluded  from  consideration. 


226  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

exist  with  lesser  ones  in  the  field  of  sense-perception, 
and  not  the  reverse.  In  all  this  there  is  simply  ex- 
pressed a  peculiar  and  profound  connection  of  things. 
To  demand  at  the  present  time  a  full  elucidation  of  this 
matter,  is  to  anticipate,  in  the  manner  of  speculative 
philosophy,  the  results  of  all  future  special  investiga- 
tion, that  is  a  perfect  physical  science.  (Compare  Ap- 
pendix, III.) 
Newton's  3.  Views  similar  to  those  concerning  time,  are  de- 

views  of 

space  and  veloped  by  Newtou  with  respect  to  space  and  motion. 
We  extract  here  a  few  passages  which  characterise  his 
position. 

"  II.  Absolute  space,  in  its  own  nature  and  with- 
*'out  regard  to  anything  external,  always  remains  sim- 
**ilar  and  immovable. 

**  Relative  space  is  some  movable  dimension  or 
"measure  of  absolute  space,  which  our  senses  deter- 
'*mine  by  its  position  with  respect  to  other  bodies, 
'*and  which  is  commonly  taken  for  immovable  [abso- 
"lute]  space.  .  .  . 

**  IV.  Absolute  motion  is  the  translation  of  a  body 
"from  one  absolute  place*  to  another  absolute  place  ; 
*'  and  relative  motion,  the  translation  from  one  relative 
"  place  to  another  relative  place.  .  .  . 
Passages  " .  .  .  .  And  thus  we  use,  in  common  affairs,  instead 

works.  "of  absolute  places  and  motions,  relathe  ones;  and 
"that  without  any  inconvenience.  But  in  physical 
"disquisitions,  we  should  abstract  from  the  senses. 
"  For  it  may  be  that  there  is  no  body  really  at  rest,  to 
"which  the  places  and  motions  of  others  can  be  re- 
"ferred.  ... 

"  The  effects  by  which  absolute  and  relative  motions 

*The  place,  or  locus  of  a  body,  according  to  Newton,  is  not  its  position, 
but  the/aW  ofspact  which  it  occupies.  It  is  either  absolute  or  relative. — Tran*. 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  D  YNAMICS. 


227 


are  distinguished  from  one  another,  are  centrifugal 
forces,  or  those  forces  in  circular  motion  which  pro- 
duce a  tendency  of  recession  from  the  axis.  For  in 
a  circular  motion  which  is  purely  relative  no  such 
forces  exist ;  but  in  a  true  and  absolute  circular  mo- 
tion they  do  exist,  and  are  greater  or  less  according 
to  the  quantity  of  the  [absolute]  motion. 

*'  For  instance.  If  a  bucket,  suspended  by  a  long  The  rota- 
cord,  is  so  often  turned  about  that  finally  the  cord  is 
strongly  twisted,  then  is  filled  with  water,  and  held 
at  rest  together  with  the  water ;  and  afterwards  by 
the  action  of  a  second  force,  it  is  suddenly  set  whirl- 
ing about  the  contrary  way,  and  continues,  while  the 
cord  is  untwisting  itself,  for  some  time  in  this  mo- 
tion ;  the  surface  of  the  water  will  at  first  be  level, 
just  as  it  was  before  the  vessel  began  to  move ;  but, 
subsequently,  the  vessel,  by  gradually  communicat- 
ing its  motion  to  the  water,  will  make  it  begin  sens- 
ibly to  rotate,  and  the  water  will  recede  little  by  little 
from  the  middle  and  rise  up  at  the  sides  of  the  ves- 
sel, its  surface  assuming  a  concave  form.  (This  ex- 
periment I  have  made  myself.) 

*'....  At  first,  when  the  relative  motion  of  the  wa-  Relative 
ter  in  the  vessel  was  greatest^  that  motion  produced  motion, 
no  tendency  whatever  of  recession  from  the  axis ;  the 
water  made  no  endeavor  to  move  towards  the  cir- 
cumference, by  rising  at  the  sides  of  the  vessel,  but 
remained  level,  and  for  that  reason  its  true  circular 
motion  had  not  yet  begun.  But  afterwards,  when 
the  relative  motion  of  the  water  had  decreased,  the 
rising  of  the  water  at  the  sides  of  the  vessel  indicated 
an  endeavor  to  recede  from  the  axis ;  and  this  en- 
deavor revealed  the  real  circular  motion  of  the  water, 
continually  increasing,  till  it  had  reached  its  greatest 


228 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 


Newton's 
criteria  for 
distinguish- 
ing absolute 
from  rela- 
tive motion. 


point,  when  relatively  the  water  was  at  rest  in  the 
vessel .... 

"  It  is  indeed  a  matter  of  great  difficulty  to  discover 
and  effectually  to  distinguish  the  true  from  the  ap- 
parent motions  of  particular  bodies  ;  for  the  parts  of 
that  immovable  space  in  which  bodies  actually  move, 
do  not  come  under  the  observation  of  our  senses. 

**  Yet  the  case,  is  not  altogether  desperate ;  for  there 
exist  to  guide  us  certain  marks,  abstracted  partly 
from  the  apparent  motions,  which  are  the  differences 
of  the  true  motions,  and  partly  from  the  forces  that 
are  the  causes  and  effects  of  the  true  motions.  If, 
for  instance,  two  globes,  kept  at  a  fixed  distance 
from  one  another  by  means  of  a  cord  that  connects 
them,  be  revolved  about  their  common  centre  of 
gravity,  one  might,  from  the  simple  tension  of  the 
cord,  discover  the  tendency  of  t^ie  globes  to  recede 
from  the  axis  of  their  motion,  and  on  this  basis  the 
quantity  of  their  circular  motion  might  be  computed. 
And  if  any  equal  forces  should  be  simultaneously 
impressed  on  alternate  faces  of  the  globes  to  augment 
or  diminish  their  circular  motion,  we  might,  from 
the  increase  or  decrease  of  the  tension  of  the  cord, 
deduce  the  increment  or  decrement  of  their  motion ; 
and  it  might  also  be  found  thence  on  what  faces 
forces  would  have  to  be  impressed,  in  order  that  the 
motion  of  the  globes  should  be  most  augmented ; 
that  is,  their  rear  faces,  or  those  which,  in  the  cir- 
cular motion,  follow.  But  as  soon  as  we  knew  which 
faces  followed,  and  consequently  which  preceded,  we 
should  likewise  know  the  direction  of  the  motion. 
In  this  way  we  might  find  both  the  quantity  and  the 
direction  of  the  circular,  motion,  considered  even  in 
an  immense  vacuum,  where  there  was  nothing  ex- 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  D  YNAMICS.  229 

'*  temal  or  sensible  with  which  the  globes  could  be 
**  compared  ....** 

4.   It  is  scarcely  necessary  to  remark  that  in  the  re-  The  predi- 
flections  here  presented  Newton  has  again  acted  con-  Newton 

,  .  -..,..  ,  are  not  the 

trary  to  his  expressed  mtention  only  to  mvestigate  actual  cv^xessAon 

_  _  .  J  •  1  •  t  o'  actual 

facts.  No  one  is  competent  to  predicate  things  about  facts. 
absolute  space  and  absolute  motion ;  they  are  pure 
things  of  thought,  pure  mental  constructs,  that  cannot 
be  pr<5duced  in  experience.  All  our  principles  of  me- 
chanics are,  as  we  have  shown  in  detail,  experimental 
knowledge  concerning  the  relative  positions  and  mo- 
tions of  bodies.  Even  in  the  provinces  in  which  they 
are  now  recognised  as  valid,  they  could  not,  and  were 
not,  admitted  without  previously  being  subjected  to 
experimental  tests.  No  one  is  warranted  in  extending 
these  principles  beyond  the  boundaries  of  experience. 
In  fact,  such  an  extension  is  meaningless,  as  no  one 
possesses  the  requisite  knowledge  to  make  use  of  it. 

Let  us  look  at  the  matter  in  detail.  When  we  say  that  Detailed 
a  body  K  alters  its  direction  and  velocity  solely  through  matter, 
the  influence  of  another  body  K\  we  have  asserted 
a  conception  that  it  is  impossible  to  come  at  unless 
other  bodies  A,  B,  C  .  .  .  are  present  with  reference 
to  which  the  motion  of  the  body  K  has  been  estimated. 
In  reality,  therefore,  we  are  simply  cognisant  of  a  re- 
lation of  the  body  K  to  A,  B,  C ,  ,  .  .  If  now  we  sud- 
denly neglect  A,  B,  C  .  .  .  and  attempt  to  speak  of 
the  deportment  of  the  body  JC  in  absolute  space,  we 
implicate  ourselves  in  a  twofold  error.  In  the  first 
place,  we  cannot  know  how  A!"  would  act  in  the  ab- 
sence of  ^,  ^,  C  .  .  . ;  and  in  the  second  place,  every 
means  would  be  wanting  of  forming  a  judgment  of  the 
behaviour  of  AT  and  of  putting  to  the  test  what  we  had 


230  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

predicated, — which  latter  therefore  would  be  bereft  of 

all  scientific  significance. 
The  part  Two  bodies  K  and  K\  which  gravitate  toward  each 

bodies  of    other,  impart  to  each  other  in  the  direction  of  their 
inthede-    line  of  junction  accelerations  inversely  proportional  to 

termination  .  #ti'  ...  .., 

of  motion,  their  masses  m,  m  ,  In  this  proposition  is  contained, 
not  only  a  relation  of  the  bodies  K  and  K*  to  otie  an- 
other, but  also  a  relation  of  them  to  other  bodies.  For 
the  proposition  asserts,  not  only  that  K  and  K*  suffer 
with  respect  to  one  another  the  acceleration  designated 
by  K  (ni  -|-  m' /r^)y  but  also  that  .^experiences  the  ac- 
celeration —  Km* jr^  and  K*  the  acceleration  +  Km/r^ 
in  the  direction  of  the  line  of  junction  ;  facts  which  can 
be  ascertained  only  by  the  presence  of  other  bodies. 

The  motion  of  a  body  K  can  only  be  estimated  by 
reference  to  other  bodies  A,  B,  C  .  .  .  But  since  we 
always  have  at  our  disposal  a  su£Scient  number  of 
bodies,  that  are  as  respects  each  other  relatively  fixed, 
or  only  slowly  change  their  positions,  we  are,  in  such 
reference,  restricted  to  no  one  definite  body  and  can 
alternately  leave  out  of  account  now  this  one  and  now 
that  one.  In  this  way  the  conviction  arose  that  these 
bodies  are  indifferent  generally. 

T*»e  hy-  It  might  be,  indeed,  that  the  isolated  bodies  A.  B. 

pothesisof  o  >  >  97 

a  medium    C  .  .  .  play  merely  a  collateral  role  in  the  determina- 

in  space  de-    .  *       "^  "^ 

terminative  tiou  of  the  motiou  of  the  body  Kt  and  that  this  motion 

of  motion.     .  ■'  , 

is  determined  by  a  tnedium  in  which  K  exists.  In  such 
a  case  we  should  have  to  substitute  this  medium  for 
Newton's  absolute  space.  Newton  certainly  did  not 
entertain  this  idea.  Moreover,  it  is  easily  demonstrable 
that  the  atmosphere  is  not  this  motion-determinative 
medium.  We  should,  therefore,  have  to  picture  to 
ourselves  some  other  medium,  filling,  say,  all  space, 
with  respect  to  the  constitution  of  which  and  its  kinetic 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  DYNAMICS,  i^t 

relations  to  the  bodies  placed  in  it  we  have  at  present 
no  adequate  knowledge.  In  itself  such  a  state  of  things 
would  not  belong  to  the  impossibilities.  It  is  known, 
from  recent  hydrodynamical  investigations,  that  a  rigid 
body  experiences  resistance  in  a  frictionless  fluid  only 
when  its  velocity  changes.  True,  this  result  is  derived 
theoretically  from  the  notion  of  inertia ;  but  it  might, 
conversely,  also  be  regarded  as  the  primitive  fact  from 
which  we  have  to  start.  Although,  practically,  and  at 
present,  nothing  is  to  be  accomplished  with  this  con- 
ception, we  might  still  hope  to  learn  more  in  the  future 
concerning  this  hypothetical  medium ;  and  from  the 
point  of  view  of  science  it  would  be  in  every  respect 
a  more  valuable  acquisition  than  the  forlorn  idea  of 
absolute  space.  When  we  reflect  that  we  cannot  abol- 
ish the  isolated  bodies  A,  B,  C  .  .  .,  that  is,  cannot 
determine  by  experiment  whether  the  part  they  play  is 
fundamental  or  collateral,  that  hitherto  they  have  been 
the  sole  and  only  competent  means  of  the  orientation 
of  motions  and  of  the  description  of  mechanical  facts, 
it  will  be  found  expedient  provisionally  to  regard  all 
motions  as  determined  by  these  bodies. 

5.  Let  us  now  examine  the  point  on  which  New-  critical 
ton,  apparently  with  sound  reasons,  rests  his  distinc-  tion  of 
tion  of  absolute  and  relative  motion.     If  the  earth  is  distinction 
affected  with  an  absolute  rotation  about  its  axis,  cen- from  reia- 

•  e         %   c  •        1  1         •  tive  motion. 

tnfugal  forces  are  set  up  m  the  earth  :  it  assumes  an 
oblate  form,  the  acceleration  of  gravity  is  diminished 
at  the  equator,  the  plane  of  Foucault's  pendulum  ro- 
tates, and  so  on.  All  these  phenomena  disappear  if 
the  earth  is  at  rest  and  the  other  heavenly  bodies  are 
affected  with  absolute  motion  round  it,  such  that  the 
same  relative  rotation  is  produced.  This  is,  indeed,  the 
case,  if  we  start  ab  initio  from  the  idea  of  absolute  space. 


232  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

But  if  we  take  our  stand  on  the  basis  of  facts,  we  shall 
find  we  have  knowledge  only  of  relative  spaces  and  mo- 
tions. Relatively,  not  considering  the  unknown  and 
neglected  medium  of  space,  the  motions  of  the  uni- 
verse are  the  same  whether  we  adopt  the  Ptolemaic  or 
the  Copernican  mode  of  view.  Both  views  are,  indeed, 
equally  correct  \  only  the  latter  is  more  simple  and  more 
practical.  The  universe  is  not  twice  given,  with  an 
earth  at  rest  and  an  earth  in  motion ;  but  only  once, 
with  its  relative  motions,  alone  determinable.  It  is, 
accordingly,  not  permitted  us  to  say  how  things  would 
be  if  the  earth  did  not  rotate.  We  may  interpret  the 
one  case  that  is  given  us,  in  different  ways.  If,  how- 
ever, we  so  interpret  it  that  we  come  into  conflict  with 
experience,  our  interpretation  is  simply  wrong.  The 
principles  of  mechanics  can,  indeed,  be  so  conceived, 
that  even  for  relative  rotations  centrifugal  forces  arise, 
interpreta-  Newton's  experiment  with  the  rotating  vessel  of 
experiment  Water  simply  iuforms  us,  that  the  relative  rotation  of 
rotatinf!  the  Water  with  respect  to  the  sides  of  the  vessel  pro- 
water,  duces  no  noticeable  centrifugal  forces,  but  that  such 
forces  are  produced  by  its  relative  rotation  with  respect 
to  the  mass  of  the  earth  and  the  other  celestial  bodies. 
No  one  is  competent  to  say  how  the  experiment  would 
turn  out  if  the  sides  of  the  vessel  increased  in  thickness 
and  mass  till  they  were  ultimately  several  leagues  thick. 
The  one  experiment  only  lies  before  us,  and  our  busi- 
ness is,  to  bring  it  into  accord  with  the  other  facts 
known  to  us,  and  not  with  the  arbitrary  fictions  of  our 
imagination. 

6.  We  can  have  no  doubts  concerning  the  signifi- 
cance of  the  law  of  inertia  if  we  bear  in  mind  the  man- 
ner in  which  it  was  reached.  To  begin  with,  Galileo 
discovered  the  constancy  of  the  velocity  and  direction 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  D  YNAMICS,  233 

of  a  body  referred  to  terrestrial  objects.     Most  terres- The  law  ot 
trial  motions  are  of  such  brief  duration  and  extent,  that  the  ii^ht  of 

this  view 

it  is  wholly  unnecessary  to  take  into  account  the  earth's 
rotation  and  the  changes  of  its  progressive  velocity  with 
respect  to  the  celestial  bodies.  This  consideration  is 
found  necessary  only  in  the  case  of  projectiles  cast 
great  distances,  in  the  case  of  the  vibrations  of  Fou- 
cault's  pendulum,  and  in  similar  instances.  When  now 
Newton  sought  to  apply  the  mechanical  principles  dis- 
covered since  Galileo's  time  to  the  planetary  system, 
he  found  that,  so  far  as  it  is  possible  to  form  any  es- 
timate at  all  thereof,  the  planets,  irrespectively  of  dy- 
namic effects,  appear  to  preserve  their  direction  and 
velocity  with  respect  to  bodies  of  the  universe  that  are 
very  remote  and  as  regards  each  other  apparently  fixed, 
the  same  as  bodies  moving  on  the  earth  do  with  re- 
spect to  the  fixed  objects  of  the  earth.  The  comport- 
ment of  terrestrial  bodies  with  respect  to  the  earth  is 
•  reducible  to  the  comportment  of  the  earth  with  respect 
to  the  remote  heavenly  bodies.  If  we  were  to  assert 
that  we  knew  more  of  moving  objects  than  this  their 
last  -  mentioned,  experimentally  -  given  comportment 
with  respect  to  the  celestial  bodies,  we  should  render 
ourselves  culpable  of  ^,  falsity.  When,  accordingly,  we 
say,  that  a  body  preserves  unchanged  its  direction  and 
velocity  in  space,  our  ■  assertion  is  nothing  more  or  less 
than  an  abbreviated  reference  to  the  entire  universe. 
The  use  of  such  an  abbreviated  expression  is  permit- 
ted the  original  author  of  the  principle,  because  he 
knows,  that  as  things  are  no  difficulties  stand  in  the 
way  of  carrying  out  its  implied  directions.  But  no 
remedy  lies  in  his  power,  if  difficulties  of  the  kind  men- 
tioned present  themselves;  if,  for  example,  the  re- 
quisite, relatively  fixed  bodies  are  wanting. 


/ 


234  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

The  reia-  7.   Instead,  now,  of  referring  a  moving  body  K  to 

bodies  of    spacc,  that  IS  to  say  to  a  system  of  coordmates,  let  us 

the  uni- 

verse  to      view  directly  its  relation  to  the  bodies  of  the  universe, 

each  other.  .  ,  .   ,        ,  ,  r  ,-  « 

by  which  alone  such  a  system  of  coordmates  can  be 
determined.  Bodies  very  remote  from  each  other,  mov- 
ing with  constant  direction  and  velocity  with  respect 
to  other  distant  fixed  bodies,  change  their  mutual  dis- 
tances proportionately  to  the  time.  We  may  also  say. 
All  very  remote  bodies — all  mutual  or  other  forces  ne- 
glected— alter  their  mutual  distances  proportionately 
to  those  distances.  Two  bodies,  which,  situated  at  a 
short  distance  from  one  another,  move  with  constant 
direction  and  velocity  with  respect  to  other  fixed  bod- 
ies, exhibit  more  complicated  relations.  If  we  should 
regard  the  two  bodies  as  dependent  on  one  another, 
and  call  r  the  distance,  /  the  time,  and  a  a  constant 
dependent  on  the  directions  and  velocities,  the  formula 
would  be  obtained:  d^rjdt^  =  (1/r)  [a^  —  (//r////)2]. 
It  is  manifestly  much  simpler  and  clearer  to  regard  the 
two  bodies  as  independent  of  each  other  and  to  con- 
sider the  constancy  of  their  direction  and  velocity  with 
respect  to  other  bodies. 

Instead  of  saying,  the  direction  and  velocity  of  a 
mass  ji  in  space  remain  constant,  we  may  also  employ 
the  expression,  the  mean  acceleration  of  the  mass  /i 
with  respect  to  the  masses  w,  ni\  m".  ...  at  the  dis- 
tances r,  r',  r".  ...  is  =  0,  or  d^{'2mr/2'm)/dt^  =  0. 
The  latter  expression  is  equivalent  to  the  former,  as 
soon  as  we  take  into  consideration  a  sufficient  number 
of  sufficiently  distant  and  sufficiently  large  masses. 
The  mutual  influence  of  more  proximate  small  masses, 
which  are  apparently  not  concerned  about  each  other, 
is  eliminated  of  itself.  That  the  constancy  of  direction 
and  velocity  is  given  by  the  condition  adduced,  will  be 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  DYNAMICS,  235 

seen  at  once  if  we  construct  through  u  as  vertex  cones  The  ezprea- 

sion  of  the 

that  cut  out  different  portions  of  space,  and  set  up  the  uw  of  iner- 
condition  with  respect  to  the  masses  of  these  separate  of  this  re- 
portions.  We  may  put,  indeed,  for  the  entire  space 
encompassing  //,  d^  {2mr/2tn) /dt^  r=z{i.  But  the 
equation  in  this  case  asserts  nothing  with  respect  to  the 
motion  of  /i,  since  it  holds  good  for  all  species  of  mo- 
tion where  /i  is  uniformly  surrounded  by  an  infinite 
number  of  masses.  If  two  masses  pi^,  M2  ^^^^^  o"  each 
other  a  force  which  is  dependent  on  their  distance  r, 
then  d^rjdf^  =  (/ij  +  /^2)/('')-  ^^^>  ^^  ^^®  ^afne  time, 
the  acceleration  of  the  centre  of  gravity  of  the  two 
masses  or  the  mean  acceleration  of  the  mass-system 
with  respect  to  the  masses  of  the  universe  (by  the  prin- 
ciple of  reaction)  remains  ==  0  ;  that  is  to  say, 


d^ 
~d~t^ 


2mr^  2mr^ 

^1  ~1S^  +  ^»     2m 


=  0. 


When  we  reflect  that  the  time-factor  that  enters  The  necm- 
into  the  acceleration  is  nothing  more  than  a  quantity  ence  of  a 
that  is  the  measure  of  the  distances  (or  angles  of  rota-  Uon  of  the 

All 

tion)  of  the  bodies  of  the  universe,  we  see  that  even  in 
the  simplest  case,  in  which  apparently  we  deal  with 
the  mutual  action  of  only  two  masses,  the  neglecting 
of  the  rest  of  the  world  is  impossible.  Nature  does  not 
begin  with  elements,  as  we  are  obliged  to  begin  with 
them.  It  is  certainly  fortunate  for  us,  that  we  can, 
from  time  to  time,  turn  aside  our  eyes  from  the  over- 
powering unity  of  the  All,  and  allow  them  to  rest  on 
individual  details.  But  we  should  not  omit,  ultimately 
to  complete  and  correct  our  views  by  a  thorough  con- 
sideration of  the  things  which  for  the  time  being  we 
left  out  of  account. 

8.  The  considerations  just  presented  show,  that  it 


236 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 


The  law  of  IS  not  necessarv  to  refer  the  law  of  inertia  to  a  special 

inertia  does  ^>.        •%  •     •  •        j      i 

not  involve  absolute  space.     On  the  contrary,  it  is  perceived  that 

absolute 

space.  the  masses  that  in  the  common  phraseology  exert  forces 
on  each  other  as  well  as  those  that  exert  none,  stand 
with  respect  to  acceleration  in  quite  similar  relations. 
We  may,  indeed,  regard  all  masses  as  related  to  each 
other.  That  accelerations  play  a  prominent  part  in  the 
relations  of  the  masses,  must  be  accepted  as  a  fact  of 
experience  ;  which  does  not,  however,  exclude  attempts 
to  elucidate  this  fact  by  a  comparison  of  it  with  other 
facts,  involving  the  discovery  of  new  points  of  view. 
In  all  the  processes  of  nature  the  differences  of  certain 

quantities    u   play   a   de- 
terminative role.     Differ- 
ences of  temperature,  of 
potential  function,  and  so 
forth,  induce  the  natural 
processes,    which   consist 
in     the     equalisation     of 
these  differences.     The  familiar  expressions  d^u/tlx^y 
d^u/dy^y   d^u/dz^y   which   are   determinative  of   the 
character  of  the  equalisation,  may  be  regarded  as  the 
measure  of  the  departure  of  the  condition  of  any  point 
from  the  mean  of  the  conditions  of  its  environment — 
to  which  mean  the  point  tends.     The  accelerations  of 
masses  may  be  analogously  conceived.    The  great  dis- 
tances between  masses  that  stand  in  no  especial  force- 
relation  to  one  another,  change  proportionately  to  each 
other.     If  we  lay  off,  therefore,  a  certain  distance  p  as 
abscissa,  and  another  r  as  ordinate,  we  obtain  a  straight 
line.     (Fig.  143.)     Every  r-ordinate  corresponding  to 
a  definite  p- value  represents,  accordingly,  the  mean  of 
the  adjacent  ordinates.     If  a  force-relation  exists  be- 
tween the  bodies,  some  value  d^r/dt^  is  determined 


F»«  143. 


Natural 
processes 
consist  in 
the  equali- 
sation of 
the  differ- 
ences of 
quantities. 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  D  YNAMICS.  237 

by  it  which  conformably  to  the  remarks  above  we  may 
replace  by  an  expression  of  the  form  d^r/dp^.  By  the 
force-relation,  therefore,  a  departure  of  the  r-ordinate 
from  the  mean  of  the  adjacent  ordinates  is  produced, 
which  would  not  exist  if  the  supposed  force-relation 
did  not  obtain.     This  intimation  will  suffice  here. 

9.  We  have  attempted  in  the  foregoing  to  give  the  character 
law  of  inertia  a  different  expression  from  that  in  ordi-  expression 
nary  use.  This  expression  will,  so  long  as  a  suffi- of  inertia, 
cient  number  of  bodies  are  apparently  fixed  in  space, 
accomplish  the  same  as  the  ordinary  one.  It  is  as 
easily  applied,  and  it  encounters  the  same  difficulties. 
In  the  one  case  we  are  unable  to  come  at  an  absolute 
space,  in  the  other  a  limited  number  of  masses  only  is 
within  the  reach  of  our  knowledge,  and  the  summation 
indicated  can  consequently  not  be  fully  carried  out.  It 
is  impossible  to  say  whether  the  new  expression  would 
still  represent  the  true  condition  of  things  if  the  stars 
were  to  perform  rapid  movements  among  one  another. 
The  general  experience  cannot  be  constructed  from  the 
particular  case  given  us.  We  must,  on  the  contrary, 
wait  until  such  an  experience  presents  itself.  Perhaps 
when  our  physico-astronomical  knowledge  has  been 
extended,  it  will  be  offered  somewhere  in  celestial 
space,  where  more  violent  and  complicated  motions 
take  place  than  in  our  environment.  The  most  impor-  The  sim- 
tant*result  of  our  reflexions  is,  however,  that  precisely  c\^\e&ot 

mechanics 

the  apparently  simplest  mechanical  principles  are  of  a  tfery  are  of  a 
complicated  character ,  that  these  principles  are  founded  on  plfcat^edna- 
uncompleted  experiences^  nay  on  experiences  that  never  can  all  derived 
be  fully  completed,  that  practically y  indeed^  they  are  suf  rience. 
ficiently  secured^  in  view  of  the  tolerable  stability  of  our 
environment y  to  serve  as  the  foundation  of  mathematical 
deduction^  but  that  they  can  by  no  means  themselves  be  re- 


238  TJIE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

garded  as  mathematically  established  truths  but  only  as 
principles  that  not  only  admit  of  constant  control  by  expe- 
rience but  actually  require  it.  This  perception  is  valu- 
able in  that  it  is  propitious  to  the  advancement  of 
science.     (Compare  Appendix,  IV.) 

VII. 
SYNOPTICAL  CRITIQUE  OF  THE  NEWTONIAN  ENUNCIATIONS. 

Newton's  I.   Now  that  we  have  discussed  the  details  with 

sufficient  particularity,  we  may  pass  again  under  re- 
view the  form  and  the  disposition  of  the  Newtonian 
enunciations.  .  Newton  premises  to  his  work  several 
definitions,  following  which  he  gives  the  laws  of  mo- 
tion.    We  shall  take  up  the  former  first. 

Mass.  ^^  Definition  I,    The  quantity  of  any  matter  is  the 

**  measure  of  it  by  its  density  and  volume  conjointly. 
"...  This  quantity  is  what  I  shall  understand  by  the 
**  term  mass  or  body  in  the  discussions  to  follow.  It  is 
* '  ascertainable  from  the  weight  of  the  body  in  ques- 
'*tion.  For  I  have  found,  by  pendulum -experiments 
"of  high  precision,  that  the  mass  of  a  body  is  propor- 
"  tional  to  its  weight ;  as  will  hereafter  be  shown. 

Quantity  of        ^^  Definition  II,  Quantity  of  motion  is  the  measure 

motion,  e    •      \  %  «       •  i  •  r 

inertia,       "  of  it  by  the  velocity  and  quantity  of  matter  con- 
force,  and        .    .     , 
accelera-       * '  J  Ol  n  tly . 

'*  Definition  III  The  resident  force  [vis  insita^  i.  e. 
"the  inertia]  of  matter  is  a  power  of  resisting,  by 
"which  every  body,  so  far  as  in  it  lies,  perseveres  in 
"its  state  of  rest  or  of  uniform  motion  in  a  straight 
"line. 

Definition  IV,  An  impressed  force  is  any  action 
upon  a  body  which  changes,  or  tends  to  change^  its 
state  of  rest,  or  of  uniform  motion  in  a  straight  line. 


tion. 


it 
it 
ti 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  D  YNAMICS. 


239 


**  Definition  V.  A  centripetal  force  is  any  force  by 
which  bodies  are  drawn  or  impelled  towards,  or  tend 
in  any  way  to  reach,  some  point  as  centre. 

^^  Definition  VI,  The  absolute  quantity  of  a  centri- 
petal force  is  a  measure  of  it  increasing  and  dimin- 
ishing with  the  efficacy  of  the  cause  that  propagates 
it  from  the  centre  through  the  space  round  about. 

^^  Definition  VII.  The  accelerative  quantity  of  a 
centripetal  force  is  the  measure  of  it  proportional  to 
the  velocity  which  it  generates  in  a  given  time. 

^^ Definition  VIII.  The  moving  quantity  of  a  cen- 
tripetal force  is  the  measured  of  it  proportional  to  the 
motion  [See  Def.  11.]  which  it  generates  in  a  given 
time. 

<<  The  three  quantities  or  measures  of  force  thus  dis- 
tinguished, may,  for  brevity's  sake,  be  called  abso- 
lute, accelerative,  and  moving  forces,  being,  for  dis- 
tinction's sake,  respectively  referred  to  the  centre  of 
force,  to  the  places  of  the  bodies,  and  to  the  bodies 
that  tend  to  the  centre  :  that  is  to  say,  I  refer  moving 
force  to  the  body,  as  being  an  endeavor  of  the  whole 
towards  the  centre,  arising  from  the  collective  en- 
deavors of  the  several  parts ;  accelerative  force  to  the 
place  of  the  body,  as  being  a  sort  of  efficacy  originat- 
ing in  the  centre  and  diffused  throughout  all  the  sev- 
eral places  round  about,  in  moving  the  bodies  that 
are  at  these  places  ;  and  absolute  force  to  the  centre, 
as  invested  with  some  cause,  without  which  moving 
forces  would  not  be  propagated  through  the  space 
round  about ;  whether  this  latter  cause  be  some  cen- 
tral body,  (such  as  is  a  loadstone  in  a  centre  of  mag- 
netic force,  or  the  earth  in  the  centre  of  the  force  of 
gravity,)  or  anything  else  not  visible.  This,  at  least, 
is  the  mathematical  conception  of  forces ;  for  their 


Forces  clas- 
sified as  ab- 
solute, ac- 
celerative, 
and  mov- 
ing. 


The  rela- 
tions of  the 
forces  thus 
distin- 
guished. 


240 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 


The  dis- 
tinction 
mathemat- 
ical and  not 
physical. 


'  physical  causes  and  seats  I  do  not  in  this  place  con- 
'  sider. 

"Accelerating  force,  therefore,  is  to  moving  force, 

*  as  velocity  is  to  quantity  of  motion.     For  quantity 

*  of  motion  arises  from  the  velocity  and  the  quantity 
'  of  matter  ;  and  moving  force  arises  from  the  accel- 

*  erating  force  and  the  same  quantity  of  matter ;  the 
'  sum  of  the  effects  of  the  accelerative  force  on  the  sev- 

*  eral  particles  of  the  body  being  the  motive  force  of 
*the  whole.  Hence,  near  the  surface  of  the  earth, 
'  where  the  accelerative  gravity  or  gravitating  force  is 

*  in  all  bodies  the  same,  the  motive  force  of  gravity  or 
'the  weight  is  as  the  body  [mass].  But  if  we  ascend 
*to  higher  regions,  where  the  accelerative  force  of 

*  gravity  is  less,  the  weight  will  be  equally  diminished, 
'  always  remaining  proportional  conjointly  to  the  mass 

*  and  the  accelerative  force  of  gravity.    Thus,  in  those 

*  regions  where  the  accelerative  force  of  gravity  is  half 

<  as  great,  the  weight  of  a  body  will  be  diminished  by 

*  one- half.  Further,  I  apply  the  terms  accelerative  and 

<  motive  in  one  and  the  same  sense  to  attractions  and 

*  to  impulses.   I  employ  the  expressions  attraction,  im- 

*  pulse,  or  propensity  of  any  kind  towards  a  centre, 

<  promiscuously  and  indifferently,  the  one  for  the  other; 
'  considering  those  forces  not  in  a  physical  sense,  but 
'mathematically.  The  reader,  therefore,  must  not 
'  infer  from  any  expressions  of  this  kind  that  I  may 

<  use,  that  I  take  upon  me  to  explain  the  kind  or  the 

<  mode  of  an  action,  or  the  causes  or  the  physical  rea- 
'  son  thereof,  or  that  I  attribute  forces  in  a  true  or 

*  physical  sense,  to  centres  (which  are  only  mathemat- 
'  ical  points),  when  at  any  time  I  happen  to  say  that 
'centres  attract  or  that  central  forces  are  in  action." 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  DYNAMICS,  241 

2.  Definition  i  is,  as  has  already  been  set  forth,  a  criticism  of 
pseudo-definition.  The  concept  of  mass  is  not  made  Definitions. 
clearer  by  describing  mass  as  the  product  of  the  volume 

into  the  density,  as  density  itself  denotes  simply  the 
mass  of  unit  of  volume.  The  true  definition  of  mass 
can  be  deduced  only  from  the  dynamical  relations  of 
bodies. 

To  Definition  11,  which  simply  enunciates  a  mode 
of  computation,  no  objection  is  to  be  made.  Defini- 
tion III  (inertia),  however,  is  rendered  superfluous  by 
Definitions  iv-viii  of  force,  inertia  being  included  and 
given  in  the  fact  that  forces  are  accelerative. 

Definition  iv  defines  force  as  the  cause  of  the  accel- 
eration, or  tendency  to  acceleration,  of  a  body.  The 
latter  part  of  this  is  justified  by  the  fact  that  in  the 
cases  also  in  which  accelerations  cannot  take  place, 
other  attractions  that  answer  thereto,  as  the  compres- 
sion and  distension  etc.  of  bodies  occur.  The  cause 
of  an  acceleration  towards  a  definite  centre  is  defined 
in  Definition  v  as  centripetal  force,  and  is  distinguished 
in  VI,  VII,  and  viii  as  absolute,  accelerative,  and  mo- 
tive. It  is,  we  may  say,  a  matter  of  taste  and  of  form 
whether  we  shall  embody  the  explication  of  the  idea 
of  force  in  one  or  in  several  definitions.  In  point  of 
principle  the  Newtonian  definitions  are  open  to  no  ob- 
jections. 

3.  The  Axioms  or  Laws  of  Motion  then  follow,  of  Newton's 

Lftws  of 

which  Newton  enunciates  three  :  Motion. 

'*  Law  /.  Every  body  perseveres  in  its  state  of  rest 
"or  of  uniform  motion  in  a  straight  line,  except  in  so 
far  as  it  is  compelled  to  change  that  state  by  im- 
pressed forces." 
'*  Law  II,  Change  of  motion  [i.  e.  of  momentum]  is 
**  proportional  to  the  moving  force  impressed,  and  takes 


242  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

• 

"  place  in  the  direction  of  the  straight  line  in  which 
'*such  force  is  impressed." 
^  ^^  Law  III,   Reaction  is  always  equal  and  opposite 

<'to  action;  that  is  to  say,  the  actions  of  two  bodies 
<  <  upon  each  other  are  always  equal  and  directly  op- 
"posite." 

Newton  appends  to  these  three  laws  a  number  of 
Corollaries.  The  first  and  second  relate  to  the  prin- 
ciple of  the  parallelogram  of  forces ;  the  third  to  the 
quantity  of  motion  generated  in  the  mutual  action  of 
bodies ;  the  fourth  to  the  fact  that  the  motion  of  the 
centre  of  gravity  is  not  changed  by  the  mutual  action 
of  bodies  \  the  fifth  and  sixth  to  relative  motion. 
Criticism  of       4.  We  readily  perceive  that  Laws  i  and  ii  are  con- 

f^  Aorf  Qfl  *  Q 

laws  of       tained  in  the  definitions  of  force  that  precede.     Ac- 


motion. 


cording  to  the  latter,  without  force  there  is  no  accel- 
eration, consequently  only  rest  or  uniform  motion  in  a 
straight  line.     Furthermore,  it  is  wholly  unnecessary 
tautology,  after  having  established  acceleration  as  the 
measure  of  force,  to  say  again  that  change  of  motion  is 
proportional  to  the  force.    It  would  have  been  enough 
to  say  that  the  definitions  premised  were  not  arbitrary 
mathematical  ones,   but  correspond  to  properties  of 
bodies  experimentally  given.  The  third  law  apparently 
contains  something  new.     But  we  have  seen  that  it  is 
unintelligible  without  the  correct  idea  of  mass,  which 
idea,  being  itself  obtained  only  from  dynamical  expe- 
rience, renders  the  law  unnecessary. 
Thccoroi-         The  first  corollary  really  does  contain  something/ 
these  laws.  new.     But  it  regards  the  accelerations  determined  in) 
a  body  K  by  different  bodies  M^  Ny  P  as  self- evidently^, 
independent  of  each  other,  whereas  this  is  precisely^ 
what  should  have  been  explicitly  recognised  as  a  fad 
of  experience.     Corollary  Second  is  a  simple  applica- 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  D  YNAMICS.  243 

tion  of  the  law  enunciated  in  corollary  First.  The  re- 
maining corollaries,  likewise,  are  simple  deductions, 
that  is,  mathematical  consequences,  from  the  concep- 
tions and  laws  that  precede. 

5.  Even  if  we  adhere  absolutely  to  the  Newtonian 
points  of  view,  and  disregard  the  complications  and  in- 
definite features  mentioned,  which  are  not  removed 
but  merely  concealed  by  the  abbreviated  designations 
"Time"  and  "Space,"  it  is  possible  to  replace  New- 
ton's enunciations  by  much  more  simple,  methodically 
better  arranged,  and  more  satisfactory  propositions. 
Such,  in  our  estimation,  would  be  the  following  : 

a.  Experimental  Proposition,     Bodies  set  opposite  Proposed 
each  other  induce  in  each  other,  under  certain  circum-  tions  for 
stances  to  be  specified  by  experimental  physics,  con-  tonian  laws 
trary  accelerations  in  the  direction  of  their  line  of  junc-  tions. 
tion.     (The  principle  of  inertia  is  included  in  this.) 

b.  Definition,  The  mass-ratio  of  any  two  bodies  is 
the  negative  inverse  ratio  of  the  mutually  induced  ac- 
celerations of  those  bodies. 

c.  Experimental  Proposition,  The  mass-ratios  of 
bodies  are  independent  of  the  character  of  the  physical 
states  (of  the  bodies)  that  condition  the  mutual  accel- 
erations produced,  be  those  states  electrical,  magnetic, 
or  what  not ;  and  they  remain,  moreover,  the  same, 
whether  they  are  mediately  or  immediately  arrived  at. 

d.  Experimental  Proposition.  The  accelerations 
which  any  number  of  bodies  Ay  B,  C ,  .  .  .  induce  in  a 
body  K,  are  independent  of  each  other.  (The  principle 
of  the  parallelogram  of  forces  follows  immediately  from 
this.) 

e.  Definition.  Moving  force  is  the  product  of  the 
mass- value  of  a  body  into  the  acceleration  induced  in 
that  body. 


244  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

Extent  and        Then  the  remaining  arbitrary  definitions  of  the  al- 

ch&ractcr 

of  the  pro-  gebraical  expressions  "momentum,"  "vis  viva,"  and 
stitutions.  the  like,  might  follow.  But  these  are  by  no  means  in- 
dispensable. The  propositions  above  set  forth  satisfy 
the  requirements  of  simplicity  and  parsimony  which, 
on  economico-sclentific  grounds,  must  be  exacted  of 
them.  They  are,  moreover,  obvious  and  clear  ;  for  no 
doubt  can  exist  with  respect  to  any  one  of  them  either 
concerning  its  meaning  or  its  source  ;  and  we  always 
know  whether  it  asserts  an  experience  or  an  arbitrary 
convention. 
The  6.   Upon  the  whole,  we  may  say,  that  Newton  dis- 

achieve- 

ments  of  cemed  in  an  admirable  manner  the  concepts  and  princi- 
from  the  ples  that  Were  sufficiently  assured  to  allow  of  being  fur- 
view  of  bis  ther  built  upon.  It  is  possible  that  to  some  extent  he 
was  forced  by  the  difi&culty  and  novelty  of  his  subject, 
in  the  minds  of  the  contemporary  world,  to  great  am- 
plitude, and,  therefore,  to  a  certain  disconnectedness 
of  presentation,  in  consequence  of  which  one  and  the 
same  property  of  mechanical  processes  appears  several 
times  formulated.  To  some  extent,  however,  he  was, 
as  it  is  possible  to  prove,  not  perfectly  clear  himself 
concerning  the  import  and  especially  concerning  the 
source  of  his  principles.  This  cannot,  however,  ob- 
scure in  the  slightest  his  intellectual  greatness.  He 
that  has  to  acquire  a  new  point  of  view  naturally  can- 
not possess  it  so  securely  from  the  beginning  as  they 
that  receive  it  unlaboriously  from  him.  He  has  done 
enough  if  he  has  discovered  truths  on  which  future 
generations  can  further  build.  For  every  new  infer- 
ence therefrom  affords  at  once  a  new  insight,  a  new 
control,  an  extension  of  our  prospect,  and  a  clarifica- 
tion of  our  field  of  view.  Like  the  commander  of  an 
army,  a  great  discoverer  cannot  stop  to  institute  petty 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  D  YNAMICS.  245 

inquiries  regarding  the  right  by  which  he  holds  each  The 
post  of  vantage  he  has  won.     The  magnitude  of  the  ments  of 
problem  to  be  solved  leaves  no  time  for  this.     But  at  the  light  of 
a  later  period,  the  case  is  different.     Newton  might  re«earch. 
well  have  expected  of  the  two  centuries  to  follow  that 
they  should  further  examine  and  confirm  the  founda- 
tions of  his  work,  and  that,  when  times  of  greater  scien- 
tific tranquillity  should  come,  the  principles  of  the  sub- 
ject might  acquire  an  even  higher  philosophical  in- 
terest than  all  that  is  deducible  from  them.  Then  prob- 
lems arise  like  those  just  treated  of,  to  the  solution  of 
which,  perhaps,  a  small  contribution  has  here  been 
made.    We  join  with  the  eminent  physicists  Thomson 
and  Tait,  in  our  reverence  and  admiration  of  Newton. 
But  we  can  only  comprehend  with  difficulty  their  opin- 
ion that  the  Newtonian  doctrines  still  remain  the  best 
and  most  philosophical  foundation  of  the  science  that 
can  be  given. 

VIII. 

RETROSPECT  OF  THE  DEVELOPMENT  OF  DYNAMICS. 

• 

I.  If  we  pass  in  review  the  period  in  which  the  de- The  chief 
velopment  of  dynamics  fell, — a  period  inaugurated  by  discovery 
Galileo,  continued  by  Huygens,  and  brought  to  a  close  fact, 
by  Newton, — its  main  result  will  be  found  to  be  the 
perception,  that  bodies  mutually  determine  in  each 
other  accelerations  dependent  on  definite  spatial  and. 
material  circumstances,  and  that  there  are  masses.  The 
reason  the  perception  of  these  facts  was  embodied  in 
so  great  a  number  of  principles  is  wholly  an  historical 
one  ;  the  perception  was  not  reached  at  once,  but  slowly 
and  by  degrees.     In  reality  only  one  great  fact  was  es- 
tablished.    Different  pairs  of  bodies  determine,  inde- 
pendently of  each  other,  and  mutually,  in  themselves. 


246  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

pairs  of  accelerations,  whose  terms  exhibit  a  constant 
ratio,  the  criterion  and  characteristic  of  each  pair. 
This  fact  Not  even  men  of  the  calibre  of  Galileo,  Huygens, 

greatest  in-  and  Newton  were  able  to  perceive  this  fact  at  once, 
could  per-  Even  they  could  only  discover  it  piece  by  piece,  as  it 
in  frag-       is  expressed  in  the  law  of  falling  bodies,  in  the  special 


Dients. 


law  of  inertia,  in  the  principle  of  the  parallelogram  of 
forces,  in  the  concept  of  mass,  and  so  forth.  To-day, 
no  difi&culty  any  longer  exists  in  apprehending  the  unity 
of  the  whole  fact.  The  practical  demands  of  communi- 
cation alone  can  justify  its  piecemeal  presentation  in 
several  distinct  principles,  the  number  of  which  is  really 
only  determined  by  scientific  taste.  What  is  more,  a 
reference  to  the  reflections  above  set  forth  respecting 
the  ideas  of  time,  inertia,  and  the  like,  will  surely  con- 
vince us  that,  accurately  viewed,  the  entire  fact  has, 
in  all  its  aspects,  not  yet  been  perfectly  apprehended. 
The  results        The  point  of  vicw  reached  has,  as  Newton  expressly 

re  ached 

havenoth-  States,  nothing  to  do  with  the  "  unknown  causes "  of 
with  the  so-  natural  phenomena.  That  which  in  the  mechanics  of 
"causes"    the  present  day  is  called  force  is  not  a  something  that 

of  phenom- 
ena, lies  latent  in  the  natural  processes,  but  a  measurable, 

actual  circumstance  of  motion,  the  product  of  the  mass 
into  the  acceleration.  Also  when  we  speak  of  the  at- 
tractions or  repulsions  of  bodies,  it  is  not  necessary  to 
think  of  any  hidden  causes  of  the  motions  produced. 
We  signalise  by  the  term  attraction  merely  an  actually 
existing  resemblance  between  events  determined  by  con- 
ditions of  motion  and  the  results  of  our  volitional  im- 
pulses. In  both  cases  either  actual  motion  occurs  or, 
when  the  motion  is  counteracted  by  some  other  circum- 
stance of  motion,  distortion,  compression  of  bodies, 
and  so  forth,  are  produced. 

2.  The  work  which  devolved  on  genius  here,  was 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  DYNAMICS.  247 

the  noting  of  the  connection  of  certain  determinative  The  form  of 
elements  of  the  mechanical  processes.  The  precise  es-  chanicai 
tablishment  of  the  form  of  this  connection  was  rather  a  f^the  m^n 
task  for  plodding  research,  which  created  the  different  icai  origin. 
concepts  and  principles  of  mechanics.     We  can  de- 
termine the  true  value  and  significance  of  these  prin- 
ciples and  concepts  only  by  the  investigation  of  their 
historical  origin.     In  this  it  appears  unmistakable  at 
times,  that  accidental  circumstances  have  given  to  the 
course  of  their  development  a  peculiar  direction,  which 
under  other  conditions  might  have  been  very  different. 
Of  this  an  example  shall  be  given. 

Before  Galileo  assumed  the  familiar  fact  of  the  de-  For  exam- 
pendence  of  the  final  velocity  on  the  time,  and  put  it  to  leo's  laws 

,  ,  .  ,  ,  ,  ,         ^     of  falling 

the  test  of  experiment,  he  essayed,  as  we  have  already  bodies 
seen,  a  different  hypothesis,  and  made  the  final  velocity  taken  a  dif- 
proportional  to  the  space  described.  He  imagined,  by  a 
course  of  fallacious  reasoning,  likewise  already  referred 
to,  that  this  assumption  involved  a  self-contradiction. 
His  reasoning  was,  that  twice  any  given  distance  of  de- 
scent must,  by  virtue  of  the  double  final  velocity  ac- 
quired, necessarily  be  traversed  in  the  same  time  as  the 
simple  distance  of  descent.  But  since  the  first  half  is 
necessarily  traversed  first,  the  remaining  half  will  have 
to  be  traversed  instantaneously,  that  is  in  an  interval 
of  time  not  measurable.  Whence,  it  readily  follows, 
that  the  descent  of  bodies  generally  is  instantaneous. 

The  fallacies  involved  in  this  reasoning  are  manifest.  Galileo's 
Galileo  was,  of  course,  not  versed  in  mental  integra-  and?u 
tions,  and  having  at  his  command  no  adequate  methods 
for  the  solution  of  problems  whose  facts  were  in  any 
degree  complicated,  he  could  not  but  fall  into  mistakes 
whenever  such  cases  were  presented.  If  we  call  s  the 
distance  and  /  the  tinie,  the  Galilean  assumption  reads 


errors. 


248  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

in  the  language  of  to-day  dsjdt  =zas^  from  which  fol- 
lows s^^Ai"^,  where  a  is  a  constant  of  experience  and 
A  a  constant  of  integration.  This  is  an  entirely  different 
conclusion  from  that  drawn  by  Galileo.     It  does  not 
conform,  it  is  true,  to  experience,  and  Galileo  would 
probably  have  taken  exception  to  a  result  that,  as  a 
condition  of  motion  generally,  made  s  different  from  0 
when  /  equalled  0.     But  in  itself  the  assumption  is  by 
no  means  j-^^-contradictory. 
The  suppo-        Let  us  suppose  that  Kepler  had  put  to  himself  the 
Kepler  had  same  questiou.     Whereas  Galileo  always  sought  after 
leo's  re-      the  Very  simplest  solutions  of  things,  and  at  once  re- 

86  Aire  tl  fiS 

jected  hypotheses  that  did  not  fit,  Kepler's  mode  of  pro- 
cedure was  entirely  different.  He  did  not  quail  before 
the  most  complicated  assumptions,  but  worked  his  way, 
by  the  constant  gradual  modification  of  his  original 
hypothesis,  successfully  to  his  goal,  as  the  history  of 
his  discovery  of  the  laws  of  planetary  motion  fully 
shows.  Most  likely,  Kepler,  on  finding  the  assumption 
dsjdt  =^as  would  not  work,  would  have  tried  a  num- 
ber of  others,  and  among  them  probably  the  correct  one 
ds/dt z=a\/s.  But  from  this  would  have  resulted  an 
essentially  different  course  of  development  for  the  sci- 
ence of  dynamics. 
In  such  a  It  is  Only  gradually  and  with  great  difficulty  that 

c&sc  the 

concept      the  concept  of  *  *  work  "  has  attained  its  present  position 

"  work  " 

might  have  of  importance  ;  and  in  our  judgment  it  is  to  the  above- 

been  the 

original  mentioned  trifling  historical  circumstance  that  the  diffi- 
inechanics.  cultics  and  obstacles  it  had  to  encounter  are  to  be  as- 
cribed. As  the  interdependence  of  the  velocity  and  the 
time  was,  as  it  chanced,  first  ascertained,  it  could  not 
be  otherwise  than  that  the  relation  v  =  gt  should  appear 
as  the  original  one,  the  equation  s  =  gt^/2  2iS  the  next 
immediate,  and  gs  =  v^/2  as  a  remoter  inference.    In- 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  DYNAMICS.  249 

troducing  the  concepts  mass  {nC)  and  force  (/),  where 
p  =  mgy  we  obtain,  by  multiplying  the  three  equations 
by  »*,  the  expressions  mv=:^fty  »ij=//*/2,  fs=:^ 
tnv^  ji — the  fundamental  equations  of  mechanics.  Of 
necessity,  therefore,  the  concepts  force  and  momentum 
{m  v)  appear  more  primitive  than  the  concepts  work  (/ j) 
and  vis  viva  (jnv^).  It  is  not  to  be  wondered  at,  accord- 
ingly, that,  wherever  the  idea  of  work  made  its  appear- 
ance, it  was  always  sought  to  replace  it  by  the  histor- 
ically older  concepts.  The  entire  dispute  of  the  Leib- 
nitzians  and  Cartesians,  which  was  first  composed  in 
a  manner  by  D'Alembert,  finds  its  complete  explana- 
tion in  this  fact. 

From  an  unbiassed  point  of  view,  we  have  exactly  Jastifica- 

,  .  tion  of  this 

the  same  right  to  inquire  after  the  interdependence  of  view, 
the  final  velocity  and  the  time  as  after  the  interde- 
pendence of  the  final  velocity  and  the  distance,  and  to 
answer  the  question  by  experiment.  The  first  inquiry 
leads  us  to  the  experiential  truth,  that  given  bodies  in 
contraposition  impart  to  each  other  in  given  times  defi- 
nite increments  of  velocity.  The  second  informs  us, 
that  given  bodies  in  contraposition  impart  to  each  other 
for  given  mutual  displacements  definite  increments  of 
velocities.  Both  propositions  are  equally  justified,  and 
both  may  be  regarded  as  equally  original. 

The  correctness  of  this  view  has  been  substantiated  Exempiifi- 

,,         1  A        t  ^    -r^    ^m  -»«•  cation  of  it 

m  our  own  day  by  the  example  of  J.  R.  Mayer.  Mayer,  in  modem 
a  modem  mind  of  the  Galilean  stamp,  a  mind  wholly 
free  from  the  influences  of  the  schools,  of  his  own  in- 
dependent accord  actually  pursued  the  last-named 
method,  and  produced  by  it  an  extension  of  science 
which  the  schools  did  not  accomplish  until  later  in  a 
much  less  complete  and  less  simple  form.  For  Mayer, 
work  was  the  original  concept.     That  which  is  called 


aso  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

work  in  the  mechanics  of  the  schools,  he  calls  force. 

Mayer's  error  was,  that  he  regarded  his  method  as  the 

only  correct  one. 
Thnxvmsttk        3.  We  may,  therefore,  as  it  suits  us,  regard  the  time 
from  it.       of  dcscent  or  the  distance  of  descent  as  the  factor  de- 


terminative of  velocity.  If  ^ro  fix  our  attention  on 
the  first  circumstance,  the  concept  of  force  appears  as 
the  original  notion,  the  concept  of  work  as  the  derived 
one.  If  we  investigate  the  influence  of  the  second  fact 
first,  the  concept  of  work  is  the  original  notion.  In 
the  transference  of  the  ideas  reached  in  the  observation 
of  the  motion  of  descent  to  more  complicated  relations, 
force  is  recognised  as  dependent  on  the  distance  be- 
tween the  bodies — that  is,  as  a  function  of  the  distance, 
/(r).  The  work  done  through  the  element  of  distance  dr 
is  then/(r)  dr.  By  the  second  method  of  investiga- 
tion work  is  also  obtained  as  a  function  of  the  distance, 
F  (r)  ;  but  in  this  case  we  know  force  only  in  the  form 
d.  F{r)/dr — that  is  to  say,  as  the  limiting  value  of  the 
ratio  :  (increment  of  work)/(increment  of  distance.) 
The  prefer-  Galileo  cultivated  by  preference  the  first  of  these 
different  in-  two  methods.  Newtou  likewise  preferred  it.  Huygens 
pursued  the  second  method,  without  at  all  restricting 
himself  to  it.  Descartes  elaborated  Galileo's  ideas  after 
a  fashion  of  his  own.  But  his  performances  are  in- 
significant compared  with  those  of  Newton  and  Huy- 
gens, and  their  influence  was  soon  totally  effaced.  After 
Huygens  and  Newton,  the  mingling  of  the  two  spheres 
of  thought,  the  independence  and  equivalence  of  which 
are  not  always  noticed,  led  to  various  blunders  and 
confusions,  especially  in  the  dispute  between  the  Car- 
tesians and  Leibnitzians,  already  referred  to,  concern- 
ing the  measure  of  force.  In  recent  times,  however,  in- 
quirers turn  by  preference  now  to  the  one  and  now  to 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  DTNAMaCS.     .  251 

the  other.  Thus  the  Galileo-Newtonian  ideas  are  culti- 
vated with  preference  by  the  school  of  Poinsot,  the 
Galileo- Huygenian  by  the  school  of  Poncelet. 

4.  Newton  operates  almost  exclusively  with  the  no-  The  impor- 

,  ,      tance  and 

tions  of  force,  mass,  and  momentum.  His  sense  of  the  history  of 
value  of  the  concept  of  m^ss  places  him  above  his  prede-  toman  con- 
cessors  and  contemporaries.  It  did  not  occur  to  Galileo  mass. 
that  mass  and  weight  were  different  things.  Huygens, 
too,  in  all  his  considerations,  puts  weights  for  masses ; 
as  for  example  in  his  investigations  concerning  the 
centre  of  oscillation.  Even  in  the  treatise  De  Percus- 
stone  (On  Impact),  Huygens  always  says  ''corpus  ma- 
jus,"  the  larger  body,  and  '*  corpus  minus,"  the  smaller 
body,  when  he  means  the  larger  or  the  smaller  mass. 
Physicists  were  not  led  to  form  the  concept  mass  till 
they  made  the  discovery  that  the  same  body  can  by  the 
action  of  gravity  receive  different  accelerations.  The 
first  occasion  of  this  discovery  was  the  pendulum-ob- 
servations of  Richer  (i 671-1673), — from  which  Huy- 
gens at  once  drew  the  proper  inferences, — and  the 
second  was  the  extension  of  the  dynamical  laws  to  the 
heavenly  bodies.  The  importance  of  the  first  point  may 
be  inferred  from  the  fact  that  Newton,  to  prove  the  pro- 
portionality of  mass  and  weight  on  the  same  spot  of  the 
earth,  personally  instituted  accurate  observations  on 
pendulums  of  different  materials  {Principia,  Lib.  II, 
Sect.  VI,  De  Motu  et  Resistentia  Corporum  Funependu- 
lorutn).  In  the  case  of  John  Bernoulli,  also,  the  first 
distinction  between  mass  and  weight  (in  the  Meditatio 
de  Natura  Centri  Oscillaiionis,  Opera  Omnia^  Lausanne 
and  Geneva,  Vol.  II,  p.  168)  was  made  on  the  ground 
of  the  fact  that  the  same  body  can  receive  different 
gravitational  accelerations.  Newton,  accordingly,  dis- 
poses of  all  dynamical  questions  involving  the  relations 


252  .       THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

of  several  bodies  to  each  other,  by  the  help  of  the  ideas 
of  force,  mass,  and  momentum. 
Tbemeth-  5.  Huygens  pursued  a  different  method  for  the  so- 
gana.  "^  lution  of  these  problems.  Galileo  had  previously  dis- 
covered that  a  body  rises  by  virtue  of  the  velocity  ac- 
quired in  its  descent  to  exactly  the  same  height  as  that 
from  which  it  fell.  Huygens,  generalising  the  principle 
(in  his  Horologium  Oscillaiorium)  to  the  effect  that  the 
centre  of  gravity  of  any  system  of  bodies  will  rise  by 
virtue  of  the  velocities  acquired  in  its  descent  to  ex- 
actly the  same  height  as  that  from  which  it  fell,  reached 
the  principle  of  the  equivalence  of  work  and  vis  viva. 
The  names  of  the  formulae  which  he  obtained,  were, 
of  course,  not  supplied  until  long  afterwards. 

The  Huygenian  principle  of  work  was  received  by 
the  contemporary  world  with  almost  universal  distrust. 
People  contented  themselves  with  making  use  of  its 
brilliant  consequences.  It  was  always  their  endeavor 
to  replace  its  deductions  by  others.  Even  after  John 
and  Daniel  Bernoulli  had  extended  the  principle,  it 
was  its  fruitfulness  rather  than  its  evidency  that  was 
valued. 
The  meth-  We  observe,  that  the  Galileo-Newtonian  principles 
ton  and  Were,  ou  accouut  of  their  greater  simplicity  and  ap- 
compared.  pareutly  greater  evidency,  invariably  preferred  to  the 
Galileo-Huygenian.  The  employment  of  the  latter  is 
exacted  only  by  necessity  in  cases  in  which  the  em- 
ployment of  the  former,  owing  to  the  laborious  atten- 
tion to  details  demanded,  is  impossible  ;  as  in  the  case 
of  John  and  Daniel  Bernoulli's  investigations  of  the 
motion  of  fluids. 

If  we  look  at  the  matter  closely,  however,  the  same 
simplicity  and  evidency  will  be  found  to  belong  to  the 
Huygenian  principles  as  to  the  Newtonian  proposi- 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  DYNAMICS.  253 

tions.  That  the  velocity  of  a  body  is  determined  by 
the  time  of  descent  or  determined  by  the  distance  of 
descent,  are  assumptions  equally  natural  and  equally 
simple.  The  form  of  the  law  must  in  both  cases  be 
supplied  by  experience.  As  a  starting-point,  therefore, 
pt  =zmv  and /J  =zmv^ /2  are  equally  well  fitted. 

6.  When  we  pass  to  the  investigation  of  the  motion  The  nece»- 
of  several  bodies,  we  are  again  compelled,  in  both  cases,  unfversai- 
to  take  a  second  step  of  an  equal  degree  of  certainty,  two  meth- 
The  Newtonian  idea  of  mass  is  justified  by  the  fact, 
that,  if  relinquished,  all  rules  of  action  for  events  would 
have  an  end  ;  that  we  should  forthwith  have  to  expect 
contradictions  of  our  commonest  and  crudest  experi- 
ences ]  and  that  the  physiognomy  of  our  mechanical 
environment  would  become  unintelligible.  The  same 
thing  must  be  said  of  the  Huygenian  principle  of  work. 
If  we  surrender  the  theorem  2ps  =z2mv^ /2j  heavy 
bodies  will,  by  virtue  of  their  own  weights,  be  able  to 
ascend  higher ;  all  known  rules  of  mechanical  occur- 
rences will  have  an  end.  The  instinctive  factors  which 
entered  alike  into  the  discovery  of  the  one  view  and  of 
the  other  have  been  already  discussed. 

The  two  spheres  of  ideas  could,  of  course,  have  The  points 
grown  up  much  more  independently  of  each  other.  But  of  the  two 
in  view  of  the  fact  that  the  two  were  constantly  in  con- 
tact, it  is  no  wonder  that  they  have  become  partially 
merged  in  each  other,  and  that  the  Huygenian  appears 
the  less  complete.  Newton  is  all-sufficient  with  his 
forces,  masses,  and  momenta.  Huygens  would  like- 
wise suffice  with  work,  mass,  and  vis  viva.  But  since 
he  did  not  in  his  time  completely  possess  the  idea  of 
mass,  that  idea  had  in  subsequent  applications  to  be 
borrowed  from  the  other  sphere.  Yet  this  also  could 
have  been  avoided.     If  with  Newton  the  mass-ratio  of 


254  ^^^  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

two  bodies  can  be  defined  as  the  inverse  ratio  of  the 
velocities  generated  by  the  same  force,  with  Huygens 
it  would  be  logically  and  consistently  definable  as  the 
inverse  ratio  of  the  squares  of  the  velocities  generated 
by  the  same  work. 
The  re8i>ec-  The  two  spheres  of  ideas  consider  the  mutual  de- 
of  each,  pendence  on  each  other  of  entirely  different  factors  of 
the  same  phenomenon.  The  Newtonian  view  is  in  so 
far  more  complete  as  it  gives  us  information  regarding 
the  motion  of  each  mass.  But  to  do  this  it  is  obliged 
to  descend  greatly  into  details.  The  Huygenian  view 
furnishes  a  rule  for  the  whole  system.  It  is  only  a  con- 
venience, but  it  is  then  a  mighty  convenience,  when 
the  relative  velocities  of  the  masses  are  previously  and 
independently  known. 
Theeen-  7.  Thus  wc  are  led  to  see,  that  in  the  develop- 

eral  devel-  ... 

opment  of   ment  of  dynamics,  just  as  in  the  development  of  statics, 

dynamics 

in  the  li^ht  the  Connection  of  widely  diHerent  features  of  mechanical 

of  the  pre-  j  i » «  •  1 

ceding  re-  phenomena  engrossed  at  different  times  the  attention 
of  inquirers.  We  may  regard  the  momentum  of  a  sys- 
teni  as  determined  by  the  forces ;  or,  on  the  other 
hand,  we  may  regard  its  vis  viva  as  determined  by  the 
work.  In  the  selection  of  the  criteria  in  question  the 
individuality  of  the  inquirers  has  great  scope.  It  will 
be  conceived  possible,  from  the  arguments  above  pre- 
sented, that  our  system  of  mechanical  ideas  might, 
perhaps,  have  been  different,  had  Kepler  instituted 
the  first  investigations  concerning  the  motions  of  fall- 
ing bodies,  or  had  Galileo  not  committed  an  error  in 
his  first  speculations.  We  shall  recognise  also  that  not 
only  a  knowledge  of  the  ideas  that  have  been  accepted 
and  cultivated  by  subsequent  teachers  is  necessary  for 
the  historical  understanding  of  a  science,  but  also  that 
the  rejected  and  transient  thoughts  of  the  inquirers. 


THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  D  YNAMICS.  255 

nay  even  apparently  erroneous  notions,  may  be  very 
important  and  very  instructive.  The  historical  investi- 
gation of  the  development  of  a  science  is  most  needful, 
lest  the  principles  treasured  up  in  it  become  a  system 
of  half-understood  prescripts,  or  worse,  a  system  of 
prejudices.  Historical  investigation  not  only  promotes 
the  understanding  of  that  which  now  is,  but  also  brings 
new  possibilities  before  us,  by  showing  that  which  ex- 
ists to  be  in  great  measure  conventional  and  accidental. 
From  the  higher  point  of  view  at  which  different  paths 
of  thought  converge  we  may  look  about  us  with  freer 
powers  of  vision  and  discover  routes  before  unknown. 

In  all  the  dynamical  propositions  that  we  have  dis-  The  sabsti- 

.  -      .  ,  .  iM  mi  tution  of 

cussed,  velocity  plays  a  promment  role.     The  reason  "intecrai** 
of  this,  in  our  view,  is,  that,  accurately  considered,  entiai" 

laws  maT 

every  single  body  of  the  universe  stands  in  some  defi-  some  day 
nite  relation  with  every  other  body  in  the  universe ;  concept  of 
that  any  one  body,  and  consequently  also  any  several  fluous. 
bodies,  cannot  be  regarded  as  wholly  isolated.  Our 
inability  to  take  in  all  things  at  a  glance  alone  compels 
us  to  consider  a  few  bodies  and  for  the  time  being  to 
neglect  in  certain  aspects  the  others ;  a  step  accom- 
plished by  the  introduction  of  velocity,  and  therefore 
of  time.  We  cannot  regard  it  as  impossible  that  inte- 
gral laws,  to  use  an  expression  of  C.  Neumann,  will 
some  day  take  the  place  of  the  laws  of  mathematical 
elements,  or  differential  laws,  that  now  make  up  the 
science  of  mechanics,  and  that  we  shall  have  direct 
knowledge  of  the  dependence  on  one  another  of  the 
positions  of  bodies.  In  such  an  event,  the  concept  of 
force  will  have  become  superfluous. 


CHAPTER  III. 

THE  EXTENDED  APPLICATION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES 
OF  MECHANICS  AND  THE  DEDUCTIVE  DE- 
VELOPMENT OF  THE  SCIENCE. 

S 

I. 

SCOPE    OF   THE    NEWTONIAN    PRINCIPLES. 

Newton's  I.  The  principles  of  Newton  suffice  by  themselves, 

Src"um-**   without  the  introduction  of  any  new  laws,  to  explore 
scope  and   thoroughly  every  mechanical  phenomenon  practically 
^^*^''        occurring,  whether  it  belongs  to  statics  or  to  dynamics. 
If  difficulties  arise  in  any  such  consideration,  they  are 

invariably  of  a  mathematical,  or 
formal,  character,  and  in  no  re- 
spect concerned  with  questions 
of  principle.     We   have  given, 
let  us  suppose,  a  number  of  mas- 
ses/n^,  fn2t  ^3- .  - .  in  space,  with 
definite  initial  velocities  »j,  v^, 
?;,....  We  imagine,  further,  lines 
of  junction  drawn  between  every 
two  masses.    In  the  directions  of 
these  lines  of  junction  are  set  up  the  accelerations  and 
counter-accelerations,  the  dependence  of  which  on  the 
distance  it  is  the  business  of  physics  to  determine.   In 
a  small  element  of  time  r  the  mass  m^,  for  example, 
will  traverse  in  the  direction  of  its  initial  velocity  the 
distance  v^t,  and  in  the  directions  of  the  lines  joining 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.  257 

it  with  the  masses  m^,  m^,  m^.  .  ,  .,  being  afiected  in  Schematic 
such  directions  with  the  accelerations  (p^,  (p^,  ^|.  .  .  .,  of  the  pre- 

ceo  1 TW 

the    distances    (^<p\/2)r^,    (<^|/2)t2,    (<^|/2)r2.  .  .  .       If  statement. 

we  imagine  all  these  motions  to  be  performed  indepen- 
dently of  each  other,  we  shall  obtain  the  new  position 
of  the  mass  m^  after  lapse  of  time  r.  The  composition 
of  the  velocities  v^  and  (p^r,  (p%r,  (p\r.,..  gives  the 
new  initial  velocity  at  the  end  of  time  t.  We  then 
allow  a  second  smalf  interval  of  time  r  to  elapse,  and, 
making  allowance  for  the  new  spatial  relations  of  the 
masses,  continue  in  the  same  way  the  investigation  of 
the  motion.  In  like  manner  we  may  proceed  with 
every  other  mass.  It  will  be  seen,  therefore,  that,  in 
point  of  principle,  no  embarrassment  can  arise ;  the 
difficulties  which  occur  are  solely  of  a  mathematical 
character,  where  an  exact  solution  in  concise  symbols, 
and  not  a  clear  insight  into  the  momentary  workings 
of  the  phenomenon,  is  demanded.  If  the  accelerations 
of  the  mass  wig,  or  of  several  masses,  collectively  neu- 
tralise each  other,  the  mass  m^  or  the  other  masses 
mentioned  are  in  equilibrium  and  will  move  uniformly 
onwards  with  their  initial  velocities.  If,  in  addition, 
the  initial  velocities  in  question  are  =  0,  both  equilib- 
rium and  rest  subsist  for  these  masses. 

Nor,  where  a  number  of  the  masses  m,,  m^  ,  .  ,  ,  The  same 

7  idea  ap- 

have  considerable  extension,  so  that  it  is  impossible  to  pUed  to  aR- 

Rrcgates  of 

speak  of  a  single  line  joining  every  two  masses,  is  the  dif-  material 

,       ,  particles. 

ficulty,  in  point  of  principle,  any  greater.  We  divide 
the  masses  into  portions  sufficiently  small  for  our  pur- 
pose, and  draw  the  lines  of  junction  mentioned  between 
every  two  such  portions.  We,  furthermore,  take  into 
account  the  reciprocal  relation  of  the  parts  of  the 
same  large  mass ;  which  relation,  in  the  case  of  rigid 
masses  for  instance,   consists  in  the  parts  resisting 


358  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

every  alteration  of  their  distances  from  one  another. 
On  the  alteration  of  the  distance  between  any  two  .parts 
of  such  a  mass  an  acceleration  is  observed  proportional 
to  that  alteration.  Increased  distances  diminish,  and 
diminished  distances  increase  in  consequence  of  this 
acceleration.  By  the  displacement  of  the  parts  with 
respect  to  one  another,  the  familiar  forces  of  elasticity 
are  aroused.  When  masses  meet  in  impact,  their 
forces  of  elasticity  do  not  come  into  play  until  contact 
and  an  incipient  alteration  of  form  take  place. 
A  practical  2.  If  we  imagine  a  heavy  perpendicular  column 
of?he  sco%  resting  on  the  earth,  any  particle  m  in  the  interior  of 
principles."  the  columu  which  we  may  choose  to  isolate  in  thought, 
is  in  equilibrium  and  at  rest.  A  vertical  downward  ac- 
celeration g  is  produced  by  the  earth  in  the  particle, 
which  acceleration  the  particle  obeys.  But  in  so  doing 
it  approaches  nearer  to  the  particles  lying  beneath  it, 
and  the  elastic  forces  thus  awakened  generate  in  x»  a 
vertical  acceleration  upwards,  which  ultimately,  when 
the  particle  has  approached  near  enough,  becomes 
equal  to  g.  The  particles  lying  above  m  likewise 
approach  m  with  the  acceleration  g.  Here,  again, 
acceleration  and  counter-acceleration  are  produced, 
whereby  the  particles  situated  above  are  brought  to 
rest,  but  whereby  m  continues  to  be  forced  nearer  and 
nearer  to  the  particles  beneath  it  until  the  acceleration 
downwards,  which  it  receives  from  the  particles  above 
it,  increased  by  g,  is  equal  to  the  acceleration  it  re- 
ceives in  the  upward  direction  from  the  particles  be- 
neath it.  We  may  apply  the  same  reasoning  to  every 
portion  of  the  column  and  the  earth  beneath  it,  readily 
perceiving  that  the  lower  portions  lie  nearer  each  other 
and  are  more  violently  pressed  together  than  the  parts 
above.  Every  portion  lies  between  a  less  closely  pressed 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES,  259 

upper  portion  and  a  more  closely  pressed  lower  por-  Rest  in  the 
tion  ;  its  downward  acceleration  g  is  neutralised  by  a  these  prin- 
surplus  of  acceleration  upwards,  which  it  experiences  pears  as  a 

SDecial  case 

from  the  parts  beneath.  We  comprehend  the  equilib-  ofmotion. 
rium  and  rest  of  the  parts  of  the  column  by  imagining 
all  the  accelerated  motions  which  the  reciprocal  rela- 
tion of  the  earth  and  the  parts  of  the  column  determine, 
as  in  fact  simultaneously  performed.  The  'apparent 
mathematical  sterility  of  this  conception  vanishes,  and 
it  assumes  at  once  an  animate  form,  when  we  reflect 
that  in  reality  no  body  is  completely  at  rest,  but  that 
in  all,  slight  tremors  and  disturbances  are  constantly 
taking. place  which  now  give  to  the  accelerations  of  de- 
scent and  now  to  the  accelerations  of  elasticity  a  slight 
preponderance.  Rest,  therefore,  is  a  case  of  motion, 
very  infrequent,  and,  indeed,  never  completely  realised. 
The  tremors  mentioned  are  by  no  means  an  unfamiliar 
phenomenon.  When,  however,  we  occupy  ourselves 
with  cases  of  equilibrium,  we  are  concerned  simply  with 
a  schematic  reproduction  in  thought  of  the  mechanical 
facts.  We  then  purposely  neglect  these  disturbances, 
displacements,  bendings,  and  tremors,  as  here  they 
have  no  interest  for  us.  All  cases  of  this  class,  which 
have  a  scientific  or  practical  importance,  fall  within  the 
province  of  the  so-called  theory  of  elasticity.  The  whole  The  unity 

,  and  homo- 

outcome  of  Newton's  achievements  is  that  we  every-  geneity 

which  tliAftA 

where  reach  our  goal  with  one  and  the  same  idea,  and  principles 

1  1"  •  1  1  t  1  \        introduce 

by  means  of  it  are  able  to  reproduce  and  construct  be-  into  the 

science 

forehand  all  cases  of  equilibrium  and  motion.  All 
phenomena  of  a  mechanical  kind  now  appear  to  us 
as  uniform  throughout  and  as  made  up  of  the  same 
elements. 

3.  Let  us  consider  another  example.     Two  mas- 
ses M,   m   are  situated   at   a  distance   a   from  each 


26o 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 


A  general 
exemplifi- 
cation of 
the  power 
of  the  prin- 
ciples. 


The  devel- 
opment of 
the  equa- 
tions ob- 
tained in 
this  exam- 
ple. 


S=&— 


Other.  (Fig.  145.)  When  displaced  with  respect  to 
each  other,  elastic  forces  proportional  to  the  change 
x^  of  distance  are  supposed  to  be 

awakened.     Let  the  masses  be 
movable  in  the  A'-direction  par- 
Fig-  145.  allel  to  tf,  and  their  codrdinates 
be  jCj,  ^Cj.     If  a  force /is  applied  at  the  point  x^^  the 
following  Equations  obtain : 


d^x. 


(1) 
(2) 


where  /  stands  for  the  force  that  one  mass  exerts  on 
the  other  when  their  mutual  distance  is  altered  by  the 
value  I.  All  the  quantitative  properties  of  the  me- 
chanical process  are  determined  by  these  equations. 
But  we  obtain  these  properties  in  a  more  comprehensi- 
ble form  by  the  integration  of  the  equations.  The  ordi- 
nary procedure  is,  to  find  by  the  repeated  differentia- 
tion of  the  equations  before  us  new  equations  in  suffi- 
cient number  to  obtain  by  elimination  equations  in  x^ 
alone  or  x^  alone,  which  are  afterwards  integrated.  We 
shall  here  pursue  a  different  method.  By  subtracting 
the  first  equation  from  the  second,  we  get 

d^{x^  —  x,^_ 
dt^ 


m 


—  2/[(^2  — ^1)  — «]+/»  or 


putting  x^  —  x^  =  Uy 

d^U  „       ^  -I       .        y 


(3) 


and  by  the  addition  of  the  first  and  the  second  equa- 
tions 

d^  (x^  +  x^)        . 
m -^- — ^  =/,  or,  puttmg  x^  +  x^=  v, 


di^ 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES,         261 

^77^=^ •••  W 

The  integrals  of  (3)  and  (4)  are  respectively  The  integ- 

rals of  these 


u  =  A  sin-^r~ .  t  -{-  B  cos-vl—  •  ^  +  <3f  +  ^  and 
v=  --  ,  -^  -\-  Ci  -\-  D\  whence 


developH 
ments. 


+  '-'        2        4/+  2' 

*»  =  -2  «"'>|  ^,-  • '  +  2  *=°^\  «r  • '  +  L  •  2- 

+  ^'+2+47+"^- 
To  take  a  particular  case,  we  will  assume  that  the  a  partica- 

-    ,       -  - ,        .  ^  -      ,  ,  .    lar  case  of 

action  01  the  force/ begins  at  /=  0,  and  that  at  this  the  exam- 
ple, 
time 

..  =  0.^  =  0 


x^  =  tf,  —j^  =  0, 


that  is,  the  initial  positions  are  given  and  the  initial 
velocities  are  =  0.  The  constants  Ay  B,  C,  D  being 
eliminated  by  these  conditions,  we  get 

(5)     -x=47'^os^lf-'+2^-Y-47' 
(7)     ^.-*x=-2^cos^^^.'+«  +  2>- 


262  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

Theinfonn-  We  scc  from  (5)  and  (6)  that  the  two  masses,  in  addi- 

ation  which    .  \jj  \    j  » 

the  result-  tion  to  a  Uniformly  accelerated  motion  with  half  the 

ant  eQua- 

tions  give    acceleration  that  the  force  /  would  impart  to  one  of 

concerning 

this  exam-  these  masses  alone,  execute  an  oscillatory  motion  sym- 
metrical with  respect  to  their  centre  of  gravity.  The 
duration  of  this  oscillatory  motion,  7'=  7.nVnil7.p^  is 
smaller  in  proportion  as  the  force  that  is  awakened  in 
the  same  mass-displacement  is  greater  (if  our  attention 
is  directed  to  two  particles  of  the  same  body,  in. pro- 
portion as  the  body  is  harder).  The  amplitude  of  os- 
cillation of  the  oscillatory  motion  fjip  likewise  de- 
creases with  the  magnitude  /  of  the  force  of  displace- 
ment generated.  Equation  (7)  exhibits  the  periodic 
change  of  distance  of  the  two  masses  during  their  pro- 
gressive motion.  The  motion  of  an  elastic  body  might 
in  such  case  be  characterised  as  vermicular.  With  hard 
bodies,  however,  the  number  of  the  oscillations  is  so 
great  and  their  excursions  so  small  that  they  remain 
unnoticed,  and  may  be  left  out  of  account.  The  oscil- 
latory motion,  furthermore,  vanishes,  either  gradually 
through  the  effect  of  some  resistance,  or  when  the  two 
masses,  at  the  moment  the  force /begins  to  act,  are  a 
distance  a  -\-f/2p  apart  and  have  equal  initial  veloci- 
ties. The  distance  a  -\-  ffip  that  the  masses  are  apart 
after  the  vanishing  of  their  vibratory  motion,  is//2/ 
greater  than  the  distance  of  equilibrium  a.  A  tension 
yy  namely,  is  set  up  by  the  action  of/,  by  which  the 
acceleration  of  the  foremost  mass  is  reduced  to  one- 
half  whilst  that  of  the  mass  following  is  increased  by 
the  same  amount.  In  this,  then,  agreeably  to  our  as- 
Thia  in-  sumption,  pyjni  ■=^fl7.  m  ox  y  =//2/.  As  we  see,  it  is 
u  exhaus-    in  our  power  to  determine  the  minutest  details  of  a 

tive* 

phenomenon  of  this  character  by  the  Newtonian  prin- 
ciples.    The  investigation  becomes  (mathematically, 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.         263 

yet  not  in  point  of  principle)  more  complicated  when 
we  conceive  a  body  divided  up  into  a  great  number  of 
small  parts  that  cohere  by  elasticity.  Here  also  in  the 
case  of  sufficient  hardness  the  vibrations  may  be  neg- 
lected. Bodies  in  which  we  pur|X)sely  regard  the  mu- 
tual displacement  of  the  parts  as  evanescent,  are  called 
rigid  bodies. 

4.  We  will  now  consider  a  case  that  exhibits  theihededuc- 

.  .  tion  of  the 

schema  of  a  lever.  We  imagine  the  masses  M^  m^,  ni^  laws  of  the 
arranged  in  a  triangle  and  joined  by  elastic  connec-  Newton's 
tions.  Every  alteration  of  the  sides,  and  consequently 
also  every  alteration  of  the  angles,  gives  rise  to  accel- 
erations, as  the  result  of  which  the  triangle  endeavors  to 
assume  its  previous  form  and  size.  By  the  aid  of  the 
Newtonian  principles  we  can  deduce  from  such  a 
schema  the  laws  of  the  lever,  and  at  the  same  time  feel 
that  the  form  of  the  deduction,  although  it  may  be 
more  complicated,  still 
remains  admissible  when 
we  pass  from  a  schematic 
lever  composed  of  three 
masses  to  the  case  of  a 
real  lever.  The  mass  M 
we  assume  either  to  be  in  itself  very  large  or  conceive 
it  joined  by  powerful  elastic  forces  to  other  very  large 
masses  (the  earth  for  instance).  Af  then  represents 
an  immovable  fulcrum. 

Let  m^,  now,  receive  from  the  action  of  some  ex-Themeth- 
temal  force  an  acceleration /perpendicular  to  the  line  deduction, 
of  junction  Mm^  =  c  -\-  d.  Immediately  a  stretching 
of  the  lines  m^m^  =  ^  and  m^M^a  is  produced,  and 
in  the  directions  in  question  there  are  respectively  set 
up  the  accelerations,  as  yet  undetermined,  s  and  <T,  of 
which  the  components  s(js/b)  and  (J^eja^  are  directed 


Fig.  146. 


264  ^^^^  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

Oppositely  to  the  acceleration/.   Here  e  is  the  altitude 
of  the  triangle  m^m^M,     The  mass  m^  receives  the 
acceleration  s\  which  resolves  itself  into  the  two  com- 
ponents j'(////^)  in  the  direction  of-Afand  s\e/b)'gdLT' 
allel  to  f.    The  former  of  these  determines  a  slight  ap- 
proach of  m^  to  M,     The  accelerations  produced  in  M 
by  the  reactions  ol  m^  and  m^,  owing  to  its  great  mass, 
are  imperceptible.     We  purposely  neglect,  therefore, 
the  motion  of  M, 
The  deduc-       The  mass  m^y  accordingly,  receives  the  accelera- 
taincdby    tion  / — s(e/b)  —  a{e/a),  whilst  the  mass  m^  suffers 
eration  of    the  parallel  acceleration  s\e/b).     Between  s  and  a  a 
tions.         simple  relation  obtains.    If,  by  supposition,  we  have  a 
very  rigid  connection,  the  triangle  is  only  impercept- 
ibly distorted.  The  components  of  s  and  ff perpendicular 
to  /  destroy  each  other.     For  if  this  were  at  any  one 
moment  not  the  case,  the  greater  component  would 
produce  a  further  distortion,  which  would  immediately 
counteract  its  excess.     The  resultant  of  s  and  <T  is 
therefore  directly  contrary  to/,  and  consequently,  as  is 
readily  obvious,   a  {^/d)  =  s  {d/3).     Between  s  and  s\ 
further,  subsists  the  familiar  relation  m^s  ^^m^s'  or 
s  =  s'{m^/m^).     Altogether    m^    and   m^    receive   re- 
spectively   the    accelerations    s\e/lf)   and  / — s\e/^^ 
(jn^/m^){c  -\-  d/e),  or,  introducing  in  the  place  of  the 
variable  value  s\e/d)  the  designation  <p,  the  accelera- 
tions q}  and/ —  ^(^2/^1)  (^  "i"  ^A)- 
On  the  pre-       At  the  Commencement  of  the  distortion,  the  accel- 
positioDs     eration  oi  m^y  owing  to  the  increase  of  (p,  diminishes, 
the  rotation  whilst  that  of  m2  iucreases.    If  we  make  the  altitude  e 
are  easily    of  the  triangle  very  small,  our  reasoning  still  remains 
applicable.   In  this  case,  however,  a  becomes  -—  e  =  r^, 
and  a-^^  =  c-\-d=r2.     We  see,  moreover,  that  the 
distortion  must  continue,  ^  increase,  and  the  accelera- 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES,         265 

tion  of  Wj  diminish  until  the  stage  is  reached  at  which 
the  accelerations  oim^  and  tn^  bear  to  each  other  the 
proportion  of  r^  to  rg.  This  is  equivalent  to  a  rotation 
of  the  whole  triangle  (without  further  distortion)  about 
M^  which  mass  by  reason  of  the  vanishing  accelera- 
tions is  at  rest.  As  soon  as  rotation  sets  in,  the  rea- 
son for  further  alterations  of  <p  ceases.  In  such  a  case, 
consequently, 


9  = 


'*2 


^2  '*2l  ^^   ^  ^  ^l^\f 


/— .  (p    -2  -2^  or  (p  = 


r^  - 


;;/^  r^  J     '   ^  ^  m^  ''1^  +  ^^\  *"  ^ 


2  '  2 
For  the  angular  acceleration  ^  of  the  lever  we  get 

^2        '^1^1^  +  ^2^2^ 
Nothing  prevents  us  from  entering  still  more  into  Discussion 
the  details  of  this  case  and  determining  the  distortions  acter  of  the 

"  preceding 

and  vibrations  of  the  parts  with  respect  to  each  other,  result. 
With  sufficiently  rigid  connections,  however,  these  de- 
tails may  be  neglected.  It  will  be  perceived  that  we . 
have  arrived,  by  the  employment  of  the  Newtonian  prin- 
ciples, at  the  same  result  to  which  the  Huygenian  view 
also  would  have  led  us.  This  will  not  appear  strange  to 
us  if  we  bear  in  mind  that  the  two  views  are  in  every  re- 
spect equivalent y  and  merely  start  from  different  aspects 
of  the  same  subject-matter.  If  we  had  pursued  the 
Huygenian  method,  we  should  have  arrived  more 
speedily  at  our  goal  but  with  less  insight  into  the  de- 
tails of  the  phenomenon.  We  should  have  employed 
the  work  done  in  some  displacement  of  /w^  to  deter- 
mine the  vires  viva  oi  tn^  and  m^^  wherein  we  should 
have  assumed  that  the  velocities  in  question  v^^  v^ 
maintained  the  ratio  v^lv^^=r^lr^.  The  example 
here  treated  is  very  well  adapted  to  illustrate  what 
such  an  equation  of  condition  means.     The  equation 


266 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 


A  simple 
case  of  the 
same  exam 
pie. 


The  equi- 
librium of 
the  lever 
deduced 
from  the 
same  con- 
siderationa. 


simply  asserts,  that  on  the  slightest  deviations  of  v^jv^ 
from  r^jr^  powerful  forces  are  set  in  action  which  in 
point  of  fact  prevent  all  further  deviation.  The  bodies 
obey  of  course,  not  the  equations^  but  \\\<&  forces. 

5.  We  obtain  a  very  obvious  case  if  we  put  in  the 
example  just  treated  m^^=^m^=^m  and  a  =  ^(Fig. 
147).  The  dynamical  state  of  the  system  ceases  to 
change  when  ^  =  2  (/ —  2  ^),  that  is,  when  the  accel- 
erations of  the  masses 
at  the  base  and  the  ver- 
ak^'^  /i^^^^^i/  tex  are  given  by  2//5 
wT      .  and  //5.     At  the  com- 

^'^'  '"'•  mencement  of  the  dis- 

tortion <p  increases,  and  simultaneously  the  accelera- 
tion of  the  mass  at  the  vertex  is  decreased  by  double 
that  amount,  until  the  proportion  subsists  between  the 
two  of  2  : 1. 

We  have  yet  to  consider  the  case  of  equilibrium  of 
a  schematic  lever,  consisting  (Fig.  148)  of  three  masses 
m^,  m^,  and  M,  of  which  the  last  is  again  supposed 


Fig.  148. 

to  be  very  large  or  to  be  elastically  connected  with 
very  large  masses.  We  imagine  two  equal  and  oppo- 
site forces  s,  —  s  applied  to  m^  and  m^  in  the  direction 
m^m^,  or,  what  is  the, same  thing,  accelerations  im- 
pressed inversely  proportional  to  the  masses  m^^,  m^. 
The  stretching  of  the  connection  m^m^  also  generates 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.         267 

accelerations  inversely  proportional  to  the  masses  m^^ 
tn^y  which  neutralise  the  first  ones  and  produce  equi- 
librium. Similarly,  along  m^M imagine  the  equal  and 
contrary  forces  /,  —  /  operative  ;  and  along  m^M the 
forces  Uy  —  u.  In  this  case  also  equilibrium  obtains. 
If  M  be  elastically  connected  with  masses  sufficiently 
large,  —  u  and  —  /  need  not  be  applied,  inasmuch 
as  the  last-named  forces  are  spontaneously  evoked  the 
moment  the  distortion  begins,  and  always  balance  the 
forces  opposed  to  them.  Equilibrium  subsists,  accord- 
ingly, for  the  two  equal  and  opposite  forces  x,  —  x  as 
well  as  for  the  wholly  arbitrary  forces  /,  u,  Aaa  matter 
of  fact  X,  —  s  destroy  each  other  and  /,  u  pass  through 
the  fixed  mass  My  that  is,  are  destroyed  on  distortion 
setting  in. 

The  condition  of  equilibrium  readily  reduces  itself  The  reduo- 
to  the  common  form  when  we  reflect  that  the  mo- preceding 
ments  of  /  and  »,  forces  passmg  through  My  are  with  common 
respect  to  M  zero,  while  the  moments  of  s  and  —  s  are 
equal  and  opposite.  If  we  compound  /  and  s  to  /,  and 
u  and  —  X  to  ^,  then,  by  Varignon's  geometrical  principle 
of  the  parallelogram,  the  moment  of  /  is  equal  to  the 
sum  of  the  moments  of  s  and  /,  and  the  moment  of  q 
is  equal  to  the  sum  of  the  moments  of  u  and  —  x.  The 
moments  of/  and  q  are  therefore  equal  and  opposite. 
Consequently,  any  two  forces  /  and  q  will  be  in  equi- 
librium if  they  produce  in  the  direction  m^m^  equal 
and  opposite  components,  by  which  condition  the  equal- 
ity of  the  moments  with  respect  to  M  is  posited.  That 
then  the  resultant  of  /  and  q  also  passes  through  My  is 
likewise  obvious,  for  x  and  —  x  destroy  each  other  and 
/  and  u  pass  through  M, 

6.  The  Newtonian  point  of  view,  as  the  example 
just  developed  shows  us,  includes  that  of  Varignon. 


268  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

Newton's    We  Were  right,  therefore,  when  we  characterised  the 

point  of  .  . 

view  in-      statics  of  Varignon  as  a  dynamical  statics,  which,  start- 
varignon's.  ing  from  the  fundamental  ideas  of  modern  dynamics, 
voluntarily  restricts  itself  to  the  investigation  of  cases 
of  equilibrium.   Only  in  the  statics  of  Varignon,  owing 
to  its  abstract  form,  the  significance  of  many  opera- 
tions, as  for  example  that  of  the  translation  of  the 
forces  in  their  own  directions,  is  not  so  distinctly  ex- 
hibited as  in  the  instance  just  treated. 
The  econ-         The  Considerations  here  developed  will  convince 
wealth  of    US  that  we  can  dispose  by  the  Newtonian  principles 

the  N  evirtOQ- 

ian  ideas,  of  every  phenomenon  of  a  mechanical  kind  which  may 
arise,  provided  we  only  take  the  pains  to  enter  far 
enough  into  details.  We  literally  see  through  the  cases 
of  equilibrium  and  motion  which  here  occur,  and  be- 
hold the  masses  actually  impressed  with  the  accelera- 
tions they  determine  in  one  another.  It  is  the  same 
grand  fact,  which  we  recognise  in  the  most  various 
phenomena,  or  at  least  can  recognise  there  if  we  make 
a  point  of  so  doing.  Thus  a  unity,  homogeneity,  and 
economy  of  thought  were  produced,  and  a  new  and 
wide  domain  of  physical  conception  opened  which 
before  Newton's  time  was  unattainable. 
The  New-  Mechauics,  however,  is  not  altogether  an  end  in  it- 

the modem,  self  ;  it  has  ^Xs^o. problems  to  solve  that  touch  the  needs 
methods,  of  practical  life  and  affect  the  furtherance  of  other  sci- 
ences. Those  problems  are  now  for  the  most  part  ad- 
vantageously solved  by  other  methods  than  the  New- 
tonian,— methods  whose  equivalence  to  that  has  already 
been  demonstrated.  It  would,  therefore,  be  mere  im- 
practical pedantry  to  contemn  all  other  advantages  and 
insist  upon  always  going  back  to  the  elementary  New- 
tonian ideas.  It  is  sufficient  to  have  once  convinced 
ourselves  that  this  is  always  possible.     Yet  the  New- 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.  269 

tonian  conceptions  are  certainly  the  most  satisfactory 
and  the  most  lucid  ;  and  Poinsot  shows  a  noble  sense 
of  scientific  clearness  and  simplicity  in  making  these 
conceptions  the  sole  foundation  of  the  science. 

II. 

THE  FORMULiE  AND  UNITS  OF  MECHANICS. 

1.  All  the  important  formulae  of  modern  mechanics  History  of 

•     %      e  r^    \'%        "**  fonnu- 

were  discovered  and  employed  in  the  period  of  Galileo  las  and 

.  .  .  .  units  of 

and  Newton.  The  particular  designations,  which,  mechanics, 
owing  to  the  frequency  of  their  use,  it  was  found  con- 
venient to  give  them,  were  for  the  most  part  not  fixed 
upon  until  long  afterwards.  The  systematical  mechan- 
ical units  were  not  introduced  until  later  still.  Indeed, 
the  last  named  improvement,  cannot  be  regarded  as 
having  yet  reached  its  completion. 

2.  Let  5  denote  the  distance,  /  the  time,  v  the  in-  The  orig- 
stantaneous  velocity,  and  €p  the  acceleration  of  a  uni-  tfons??* 
formly  accelerated  motion.     From  the  researches  ofHuygens. 
Galileo  and  Huygens,  we  derive  the  following  equa- 
tions : 


V  =  <pt 

mi 


(1) 


Multiplying  throughout  by  the  mass  m,  these  equa-  The  intro- 

,1        r    11        •  duction 

tions  give  the  following  :  of  "mass 

and  "mov- 
m%)  =  m(pt  ^  force." 

mm  . 


mcps  -=1 


mv^ 


2   ' 


270 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS 


Final  form  and,  denoting  the  moving  force  mq>\iy  the  letter  /,  we 

of  the  fun- 
dament&I      Obtain 


equations. 


ms 


mv  •=  pt 

•  2 

2," 


ps  = 


(2) 


Equations  (i)  all  contain  the  quantity  (p ;  and  each 
contains  in  addition  two  of  the  quantities  s^  /,  Vy  as 
exhibited  in  the  following  table : 


9  \ 


Equations  (2)  contain  the  quantities  m^  /,  Sy  /,  v  ; 
each  containing  m^  p  and  in  addition  to  m^  p  two  of  the 
three  quantities  x,  /,  v^  according  to  the  following  table  : 


m,p 


.  S,  V 


The  scope 
and  appli- 


Questions  concerning  motions  due  to  constant  forces 
catiotTof'  are  answered  by  equations  (2)  in  great  variety.  If,  for 
tions.  ***""  example,  we  want  to  know  the  velocity  v  that  a  mass 
m  acquires  in  the  time  /  through  the  action  of  a  force 
/,  the  first  equation  gives  v  z=pt/m.  If,  on  the  other 
hand,  the  time  be  sought  during  which  a  mass  m  with 
the  velocity  v  can  move  in  opposition  to  a  force  /,  the 
same  equation  gives  us  /  =  /« v/p.  Again,  if  we  in- 
quire after  the  distance  through  which  m  will  move  with 
velocity  v  in  opposition  to  the  force  /,  the  third  equa- 
tion gives  s  =  tnv^  jip.  The  two  last  questions  illus- 
trate, also,  the  futility  of  the  Descartes- Leibnitzian  dis- 
pute concerning  the  measure  of  force  of  a  body  in  mo- 
tion.    The  use  of  these  equations  greatly  contributes 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.         271 

to  confidence  in  dealing  with  mechanical-  ideas.  Sup- 
pose, for  instance,  we  put  to  ourselves,  the  question, 
what  force  p  will  impart  to  a  given  mass  m  the  velocity 
V  \  we  readily  see  that  between  »i,  /,  and  v  alone,  no 
equation  exists,  so  that  either  x  or  /  must  be  supplied, 
and  consequently  the  question  is  an  indeterminate  one. 
We  soon  learn  to  recognise  and  avoid  indeterminate 
cases  of  this  kind.  The  distance  that  a  mass  m  acted 
on  by  the  force  /  describes  in  the  time  /,  if  moving 
with  the  initial  velocity  0,  is  found  by  the  second  equa- 
tion s=ipt^/2m. 

3.  Several  of  the  formulae  in  the  above-discussed  The  names 
equations  have  received  particular  names.  The  force  formula  of 
of  a  moving  body  was  spoken  of  by  Galileo,  who  al-  tionsHave 
ternately calls  it  ''momentum,"  "impulse,"  and  "en- 
ergy. "  He  regards  this  momentum  as  proportional  to 
the  product  of  the  mass  (or  rather  the  weight,  for  Gali- 
leo had  no  clear  idea  of  mass^  and  for  that  matter  no 
more  had  Descartes,  nor  even  Leibnitz)  into  the  velo- 
city of  the  body.  Descartes  accepted  this  view.  He  put 
the  force  of  a  moving  body  =  w  z/,  called  it  quantity  of 
motion,  and  maintained  that  the  sum-total  of  the  quan- 
tity of  motion  in  the  universe  remained  constant,  so  that 
when  one  body  lost  momentum  the  loss  was  compen- 
sated for  by  an  increase  of  momentum  in  other  bodies. 
Newton  also  employed  the  designation  "quantity  of 
motion  "  for  m  v,  and  this  name  has  been  retained  to  the  Momen- 

,  _T-»  .       t  ,  -,  tum  and 

present  day.    [But  momentum  is  the  more  usual  term.  J  impulse. 
For  the  second  member  of  the  first  equation,  viz.  /  /, 
Belanger,  proposed,  as  late  as  1847,  the  name  impulse* 
The  expressions  of  the  second  equation  have  received 

*  See,  also,  Maxwell,  Matter  and  Motion^  American  edition,  page  7a.  But 
this  word  is  commonly  used  in  a  different  sense,  namely,  as  "the  limit  of  a 
force  which  is  infinitely  great  but  acts  only  during  an  infinitely  short  time." 
See  Routh,  Rigid  Dynamic*^  Part  I,  pages  65-66.— TVaiw. 


272  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

visvrva  no  particular  designations.  Leibnitz  (1695)  called  the 
expression  mv'^  of  the  third  equation  vis  viva  or  living 
force,  and  he  regarded  it,  in  opposition  to  Descartes, 
as  the  true  measure  of  the  force  of  a  body  in  motion, 
calling  the  pressure  of  a  body  at  rest  vis  mortua,  or 
dead  force.  Coriolis  found  it  more  appropriate  to  give 
the  term  \mv^  the  name  vis  viva.  To  avoid  confusion, 
Belanger  proposed  to  call  mv^  Urging  force  and  \mi^^ 
living  power  [now  commonly  called  in  English  kinetic 
energy].  For  ps  Coriolis  employed  the  name  work. 
Poncelet  confirmed  this  usage,  and  adopted  the  kilo- 
gramme-metre (that  is,  a  force  equal  to  the  weight  of  a 
kilogramme  acting  through  the  distance  of  a  metre)  as 
the  unit  of  work. 

The  history        a    Concerning  the  historical  details  of  the  origin  of 

of  the  ideas  ~  °  .  .      ° 

quantity  of  thcse  notious  "quantity  of  motion*'  and  "vis  viva," 

motion  and 

vis  viva,  a  glance  may  now  be  cast  at  the  ideas  which  led  Des- 
cartes and  Leibnitz  to  their  opinions.  In  his  Principia 
Fhilosophice,  published  in  1644,  II,  36,  Descartes  ex- 
pressed himself  as  follows : 

"Now  that  the  nature  of  motion  has  been  examined, 
"we  must  consider  its  cause,  which  may  be  conceived 
"in  two  senses :  first,  as  a  universal,  original  cause — 
"  the  general  cause  of  all  the  motion  in  the  world  ;  and 
"second,  as  a  special  cause,  from  which  the  individual 
"  parts  of  matter  receive  motion  which  before  they  did 
"not  have.  As  to  the  universal  cause,  it  can  mani- 
"festly  be  none  other  than  God,  who  in  the  beginning 
"  created  matt-er  with  its  motion  and  rest,  and  who  now 
"  preserves,  by  his  simple  ordinary  concurrence,  on  the 
"whole,  the  same  amount  of  motion  and  rest  as  he 
"originally  created.  For  though  motion  is  only  a  con- 
"dition  of  moving  matter,  there  yet  exists  in  matter 
"a  definite  quantity  of  it,  which  in  the  world  at  large. 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES,  273  I 

^<  never  increases  or  diminishes,  although  in  single  por-  Passage 

''tions  it  changes;  namely,  in  this  way,  that  we  must cartes's .  \ 

'*  assume,  in  the  case  of  the  motion  of  a  piece  of  matter 

'*  which  is  moving  twice  as  fast  as  another  piece,  but  in 

*'  quantity  is  only  one  half  of  it,  that  there  is  the  same 

**  amount  of  motion  in  both,  and  that  in  the  proportion 

**  as  the  motion  of  one  part  grows  less,  in  the  same  pro- 

**  portion  must  the  motion  of  another,  equally  large 

'*part  grow  greater.     We  recognise  it,  moreover,  as 

**a  perfection  of  God,  that  He  is  not  only  in  Himself 

'^  unchangeable,  but  that  also  his  modes  of  operation 

"  are  most  rigorous  and  constant ;  so  that,  with  the  ex- 

"ception  of  the  changes  which  indubitable  experience 

'*or  divine  revelation  offer,  and  which  happen,  as  our 

**  faith  or  judgment  show,  without  any  change  in  the 

"Creator,  we  are  not  permitted  to  assume  any  others 

"in  his  works — lest  inconstancy  be  in  anyway  pre- 

"dicated  of  Him.     Therefore,  it  is  wholly  rational  to 

"assume  that  God,  since  in  the  creation  of  matter  he 

"  imparted  different  motions  to  its  parts,  and  preserves 

"all  matter  in  the  same  way  and  conditions  in  which 

"he  created  it,  so  he  ^wcvXKxXy preserves  in  it  the  same 

* '  quantity  of  motion.  *' 

The  merit  of  having  first  sought  after  a  more  uni-  The  merits 

.  and  defects 

versal  and  more  fruitful  point  of  view  in  mechanics,  o'  t)escar- 

'      .      ,  tes's  phys- 

cannot  be  denied  Descartes.    This  is  the  peculiar  task  »cai  inquir- 
ies. 

of  the  philosopher,  and  it  is  an  activity  which  con- 
stantly exerts  a  fruitful  and  stimulating  influence  on 
physical  science. 

Descartes,  however,  was  infected  with  all  the  usual 
errors  of  the  philosopher.  He  places  absolute  confi- 
dence in  his  own  ideas.  He  never  troubles  himself  to 
put  them  to  experiential  test.  On  the  contrary,  a  min- 
imum of  experience  always  suffices  him  for  a  maximum 


274  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

of  inference.     Added  to  this,  is  the  indistinctness  of 
«  his  conceptions.     Descartes  did  not  possess  a  clear 

idea  of  mass.  It  is  hardly  allowable  to  say  that  Des- 
cartes defined  m  v  as  momentum,  although  Descartes's 
scientific  successors,  feeling  the  need  of  more  definite 
notions,  adopted  this  conception.  Descartes's  greatest 
error,  however, — and  the  one  that  vitiates  all  his  phys- 
ical inquiries, — is  this,  that  many  propositions  appear 
to  him  self-evident  a  priori  concerning  the  truth  of 
which  experience  alone  can  decide.  Thus,  in  the  two 
paragraphs  following  that  cited  above  (§§37-39)  it  is 
asserted  as  a  self-evident  proposition  that  a  body  pre- 
serves unchanged  its  velocity  and  direction.  The  ex- 
periences cited  in  §38  should  have  been  employed,  not 
as  a  confirmation  of  an  h  priori  law  of  inertia,  but  as  a 
foundation  on  which  this  law  in  an  empirical  sense 
should  be  based. 
Leibnitz  Dcscartes's  view  was  attacked  by  Leibnitz  (1686) 

on  quantity  "^  ^  ^ 

of  motion,  in  the  Acta  Eruditorumy  in  a  little  treatise  bearing  the 
title  :  "A  short  Demonstration  of  a  Remarkable  Error 
of  Descartes  and  Others,  Concerning  the  Natural  Law 
by  which  they  think  that  the  Creator  always  preserves 
the  same  Quantity  of  Motion ;  by  which,  however,  the 
Science  of  Mechanics  is  totally  perverted. " 

In  machines  in  equilibrium,  Leibnitz  remarks,  the 
loads  are  inversely  proportional  to  the  velocities  of  dis- 
placement ;  and  in  this  way  the  idea  arose  that  the 
product  of  a  body  ("  corpus,"  "  moles  ")  into  its  velocity 
is  the  measure  of  force.  This  product  Descartes  re- 
garded as  a  constant  quantity.  Leibnitz's  opinion, 
however,  is,  that  this  measure  of  force  is  only  acci- 
dentally the  correct  measure,  in  the  case  of  the  ma- 
chines. The  true  measure  of  force  is  different,  and 
must  be  determined  by  the  method  which  Galileo  and 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.  275 

Huygens  pursued.  Every  body  rises  by  virtue  of  the  Leibnitz  on 
velocity  acquired  in  its  descent  to  a  height  exactly  ure  of  force, 
equal  to  that  from  which  it  fell.  If,  therefore,  we  as- 
sume, that  the  same  "force"  is  requisite  to  raise  a 
body  m  a  height  4^  as  to  raise  a  body  ^m  a  height  //, 
we  must,  since  we  know  that  in  the  first  case  the  ve- 
locity acquired  in  descent  is  but  twice  as  great  as  in 
the  second,  regard  the  product  of  a  "body"  into  the 
square  of  its  velocity  as  the  measure  of  force. 

In  a  subsequent  treatise  (1695),  Leibnitz  reverts  to 
this  subject.  He  here  makes  a  distinction  between 
simple  pressure  {vis  mortua)  and  the  force  of  a  moving 
body  {vis  viva),  which  latter  is  made  up  of  the  sum  of 
the  pressure- impulses.  These  impulses  produce,  in- 
deed, an  "impetus"  {mv),  but  the  impetus  produced 
is  not  the  true  measure  of  force ;  this,  since  the  cause 
must  be  equivalent  to  the  effect,  is  (in  conformity  with 
the  preceding  considerations)  determined  by  mv^, 
Leibnitz  remarks  further  that  the  possibility  of  per- 
petual motion  is  excluded  only  by  the  acceptance  of  his 
measure  of  force. 

Leibnitz,  no  more  than  Descartes,  possessed  a  gen-  The  idea  of 

mass  in 

uine  concept  of  mass.     Where  the  necessity  of  such  Leibnitz's 

view 

an  idea  occurs,  he  speaks  of  a  body  {corpus)^  of  a  load 
{moles),  of  different-sized  bodies  of  the  same  specific 
gravity,  and  so  forth.  Only  in  the  second  treatise,  and 
there  only  once,  does  the  expression  "massa"  occur, 
in  all  probability  borrowed  from  Newton.  Still,  to  de- 
rive any  definite  results  from  Leibnitz's  theory,  we  must 
associate  with  his  expressions  the  notion  of  mass,  as 
his  successors  actually  did.  As  to  the  rest,  Leibnitz's 
procedure  is  much  more  in  accordance  with  the  meth- 
ods of  science  than  Descartes's.  Two  things,  however, 
are  confounded  :  the  question  of  the  measure  of  force 


276  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

In  a  sense,  and  the  question  of  the  constancy  of  the  sums  2mv  and 
andLeib-    2mv^,     The  two  have  in  reality  nothing  to  do  with 
each  right,  each  Other.    With  regard  to  the  first  question,  we  now 
know  that  both  the  Cartesian  and  the  Leibnitzian  meas- 
ure of  force,  or,  rather,  the  measure  of  the  effective- 
ness of  a  body  in  motion,  have,  each  in  a  different 
sense,  their  justification.     Neither  measure,  however, 
as  Leibnitz  himself  correctly  remarked,  is  to  be  con- 
founded with   the  common,   Newtonian,   measure  of 
force. 
The  dis-  With  regard  to  the  second  question,  the  later  in- 

8ui?of  mf^  vestigations  of  Newton  really  proved  that  iox  free  ma- 
sundings.   terial  systems  not  acted  on  by  external  forces  the  Car- 
tesian sum  2mz;  is  a  constant ;  and  the  investigations 
of  Huygens  showed  that  also  the  sum  2mv^  is  a  con- 
stant, provided  work  performed  by  forces  does  not  alter 
it.     The  dispute  raised  by  Leibnitz  rested,  therefore, 
on   various    misunderstandings.     It   lasted    fifty-seven 
years,   till  the  appearance  of  D'Alembert's   Traite  de 
dynamiquCy  in  1743.     To  the  theological  ideas  of  Des- 
cartes and  Leibnitz,  we  shall  revert  in  another  place. 
Theappii-         5-  The  three  equations  above  discussed,  though 
the  funda-  they  are  only  applicable  to  rectilinear  motions  produced 
equations    by  Constant  forces,  may  yet  be  considered  the  funda- 
forces?  *  mental  equations  of  mechanics.     If  the  motion  be  recti- 
linear  but  the  force  variable,  these  equations  pass  by  a 
slight,   almost   self-evident,  modification  into  others, 
which  we  shall  here  only  briefly  indicate,  since  mathe- 
matical developments  in  the  present  treatise  are  wholly 
subsidiary. 

From  the  first  equation  we  get  for  variable  forces 

mv  =  Ipdt  '\-  C,  where /  is  the  variable  force,  dt  the 

time-element  of  the  action,    { pdt  the  sum  of  all  the 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES,         277 


• 


products  / .  dt  from  the  beginning  to  the  end  of  the 
action,  and  C  a  constant  quantity  denoting  the  value 
of  m  V  before  the  force  begins  to  act. 

The  second  equation  passes  in  like  manner  into  the 

form  s  =i\dt\^-dt  +  C^  +  I>,  with  two  so-called 

constants  of  integration. 

The  third  equation  must  be  replaced  by 


-;-=Sf'"+c. 


Curvilinear  motion  may  always  be  conceived  as  the 
product  of  the  simultaneous  combination  of  three  rec- 
tilinear motions,  best  taken  in  three  mutually  perpen- 
dicular directions.  Also  for  the  components  of  the  mo- 
tion of  this  very  general  case,  the  above-given  equa- 
tions retain  their  significance. 

6.  The  mathematical  processes  of  addition,  sub- The  units  of 
traction,  and  equating  possess  intelligible  meaning  only 
when  applied  to  quantities  of  the  same  kind.  We  can- 
not add  or  equate  masses  and  times,  or  masses  and 
velocities,  but  only  masses  and  masses,  and  so  on. 
When,  therefore,  we  have  a  mechanical  equation,  the 
question  immediately  presents  itself  whether  the  mem- 
bers of  the  equation  are  quantities  of  f/ie  same  kind, 
that  is,  whether  they  can  be  measured  by  the  same  unit, 
or  whether,  as  we  usually  say,  the  equation  is  homo- 
geneous. The  units  of  the  quantities  of  mechanics  will 
form,  therefore,  the  next  subject  of  our  investigations. 

The  choice  of  units,  which  are,  as  we  know,  quan- 
tities of  the  same  kind  as  those  they  serve  to  measure, 
is  in  many  cases  arbitrary.  Thus,  an  arbitrary  mass  is 
employed  as  the  unit  of  length,  an  arbitrary  time  as  the 
unit  of  time.  The  mass  and  the  length  employed  as 
units  can  be  preserved ;  the  time  can  be  reproduced 


force. 


278  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

■ 

Arbitrary    by  pendulum-experiments  and  astronomical  observa- 

units,  and       .  _..  •••i  •/•!•  •        r 

derived  or  tions.  But  units  like  a  unit  of  velocity,  or  a  unit  of 
units.  acceleration,  cannot  be  preserved,  and  are  much  more 
difficult  to  reproduce.  These  quantities  are  conse- 
quently so  connected  with  the  arbitrary  fundamental 
units,  mass,  length,  and  time,  that  they  can  be  easily 
and  at  once  derived  from  them.  Units  of  this  class 
are  called  derived  or  absolute  units.  This  latter  desig- 
nation is  due  to  Gauss,  who  first  derived  the  magnetic 
units  from  the  mechanical,  and  thus  created  the  possi- 
bility of  a  universal  comparison  of  magnetic  measure- 
ments.  The  name,  therefore,  is  of  historical  origin. 
The  de-  As  unit  of  velocity  we  might  choose  the  velocity 

of  velocity,  with  which,  Say,  q  units  of  length  are  travelled  over  in 
tion.  and  unit  of  time.  But  if  we  did  this,  we  could  not  express 
the  relation  between  the  time  /,  the  distance  i*,  and  the 
velocity  v  by  the  usual  simple  formula  s=:zvt,  but 
should  have  to  substitute  for  \t  s  =  q,iJt,  If,  however, 
we  define  the  unit  of  velocity  as  the  velocity  with 
which  the  unit  of  length  is  travelled  over  in  unit  of 
time,  we  may  retain  the  form  s=:vL  Among  the  de- 
rived units  the  simplest  possible  relations  are  made 
to  obtain.  Thus,  as  the  unit  of  area  and  the  unit  of  vol- 
ume, the  square  and  cube  of  the  unit  of  length  are  al- 
ways employed. 

According  to  this,  we  assume  then,  that  by  unit  ve- 
locity unit  length  is  described  in  unit  time,  that  by  unit 
acceleration  unit  velocity  is  gained  in  unit  time,  that 
by  unit  force  unit  acceleration  is  imparted  to  unit  mass, 
and  so  on. 

The  derived  units  depend  on  the  arbitrary  funda- 
mental units  ;  they  are  functions  of  them.  The  func- 
tion which  corresponds  to  a  given  derived  unit  is  called 
its  dimensions.  The  theory  of  dimensions  was  laid  down 


• 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.  279 

by  Fourier,  in  1822,  in  his  Theory  of  Heat,    Thus,  if  /The  theory 
denote  a  length,  /  a  time,  and  m  a  mass,  the  dimen-  sions. 
sions  of  a  velocity,  for  instance,  are  ///  or  //~i.    After 
this  explanation,  the  following  table  will  be  readily  un- 
derstood : 

NAMS8  SYMBOLS  bIMBMSIOMS 

Velocity v  lt~^ 

Acceleration <p  lt~^ 

Force /  mlt-^ 

Momentum mv  mit~^ 

Impulse //  mli"^ 

Work ps  tnl^t-'^ 

TT*      •  mii^  ,« .   « 

Vis  viva -^—         w/*/-a 

li 

Moment  of  inertia 0         ml^ 

Statical  moment D        ml^t-^ 

This  table  shows  at  once  that  the  above-discussed  equa- 
tions are  homogeneous,  that  is,  contain  only  members  of 
the  same  kind.  Every  new  expression  in  mechanics 
might  be  investigated  in  the  same  manner. 

7.  The  knowledge  of  the  dimensions  of  a  quantity  The  usefui- 
is  also  important  for  another  reason.     Namely,  if  the  theoir  of  ^ 
value  of  a  quantity  is  known  for  one  set  of  fundamental  s/oSIf 
units  and  we  wish  to  pass  to  another  set,  the  value  of 
the  quantity  in  the  new  units  can  be  easily  found  from 
the  dimensions.     The  dimensions  of  an  acceleration, 
which  has,  say,  the  numerical  value  9?,  are  //~2.     if 
we  pass  to  a  unit  of  length  X  times  greater  and  to  a 
unit  of  time  t  times  greater,  then  a  number  X  times 
smaller  must  take  the  place  of  /  in  the  expression  //"*, 
and  a  number  t  times  smaller  the  place  of  /.     The 
numerical  value  of  the  same  acceleration  referred  to 
the  new  units  will  consequently  be  (t*  A)  <p.     If  we 


28o 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 


The  Inter- 
national 
Bureau  of 
Weights 
and  Meas- 
ures. 


The  inter- 
national 
unit  of 
length. 


take  the  metre  as  our  unit  of  length,  and  the  second  as 
our  unit  of  time,  the  acceleration  of  a  falling  body  for 
example  is  9-81,  or  as  it  is  customary  to  write  it,  in- 
dicating at  once  the  dimensions  and  the  fundamental 
measures:  9-81  (metre/second 2).  If  we  pass  now  to 
the  kilometre  as  our  unit  of  length  (A,  =  1000),  and  to 
the  minute  as  our  unit  of  time  (t  =  60),  the  value  of  the 
same  acceleration  of  descent  is  (60  X  60/1000)9-81, 
or  35-316  (kilometre/minute 2). 

[8.  The  following  statement  of  the  mechanical  units 
at  present  in  use  in  the  United  States  and  Great  Britain 
is  substituted  for  the  statement  by  Professor  Mach  of 
the  units  formerly  in  use  on  the  continent  of  Europe. 
All  the  civilised  governments  have  united  in  establish- 
ing an  International  Bureau  of  Weights  and  Measures 
in  the  Pavilion  de  Breteuil,  in  the  Pare  of  St.  Cloud, 
at  Sevres,  near  Paris.  In  some  countries,  the  stan- 
dards emanating  from  this  office  are  exclusively  legal ; 
in  others,  as  the  United  States  and  Great  Britain,  they 
are  optional  in  contracts,  and  are  usual  with  physi- 
cists. These  standards  are  a  standard  of  length  and  a 
standard  of  mass  (not  weight.^ 

The  unit  of  length  is  the  International  Metre,  which 
is  defined  as  the  distance  at  the  melting  point  of  ice 
between  the  centres  of  two  lines  engraved  upon  the 
polished  surface  of  a  platiniridium  bar,  of  a  nearly 
X-shaped  section,  called  the  International  Prototype 
Metre.  Copies  of  this,  called  National  Prototype  Me- 
tres, are  distributed  to  the  different  governments.  The 
international  metre  is  authoritatively  declared  to  be 
identical  with  the  former  French  metre,  used  until  the 
adoption  of  the  international  standard  ;  and  it  is  im- 
possible to  ascertain  any  error  in  this  statement,  be- 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES,  281 

cause  of  doubt  as  to  the  length  of  the  old  metre, 
owing  partly  to  the  imperfections  of  the  standard,  and 
partly  to  obstacles  now  intentionally  put  in  the  way  of 
such  ascertainment.  The  French  .  metre  was  defined 
as  the  distance,  at  the  melting-point  of  ice,  between 
the  ends  of  a  platinum  bar,  called  the  metre  des  archives. 
It  was  against  the  law  to  touch  the  ends,  which  made 
it  difficult  to  ascertain  the  distance  between  them. 
Nevertheless,  there  was  a  strong  suspicion  they  had 
been  dented.  The  metre  des  archives  was  intended  to 
be  one  ten-millionth  of  a  quadrant  of  a  terrestrial 
meridian.  In  point  of  fact  such  a  quadrant  is,  ac- 
cording to  Clarke,  32814820  feet,  which  is  100020 15 
metres. 

The  international  unit  of  mass  is  the  kilogramme.  The  inter- 
national 
which  is  the  mass  of  a  certain  cylinder  of  platiniridium  unit  of 

mass. 

called  the  International  Prototype  Kilogramme.  Each 
government  has  copies  of  it  called  National  Prototype 
Kilogrammes.  This  mass  was  intended  to  be  identical 
with  the  former  French  kilogramme,  which  was  defined 
as  the  mass  of  a  certain  platinum  cylinder  called  the 
kilogramme  des  archives.  The  platinum  being  somewhat 
spongy  contained  a  variable  amount  of  occluded  gases, 
ajid  had  perhaps  suffered  some  abrasion.  The  kilo- 
gramme is  1000  grammes ;  and  a  gramme  was  intended 
to  be  the  mass  of  a  cubic  centimetre  of  water  at  its 
temperature  of  maximum  density,  about  3  •  93°  C.  It 
is  not  known  with  a  high  degree  of  precision  how  nearly 
this  is  so,  owing  to  the  difficulty  of  the  determination. 

The  regular  British  unit  of  length  is  the  Imperial  The  British 
Yard  which  is  the  distance  at  62°  F.  between  the  cen-  iSJgth. 
tres  of  two  lines  engraved  on  gold  plugs  inserted  in  a 
bronze  bar  usually  kept  walled  up  in  the  Houses  of 
Parliament  in  Westminster.     These  lines  are  cut  rela- 


282  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

Conditions  tivelv  deep,  and  the  burr  is  rubbed  off  and  the  surface 

of  compari- 
son of  the    rendered  mat,  by  rubbing  with  charcoal.     The  centre 

Imperial  • 

Yard  with    of  such  a  line  can  easily  be  displaced  by  rubbing  :  which 

other  meas-  .  ,     ,  ,  r     «       « •  i       -r-^ 

urea.  is  probably  not  true  of  the  lines  on  the  Prototype  me- 

tres.    The  temperature  is,   by  law,  ascertained  by  a 
mercurial  thermometer  ;  but  it  was  not  known,  at  the 
time  of  the  construction  of  the  standard,  that  such 
thermometers  may  give  quite  different  readings,  ac- 
cording to  the  mode  of  their  manufacture.  The  quality 
of  glass  makes  considerable  difference,  and  the  mode 
of  determining  the  fixed  points  makes  still  more.    The 
best  way  of  marking  these  points  is  first  to  expose  the 
thermometer  for  several  hours  to  wet  aqueous  vapor  at 
a  known  pressure,  and  mark  on  its  stem  the  height  of 
the  column  of  mercury.     The   thermometer  is  then 
brought  down  to  the  temperature  of  melting  ice,  as 
rapidly  as  possible,  and  is  immersed  in  pounded  ice 
which  is  melting  and  from  which  the  water  is  not 
allowed  to  drain  off.      The  mercury  being  watched 
with  a  magnifying  glass  is  seen  to  fall,  to  come  to 
rest,  and  to  commence  to  rise,  owing  to  the  lagging 
contraction  of  the  glass.     Its  lowest  point  is  marked 
on  the  stem.     The  interval  between  the  two  marks  is 
then  divided  into  equal  degrees.     When  such  a  ther- 
mometer is  used,  it  is  kept  at  the  temperature  to  be 
determined  for  as  long  a  time  as  possible,  and  imme- 
diately after  is  cooled  as  rapidly  as  it  is  safe  to  cool  it, 
and  its  zero  is  redetermined.   Thermometers,  so  made 
and  treated,  will  give  very  constant  indications.     But 
the  thermometers  made  at  the  Kew  observatory,  which 
are  used  for  determining  the  temperature  of  the  yard, 
are  otherwise  constructed.     Namely  the  melting-point 
is  determined  first  and  the  boiling-point  afterwards  \ 
and  the  thermometers  are  exposed  to  both  tempera- 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.         283 

tures  for  many  hours.     The  point  which  upon  such  a  Relative 
thermometer  will  appear  as  62°  will  really  be  consider-  the  metre 
ably  hotter  (perhaps  a  third  of  a  centigrade  degree) "  ^""^  ' 
than  if  its  melting-point  were  marked  in  the  other  way. 
If  this  circumstance  is  hot  attended  to  in  making  com- 
parisons, there  is  danger  of  getting  the  yard  too  short 
by  perhaps  one  two-hundred-thousandth  part.  General 
Comstock  finds  the  metre  equal  to  39*36985  inches. 
Several  less  trustworthy  determinations  give  nearly  the 
same  value.  This  makes  the  inch  2  *  540014  centimetres. 

At  the  time  the  United  States  separated  from  Eng-  The  Amen- 

*  can  anit  of 

land,  no  precise  standard  of  length  was  legal*;  and  length, 
none  has  ever  been  established.  We  are,  therefore, 
without  any  precise  legal  yard ;  but  the  United  States 
office  of  weights  and  measures,  in  the  absence  of  any 
legal  authorisation,  refers  standards  to  the  British  Im- 
perial Yard. 

The  regular  British  unit  of  mass  is  the  Pound,  de-  The  British 
fined  as  the  mass  of  a  certain  platinum  weight,  called  ^m? 
the  Imperial  Pound.     This  was  intended  to  be  so  con-  _ 
structed  as  to  be  equal  to  7000  grains,  each  the  ^6oth 
part  of  a  former  Imperial  Troy  pound.    This  would  be 
within  3  grains,  perhaps  closer,  of  the  old  avoirdupois 
pound.     The  British  pound  has  been  determined  by 
Miller  to  be  0-4535926525  kilogramme  ;  that  is  the  kilo- 
gramme is  2-204621249  pounds. 

At  the  time  the  United  States  separated  from  Great 
Britain,  there  were  two  incommensurable  units  of 
weight,  the  avoirdupois  pound  and  the  Troy  pound.  Con- 
gress has  since  established  a  standard  Troy  pound, 
which  is  kept  in  the  Mint  in  Philadelphia.  It  was  a 
copy  of  the  old  Imperial  Troy  pound  which  had  been 
adopted  in  England  after  American  independence.    It 

*  The  ao-called  standard  of  1758  had  not  been  legalised. 


284  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

TheAmeri-  IS  a  hollow  brass  Weight  of  unknown  volume  :  and  no 

can  unit  of  .  , 

mass.  accurate  comparisons  of  it  with  modem  standards  have 
ever  been  published.  Its  mass  is,  therefore,  unknown. 
The  mint  ought  by  law  to  use  this  as  the  standard  of 
gold  and  silver.  In  fact,  they  use  weights  furnished 
by  the  office  of  weights  and  measures,  and  no  doubt 
derived  from  the  British  unit ;  though  the  mint  officers 
profess  to  compare  these  with  the  Troy  pound  of  the 
United  States,  as  well  as  they  are  able  to  do.  The  old 
avoirdupois  pound,  which  is  legal  for  most  purposes, 
differed  without  much  doubt  quite  appreciably  from 
the  British  Imperial  pound  ;  but  as  the  Office  of  Weights 
and  Measures  has  long  been,  without  warrant  of  law, 
standardising  pounds  according  to  this  latter,  the  legal 
avoirdupois  pound  has  nearly  disappeared  from  use  of 
late  years.  The  makers  of  weights  could  easily  detect 
the  change  of  practice  of  the  Washington  Office. 

Measures  of  capacity  are  not  spoken  of  here,  be- 
cause they  are  not  used  in  mechanics.  It  may,  how- 
ever, be  well  to  mention  that  they  are  defined  by  the 
weight  of  water  at  a  given  temperature  which  they 
measure. 
The  unit  of  The  Universal  unit  of  time  is  the  mean  solar  day  or 
its  one  86400th  part,  which  is  called  a  second.  Side- 
real time  is  only  employed  by  astronomers  for  special 
purposes. 

Whether  the  International  or  the  British  units  are 
employed,  there  are  two  methods  of  measurement  of 
mechanical  quantities,  the  absolute  and  \}[i^  gravitational. 
The  absolute  is  so  called  because  it  is  not  relative  to 
the  acceleration  of  gravity  at  any  station.  This  method 
was  introduced  by  Gauss. 

The  special  absolute  system,  widely  used  by  physi- 
cists in  the  United  States  and  Great  Britain,  is  called 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES,         285 

the  Centimetre-Gramine-Second  system.     In  this  sys- The  abso- 
lute system 

tern,  writing  C  for  centimetre,  G  for  gramme  mass,  of  the 

United 

and  S  for  second,  states  and 

Great  Brit- 

the  unit  of  length  is C 

the  unit  of  mass  is G 

the  unit  of  time  is S 

the  unit  of  velocity  is C/S  * 

the  unit  of  acceleration  (which  might 
be  called  a  "galileo,"  because  Gali- 
leo Galilei  first  measured  an  accele- 
ration) is C/S  2 

the  unit  of  density  is G/C  ' 

the  unit  of  momentum  is G  C/S 

the  unit  of  force  (called  a  dyne)  is    ...  G  C/S  ^ 
the  unit  of  pressure  (called  one  mil- 
lionth of  an  absolute  atmosphere)  is .   .     G/C  S^ ; 
the  unit  of  energy  (tns  viva,  or  work, 

called  an  erg)  is JGC*/S*; 

etc. 

The  gravitational  system  of  measurement  of  me-  The  cravi- 
chanical  quantities,  takes  the  kilogramme  or  pound,  or  system, 
rather  the  attraction  of  these  towards  the  earth,  com- 
pounded with  the  centrifugal  force, — which  is  the  ac- 
celeration called  gravity,  and  denoted  by  g,  and  is  dif- 
ferent at  different  places, — as  the  unit  of  force,  and 
the  foot-pound  or  kilogramme-metre,  being  the  amount 
of  gravitational  energy  transformed  in  the  descent  of  a 
pound  through  a  foot  or  of  a  kilogramme  through  a 
metre,  as  the  unit  of  energy.  Two  ways  of  reconciling 
these  convenient  units  with  the  adherence  to  the  usual 
standard  of  length  naturally  suggest  themselves,  namely, 
first,  to  use  the  pound  weight  or  the  kilogramme  weight 
divided  by  g  as  the  unit  of  mass,  and,  second,  to  adopt 


286  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

such  a  unit  of  time  as  will  make  the  acceleration  of  g, 
at  an  initial  station,  unity.  Thus,  at  Washington,  the 
acceleration  of  gravity  is  980  •  05  galileos.  If,  then, 
we  take  the  centimetre  as  the  unit  of  length,  and  the 
0*03 1 943  second  as  the  unit  of  time,  the  acceleration 
of  gravity  will  be  i  centimetre  for  such  unit  of  time 
squared.  The  latter  system  would  be  for  most  pur- 
poses the  more  convenient ;  but  the  former  is  the  more 
familiar. 
Coropari-  In  either  system,  the  formula  p=zmg  is  retained: 

son  of  the  ,  J  f  /-  6  i 

absolute,    but  in  the  former  g  retains  its  absolute  value,  while  in 

and  gravi-  . 

tationai      the  latter  it  becomes  unity  for  the  initial  station.     In 

systems. 

Paris,  g  is  980 '96  galileos ;  in  Washington  it  is  980*05 
galileos.  Adopting  the  more  familiar  system,  and 
taking  Paris  for  the  initial  station,  if  the  unit  of  force 
is  a  kilogramme's  weight,  the  unit  of  length  a  centi- 
metre, and  the  unit  of  time  a  second,  then  the  unit  of 
mass^will  be  1/981-0  kilogramme,  and  the  unit  of 
energy  will  be  a  kilogramme-centimetre,  or  (1/2)- 
(1000 798 1  0)0  0  2/5  a.  Then,  at  Washington  the 
gravity  of  a  kilogramme  will  be,  not  i,  as  at  Paris, 
but  980-1/981  •0  =  0-99907  units  or  Paris  kilogramme- 
weights.  Consequently,  to  produce  a  force  of  one  Paris 
kilogramme- weight  we  must  allow  Washington  gravity 
to  act  upon  981  -0/980 •!  =  i  -00092  kilogrammes.] 

In  mechanics,  as  in  some  other  branches  of  physics 
closely  allied  to  it,  our  calculations  involve  but  three 
fundamental  quantities,  quantities  of  space,  quantities 
of  time,  and  quantities  of  mass.  This  circumstance  is 
a  sourpe  of  simplification  and  power  in  the  science 
which  should  not  be  underestimated. 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.         287 


III. 

THE  LAWS  OF  THE  CONSERVATION  OF  MOMENTUM,  OF  THE 

CONSERVATION  OF  THE  CENTRE  OF  GRAVITY,  AND 

OF  THE  CONSERVATION  OF  AREAS. 

1 .  Although  Newton's  principles  are  fully  adequate  Spedaiisa- 
to  deal  with  any  mechanical  problem  that  may  arise,  mechanical 
it  is  yet  convenient  to  contrive  for  cases  more  frequently 
occurring,  particular  rules,  which  will  enable  us  to  treat 
problems  of  this  kind  by  routine  forms  and  to  dis- 
pense with  the  minute  discussion  of  them.     Newton 

and  his  successors  developed  several  such  principles. 
Our  first  subject  will  be  Newton's  doctrines  concern- 
ing freely  movable  material  systems. 

2.  If  two  free  masses  tn  and  m*  are  subjected  in  Mutual  ac- 
Ihe  direction  of  their  line  of  junction  to  the  action  of  masses. 
forces  that  proceed  from  other  masses,  then,  in  the  in- 
terval of  time  /,  the  velocities  v^  v*  will  be  generated, 

and  the  equation  (^p  -^  f^  t  =  m  v  -{-  m'v*  will  subsist. 
This  follows  from  the  equations// =  wz^  2ind  p'f  = 
m'v'.  The  sum  mv  '\-  m'v'  is  called  the  momentum  of 
the  system,  and  in  its  computation  oppositely  directed 
forces  and  velocities  are  regarded  as  having  opposite 
signs.  If,  now,  the  masses  m,  m*  in  addition  to  being 
subjected  to  the  action  of  the  external  forces  /,  /'  are 
also  acted  upon  by  internal  forces,  that  is  by  such  as 
are  mutually  exerted  by  the  masses  on  one  another,  these 
forces  will,  by  Newton's  third  law,  be  equal  and  op- 
posite, q,  —  q.     The  sum  of  the  impressed  impulses 

is,  then,  (/+/'  +  ^  —  ^)^  =  (/ +/')^'  ^^®  same  as 
before  ;  and,  consequently,  also,  the  total  momentum 
of  the  system  will  be  the  same.     The  momentum  of  a 


288  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

system  is  thus  determined  exclusively  by  ex/erna/ iorceSf 
that  isy  by  forces  which  masses  outside  of  the  system 
exert  on  its  parts. 
Law  of  the         Imagine  a  number  of  free  masses  »i,  m\  m*\  .  .  . 

Cons6rvt&- 

Uon  or  Mo-  distributed  in  any  manner  in  space  and  acted  on  by 


mentum. 


external  forces  /,  /',  /".  .  .  .  whose  lines  have  any  di- 
rections. These  forces  produce  in  the  masses  in  the 
interval  of  time  /  the  velocities  v^  v\  v*\  .  .  .  Resolve 
all  the  forces  in  three  directions  jc,  y^  z  at  right  angles 
to  each  other,  and  do  the  same  with  the  velocities. 
The  sum  of  the  impulses  in  the  a:-direction  will  be  equal 
to  the  momentum  generated  in  the  jc-direction ;  and 
so  with  the  rest.  If  we  imagine  additionally  in  action 
between  the  masses  m^  m*,  m".  .  .  .,  pairs  of  equal  and 
opposite  internal  forces  q,  —  ^>  '',  —  '',  s,  —  j,  etc. , 
these  forces,  resolved,  will  also  give  in  every  direction 
pairs  of  equal  and  opposite  components,  and  will  con- 
sequently have  on  the  sum-total  of  the  impulses  no  in- 
fluence. Once  more  the  momentum  is  exclusively  de- 
termined by  external  forces.  The  law  which  states 
this  fact  is  called  the  law  of  the  conservation  of  momen- 
tum. 
Law  of  the         3.  Another  form  of  the  same  principle,  which  New- 

Conserva- 
tion of  the  ton  likewise  discovered,  is  called  the  law  of  the  comer- 

Centre  of  •>•»>- 

Gravity.  vatton  of  the  centre  of  grav- 

'  ^    Ji — ^  ^ p      ity.     Imagine  in  A  and  B 

(Fig.  149)  two  masses,  2w 
^^^'  '*^*  and  m,  in  mutual  action, 

say  that  of  electrical  repulsion  ;  their  centre  of  gra;^ity 
is  situated  at  5,  where  BS=  2 AS.  The  accelerations 
they  impart  to  each  other  are  oppositely  directed  and 
in  the  inverse  proportion  of  the  masses.  If,  then,  in 
consequence  of  the  mutual  action,  2  m  describes  a  dis- 
tance AD,  m  will  necessarily  describe  a  distance  BC  = 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.  289 

ilAD,  The  point  S  will  still  remain  the  position  of  the 
centre  of  gravity,  as  CS  =  2DS.  Therefore,  two  masses 
cannot,  by  mutual  action,  displace  their  common  centre 
of  gravity. 

If  our  considerations  involve  several  masses,  dis-  This  law 

applied  to 

tributed  in  any  way  in  space,  the  same  result  will  also  systems  of 

masses. 

be  found  to  hold  good  for  this  case.  For  as  no  two  of 
the  masses  can  displace  their  centre  of  gravity  by  mu- 
tual action,  the  centre  of  gravity  of  the  system  as  a 
whole  cannot  be  displaced  by  the  mutual  action  of  its 
parts. 

Imagine  freely  placed  in  space  a  system  of  masses 
Pij  m\  m'\  .  .  .  acted  on  by  external  forces  of  any  kind. 
We  refer  the  forces  to  a  system  of  rectangular  co6rdi- 
nates  and  call  the  coordinates  respectively  x,  y^  z,  x\ 
y,  2',  and  so  forth.  The  coordinates  of  the  centre  of 
gravity  are  then 

^ 2mx      2  my 2mz  ^ 

2,m  ^m  ^  m 

in  which  expressions  jc,  y^  z  may  change  either  by  uni- 
form motion  or  by  uniform  acceleration  or  by  any  other 
law,  according  as  the  mass  in  question  is  acted  on  by 
no  external  force,  by  a  constant  external  forpe,  or  by  a 
variable  external  force.  The  centre  of  gravity  will  have 
in  all  these  cases  a  different  motion,  and  in  the  first 
may  even  be  at  rest.  If  now  internal  forces,  acting  be- 
tween every  two  masses,  ///  and  m*\  come  into  play  in 
the  system,  opposite  displacements  a/',  w"  will  thereby 
be  produced  in  the  direction  of  the  lines  of  junction 
of  the  masses,  such  that,  allowing  for  signs,  m*^/  -(- 
»i"w"  =  0.  Also  with  respect  to  the  components  x^ 
and  x^  of  these  displacements  the  equation  m*x^  + 
m**x^  =  0  will  hold.    The  internal  forces  consequently 


ago  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

produce  in  the  expressions  ^,  r}y  ^  only  such  additions 
as  mutually  destroy  each  other.     Consequently,  the 
motion  of  the  centre  of  gravity  of  a  system  is  determined 
by  external  forces  only. 
Acceiera-  If  we  wish  to  know  the  acceleration  of  the  centre  of 

lion  of  the 

centre  of     gravity  of  the  system,  the  accelerations  of  the  system's 

gravity  of  a  i--ii  ^         tr  §         **  j 

system.  parts  must  be  similarly  treated.  If  ^,  9? ,  9?  .  .  .  .  de- 
note the  accelerations  of  m^  m\  m*\  ...  in  any  direc- 
tion, and  <p  the  acceleration  of  the  centre  of  gravity  in 
the  same  direction,  <p  =  2m(p/^m,  or  putting  the 
total  mass  2m  =  Jf,  q}  =  2m  (p/M.  Accordingly,  we 
obtain  the  acceleration  of  the  centre  of  gravity  of  a 
system  in  any  direction  by  taking  the  sum  of  all  the 
forces  in  that  direction  and  dividing  the  result  by  the 
total  mass.  The  centre  of  gravity  of  a  system  moves 
exactly  as  if  all  the  masses  and  all  the  forces  of  the 
system  were  concentrated  at  that  centre.  Just  as  a 
single  mass  can  acquire  no  acceleration  without  the 
action  of  some  external  force,  so  the  centre  of  gravity 
6f  a  system  can  acquire  no  acceleration  without  the 
action  of  external  forces. 

4.  A  few  examples  may  now  be  given  in  illustra- 
tion of  the  principle  of  the  conservation  of  the  centre 
of  gravity. 
Movement         Imagine  an  animal  free  in  space.     If  the  animal 
maUree*in  move  in  One  direction  a  portion  m  of  its  mass,  the  re- 
space,        mainder  of  it  J/ will  be  moved  in  the  opposite  direction, 
always  so  that  its  centre  of  gravity  retains  its  original 
position.     If  the  animal  draw  back  the  mass  m,  the 
motion  of  M  also  will  be  reversed.     The  animal  is  un- 
able, without  external  supports  or  forces,  to  move  itself 
from  the  spot  which  it  occupies,  or  to  alter  motions  im- 
pressed upon  it  from  without. 
'"A  lightly  running  vehicle  A  is  placed  on  rails  and 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.         291 

loaded  with  stones.     A  man  stationed  in  the  vehicle  of  a  ve- 

,  .        1  -I .    hicle,  from 

casts  out  the  stones  one  after  another,  m  the  same  di-  which 

stones  are 

rection.  The  vehicle,  supposing  the  friction  to  be  suf-  cast, 
ficiently  slight,  will  at  once  be  set  In  motion  in  the  op- 
posite direction.  The  centre  of  gravity  of  the  system 
as  a  whble  (of  the  vehicle  -|-  ^'^  stones)  will,  so  far  as 
its  motion  is  not  destroyed  by  external  obstacles,  con- 
tinue to  remain  in  its  original  spot.  If  the  same  man 
were  to  pick  up  the  stones  from  without  and  place 
them  in  the  vehicle,  the  vehicle  in  this  case  would  also 
be  set  in  motion ;  but  not  to  the  same  extent- as  before, 
as  the  following  example  will  render  evident. 

A  projectile  of  mass  ni  is  thrown  with  a  velocity  v  Motion  of  a 

"^      '  ,  •'       cannon  and 

from  a  cannon  of  mass  M,    In  the  reaction,  M  also  re-  it?  projec- 

tile. 

ceives  a  velocity,  F,  such  that,  making  allowance  for 
the  signs,  MV  -\'  mv  =  0.  This  explains  the  so-called 
recoil.  The  relation  here  is  V=  —  (m/M)v;  or,  for 
equal  velocities  of  flight,  the  recoil  is  less  according  as 
the  mass  of  the  cannon  is  greater  than  the  mass  of  the 
projectile.  If  the  work  done  by  the  powder  be  expressed 
by  A,  the  vt'res  viva  will  be  determined  by  the  equation 
MV^/2  -{-  mv* /2  =  A  ;  and,  the  sum  of  the  momenta 
being  by  the  first-cited  equation  =  0,  we  readily  obtain 
y=\/2Am/M(^M-{-  m).  Consequently,  neglecting 
the  mass  of  the  exploded  powder,  the  recoil  vanishes 
when  the  mass  of  the  projectile  vanishes.  If  the  mass 
m  were  not  expelled  from  the  cannon  but  sucked  into 
it,  the  recoil  would  take  place  in  the  opposite  direc- 
tion. But  it  would  have  no  time  to  make  itself  visible 
since  before  any  perceptible  distance  had  been  trav- 
ersed, m  would  have  reached  the  bottom  of  the  bore. 
As  soon,  however,  as  Af  and  m  are  in  rigid  connection 
with  each  other,  as  soon,  that  is,  a^  they  are  relatively 
at  rest  to  each  other,  they  must  be  absolutely  at  rest. 


292  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

for  the  centre  of  gravity  of  the  system  as  a  whole  has 
no  motion.  For  the  same  reason  no  considerable  mo- 
tion can  take  place  when  the  stones  in  the  preceding 
example  are  taken  into  the  vehicle,  because  on  the 
establishment  of  rigid  connections  between  the  vehicle 
and  the  stones  the  opposite  momenta  generated  are 
destroyed.  A  cannon  sucking  in  a  projectile  would 
experience  a  perceptible  recoil  only  if  the  sucked  in 
projectile  could  fly  through  it. 
osciiia-  Imagine  a  locomotive  freely  suspended  in  the  air, 

tionsof  the  i  .n         i  i  •  i 

body  of  a    or,  what  Will  subserve  the  same  purpose,  at  rest  with 

locomotive.  .  ^^.  r--  i  •»  -r^ii  r       \ 

insufficient  friction  on  the  rails.  By  the  law  of  the 
conservation  of  the  centre  of  gravity,  as  soon  as  the 
heavy  masses  of  iron  in  connection  with  the  piston- 
rods  begin  to  oscillate,  the  body  of  the  locomotive  will 
be  set  in  oscillation  in  a  contrary  direction — a  motion 
which  may  greatly  disturb  its  uniform  progress.  To 
eliminate  this  oscillation,  the  motion  of  the  masses  of 
iron  worked  by  the  piston-rods  must  be  so  compensated 
for  by  the  contrary  motion  of  other  masses  that  the 
centre  of  gravity  of  the  system  as  a  whole  will  remain 
in  one  position.  In  this  way  no  motion  of  the  body  of 
the  locomotive  will  take  place.  This  is  done  by  affix- 
ing masses  of  iron  to  the  driving-wheels. 
Illustration  The  facts  of  this  case  may  be  very  prettily  shown 
case.  by  Page's  electromotor  (Fig.    150).     When  the  iron 

core  in  the  bobbin -^^  is  projected  by  the  internal  forces 
acting  between  bobbin  and  core  to  the  right,  the  body 
of  the  motor,  supposing  it  to  rest  on  lightly  movable 
wheels  rr^  will  move  to  the  left.  But  if  to  a  spoke  of 
the  fly-wheel  R  we  affix  an  appropriate  balance-weight 
a,  which  always  moves  in  the  contrary  direction  to  the 
iron  core,  the  sideward  movement  of  the  body  of  the 
motor  may  be  made  totally  to  vanish. 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.  293 

Of  the  motion  of  the  fragments  of  a  bursting  bomb  a  bm 
we  know  nothing.  But  it  is  plain,  by  the  law  of  the 
conservation  of  the  centre  of  gravity,  that,  making  al- 
lowance for  the  resistance  of  the  air  and  the  obstacles 
the  individual  parts  may  meet,  the  centre  of  gravity  of 
the  system  will  continue  after  the  bursting  to  describe 
the  parabolic  path  of  its  original  projection. 

5.  A  law  closely  allied  to  the  law  of  the  centre  of  l«wi 
gravity,  and  similarly  applicable  io/ree  systems,  is  theHont 
principle  of  the  amservation  of  areas.    Although  Newton 


had,  so  to  say,  this  principle  within  his  very  grasp,  it 
was  nevertheless  not  enunciated  until  a  long  time  after- 
wards by  EuLER,  D'Arcy,  and  Daniel  Bernoulli. 
Euler  and  Daniel  Bernoulli  discovered  the  law  almost 
simultaneously  (1746),  on  the  occasion  of  treating  a 
problem  proposed  by  Euler  concerning  the  motion  of 
balls  in  rotatable  tubes,  being  led  to  it  by  the  consider- 
ation of  the  action  and  reaction  of  the  balls  and  the 
tubes.  D'Arcy  (1747)  started  from  Newton's  investiga- 
tions, and  generalised  the  law  of  sectors  which  the 
latter  had  employed  to  explain  Kepler's  laws. 


294 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 


Deduction 
of  the  law. 


Two  masses  m,  ni  (Fig.  151)  are  in  mutual  action. 
By  virtue  of  this  action  the  masses  describe  the  dis- 
tances ABy  CD  in  the  direction  of  their  line  of  junction. 
Allowing  for  the  signs,  then,  m .  AB  +  m*,  CD  =  0. 
Drawing  radii  vectores  to  the  moving  masses  from  any 

point  Oy  and  regarding 
the   areas    described    in 
opposite   senses  by  the 
T  radii  as  having  opposite 

signs,  we  further  obtain 
^^  m.OAB  +  m\OCD  =  Q. 
Which  is  to  say,  if  two 
masses  mutually  act  on 
each  other,  and  radii  vec- 
tores  be  drawn  to  these 
masses  from  any  point, 
the  sum  of  the  areas 
described  by  the  radii 
multiplied  by  the  respec- 
If  the  masses  are  also  acted  on 
by  external  forces  and  as  the  effect  of  these  the  areas 
OAE  and  OCF  are  described,  the  joint  action  of  the 
internal  and  external  forces,  during  any  very  small 
period  of  time,  will  produce  the  areas  OAG^xnA  OCH, 
But  it  follows  from  Varignon's  theorem  that 

mOAG  +  m'OCH=  m  OAE  +  m  OCF  + 
mOAB  +  niOCD  =  mOAE  +  m'OCF; 

in  other  words,  the  sum  of  the  products  of  the  areas  so  de- 
scribed into  the  respective  masses  which  compose  a  system 
is  unaltered  by  the  action  of  internal  forces. 

If  we  have  several  masses,  the  same  thing  may  be 
asserted,  for  every  two  masses,  of  the  projection  on  any 
given  plane  of  the  motion.     If  we  draw  radii  from 


tive  masses  is  =  0. 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.  295 

any  point  to  the  several  masses,  and  project  on  any 
plane  the  areas  the  radii  describe,  the  sum  of  the 
products  of  these  areas  into  the  respective  masses  will 
be  independent  of  the  action  of  internal  forces.  This 
is  the  law  of  the  conservation  of  areas. 

If  a  single  mass  not  acted  on  by  forces  is  moving  interpretn- 

,  ,  tion  of  the 

uniformly  forward  in  a  straight  line  and  we  draw  a  law. 
radius  vector  to  the  mass  from  any  point  (9,  the  area 
described  by  the  radius  increases  proportionally  to  the 
time.  The  same  law  holds  for  ^mf  in  cases  in  which 
several  masses  not  acted  on  by  forces  are  moving, 
where  we  signify  by  the  summation  the  algebraic  sum 
of  all  the  products  of  the  areas  (/)  into  the  moving 
masses — a  sum  which  we  shall  hereafter  briefly  refer 
to  as  the  sum  of  the  mass-areas.  If  internal  forces 
come  into  play  between  the  masses  of  the  system,  this 
relation  will  remain  unaltered.  It  will  still  subsist, 
also,  if  external  forces  be  applied  whose  lines  of  action 
pass  through  ih&  fixed  point  Oy  as  we  know  from  the 
researches  of  Newton. 

If  the  mass  be  acted  on  by  an  external  force,  the 
area  /  described  by  its  radius  vector  will  increase  in 
time  by  the  law/=  at^  ji  -{-  bt  -\-  c^  where  a  depends 
on  the  accelerative  force,  b  on  the  initial  velocity,  and 
c  on  the  initial  position.  The  sum  ^mf  increases  by 
the  same  law,  where  several  masses  are  acted  upon  by 
external  accelerative  forces,  provided  these  may  be  Re- 
garded as  constant,  which  for  sufficiently  small  inter- 
vals of  time  is  always  the  case.  The  law  of  areas  in 
this  case  states  that  the  internal  forces  of  the  system 
have  no  influence  on  the  increase  of  the  sum  of  the  mass- 
areas. 

A  free  rigid  body  may  be  regarded  as  a  system 
whose  parts  are  maintained  in  their  relative  positions 


296  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

Uniform  ro-  bv  internal  forces.  The  law  of  areas  is  applicable  there - 

tation  of  a  , 

free  rigid    fore  to  this  case  also.     A  simple  instance  is  afforded 

body.  .  ^ 

by  the  uniform  rotation  of  a  rigid  body  about  an  axis 
passing  through  its  centre  of  gravity.  If  we  call  m  a 
portion  of  its  mass,  r  the  distance  of  the  portion  from 
the  axis,  and  a  its  angular  velocity,  the  sum  of  the 
mass-areas  produced  in  unit  of  time  will  be  ^m 
{r/2)ra  =  (^a/2)2mr^,  or,  the  product  of  the  moment 
of  inertia  of  the  system  into  half  its  angular  velocity. 
This  product  can  be  altered  only  by  external  forces. 
Illustrative        6.  A  few  examples  may  now  be  cited  in  illustration 

examples,     ^f  ^^e  kw. 

If  two  rigid  bodies  ^  and  K'  are  connected,  and  IC 
is  brought  by  the  action  of  internal  forces  into  rotation 
relatively  to  IC\  immediately  A"  also  will  be  set  in  ro- 
tation, in  the  opposite  direction.  The  rotation  of  AT 
generates  a  sum  of  mass-areas  which,  by  the  law,  must 
be  compensated  for  by  the  production  of  an  equals  but 
opposite,  sum  by  K\ 
Opposite  This  is  very  prettily  exhibited  by  the  electromotor 

the  wheel  of  Fig.  1 5  2.  The  fly-wheel  of  the  motor  is  placed  in 
a^free^eiec'-  a  horizontal  plane,  and  the  motor  thus  attached  to  a 
vertical  axis,  on  which  it  can  freely  turn.  The  wires 
conducting  the  current  dip,  in  order  to  prevent  their 
interference  with  the  rotation,  into  two  conaxial  gutters 
of  mercury  fixed  on  the  axis.  The  body  of  the  motor 
{X')  is  tied  by  a  thread  to  the  stand  supporting  the 
axis  and  the  current  is  turned  on.  As  soon  as  the  fly- 
wheel (-^),  viewed  from  above,  begins  to  rotate  in  the 
direction  of  the  hands  of  a  watch,  the  string  is  drawn 
taut  and  the  body  of  the  motor  exhibits  the  tendency 
to  rotate  in  the  opposite  direction — a  rotation  which  im- 
mediately takes  place  when  the  thread  is  burnt  away. 
The  motor  is,  with  respect  to  rotation  about  its 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.        ^97 

axis,  a  free  system.     The  sum  of  the  mass-areas  gen-  i.i>e 
erated,  for  the  case  of  rest,  is  ^  0.      But  the  -wheel  of  law. 
the  motor  being  set  in  rotation  by  the  action  of  the  in- 
ternal electro -magnetic  forces,  a  sum  of  mass-areas  is 


produced  which,  as  the  total  sum  must  remain  ^  0,  is 
compensated  for  by  the  rotation  in  the  opposite  direc- 
tion of  the  body  of  the  motor,  ff  an  index  be  attached 
to  the  body  of  the  motor  and  kept  in  a  fixed  position 


non. 


2^  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

by  an  elastic  spring,  the  rotation  of  the  body  of  the 
motor  cannot  take  place.  Yet  every  acceleration  of 
the  wheel  in  the  direction  of  the  hands  of  a  watch  (pro- 
duced by  a  deeper  immersion  of  the  battery)  causes 
the  index  to  swerve  in  the  opposite  direction,  and  every 
retardation  produces  the  contrary  effect, 
A  variation  A  beautiful  but  curious  phenomenon  presents  itself 
pheno^!**  when  the  current  to  the  motor  is  interrupted.  Wheel 
and  motor  continue  at  first  their  movements  in  oppo- 
site directions.  But  the  effect  of  the  friction  of  the 
axes  soon  becomes  apparent  and  the  parts  gradually 
assume  with  respect  to  each  other  relative  rest.  The 
motion  of  the  body  of  the  motor  is  seen  to  diminish  ; 
for  a  moment  it  ceases ;  and,  finally,  when  the  state  of 
relative  rest  is  reached,  it  is  reversed  and  assumes  the 
direction  of  the  original  motion  of  the  wheel.  The 
whole  motor  now  rotates  in  the  direction  the  wheel  did 
at  the  start.  The  explanation  of  the  phenomenon  is 
obvious.  The  motor  is  not  a  perfectly  free  system.  It 
is  impeded  by  the  friction  of  the  axes.  In  a  perfectly 
.  free  system  the  sum  of  the  mass-areas,  the  moment 
the  parts  re-entered  the  state  of  relative  rest,  would 
again  necessarily  be  =  0.  But  in  the  present  instance, 
an  external  force  is  introduced — the  friction  of  the 
axes.  The  friction  on  the  axis  of  the  wheel  diminishes 
the  mass-areas  generated  by  the  wheel  and  body  of 
the  motor  alike.  But  the  friction  on  the  axis  of  the 
body  of  the  motor  only  diminishes  the  sum  of  the  mass- 
areas  generated  by  the  body.  The  wheel  retains,  thus, 
an  excess  of  mass- area,  which  when  the  parts  are  rela- 
tively at  rest  is  rendered  apparent  in  the  motion  of  the 
entire  motor.  The  phenomenon  subsequent  to  the  in- 
terruption of  the  current  supplies  us  with  a  model  of 
what  according  to  the  hypothesis  of  astronomers  has 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.         299 

taken  place  on  the  moon.     The  tidal  wave  created  by  its  iiiostra- 
the  earth  has  reduced  to  such  an  extent  by  friction  the  case  of  the 
velocity  of  rotation  of  the  moon  that  the  lunar  day  has 
grown  to  a  month.     The  fly-wheel  represents  the  fluid 
mass  moved  by  the  tide. 

Another  example  of  this  law  is  furnished  by  reac-  Reaction- 

wheels. 

tion-wheeis.  If  air  or  gas  be  emitted  from  the  wheel 
(Fig.  153^)  in  the  direction  of  the  short  arrows,  the 
whole  wheel  will  be  set  in  rotation  in  the  direction  of 
the  large  arrow.  In  Fig.  153^,  another  simple  reac- 
tion-wheel is  represented.  A  brass  tube  rr  plugged  at 
both  ends  and  appropriately  perforated,  is  placed  on  a 
second  brass  tube  R,  supplied  with  a  thin  steel  pivot 
through  which  air  can  be  blown ;  the  air  escapes  at 
the  apertures  (9,  ff. 

It  might  be  supposed  that  sucking  on  the  reaction-  variation 

i_       1  ij  J  t  .  .  t  ofthephe- 

wheels  would  produce  the  opposite  motion  to  that  re-  nomcna  of 
suiting  from  blowing.  Yet  this  does  not  usually  take  wheels, 
place,  and  the  reason  is  obvious.  The  air  that  is 
sucked  into  the  spokes  of  the  wheel  must  take  part 
immediately  in  the  motion  of  the  wheel,  must  enter 
the  condition  of  relative  rest  with  respect  to  the  wheel ; 
and  when  the  system  is  completely  at  rest,  the  sum  of 
its  mass-areas  must  be  =:  0.  Generally,  no  perceptible 
rotation  takes  place  on  the  sucking  in  of  the  air.  The 
circumstances  are  similar  to  those  of  the  recoil  of  a 
cannon  which  sucks  in  a  projectile.  If,  therefore,  an 
elastic  ball,  which  has  but  one  escape- tube,  be  attached 
to  the  reaction-wheel,  in  the  manner  represented  in 
Fig.  153  a,  and  be  alternately  squeezed  so  that  the 
same  quantity  of  air  is  by  turns  blown  out  and  sucked 
in,  the  wheel  will  continue  rapidly  to  revolve  in  the 
same  direction  as  it  did  in  the  case  in  which  we  blew 
into  it.     This  is  partly  due  to  the  fact  that  the  air 


300  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.  301 

sucked  into  the  spokes  must  participate  in  the  motion  Ezpiana- 
of  the  latter  and  therefore  can  produce  no  reactional  variations, 
rotation,  but  it  also  partly  results  from  the  difference 
of  the  motion  which  the  air  outside  the  tube  assumes 
in  the  two  cases.  In  blowing,  the  air  flows  out  in  jets, 
and  performs  rotations.  In  sucking,  the  air  comes  in 
from  all  sides,  and  has  no  distinct  rotation. 

The  correctness  of  this  view  is  easily  demonstrated. 
If  we  perforate  the  bottom  of  a  hollow  cylinder,  a  closed 
band-box  for  instance,  and 
place  the  cylinder  on  the  steel 
pivot  of  the  tube  R^  after  the 
side  has  been  slit  and  bent  in 
the  manner  indicated  in  Fig. 
154,  the  box  will  turn  in  the 
direction  of  the  long  arrow 
when  blown  into  and  in  the  fir.  154- 

direction  of  the  short  arrow  when  sucked  on.  The  air, 
here,  on  entering  the  cylinder,  can  continue  its  rotation 
unimpeded^  and  this  motion  is  accordingly  compensated 
for  by  a  rotation  in  the  opposite  direction. 

7.  The  following  case  also  exhibits  similar  condi-  ReacUon- 
tions.     Imagine  a  tube  (Fig.    155a)  which,  running 
straight  from  a  to  ^,  turns  at  right  angles 
to  itself  at  the  latter  point,  passes  to  r, 
describes  the  circle  cdef^  whose  plane 
is  at  right  angles  to  ab^  and  whose  cen- 
tre is  at  by  then  proceeds  from  /  to  g^ 
and,  finally,  continuing  the  straight  line 
aby  runs  from  g  to  h.     The  entire  tube 
is  free  to  turn  on  an  axis  ah.     If  we 
pour  into  this  tube,  in  the  manner  in- 
dicated in  Fig.  155^,  a  liquid,  which  flows  in  the  di- 
rection cdefy  the  tube  will  immediately  begin  to  turn 


3oa  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

in  the  direction /ir^i-.  This  impulse,  however,  ceases, 
the  moment  the  liquid  reaches  the  point  _;^  and  Bowing 
out  into  the  radius/g-  is  obliged  to  join  in  the  motion 
of  the  latter.  By  the  use  of  a  constant  stream  of  liquid, 
therefore,  the  rotation 
of  the  tube  may  soon 
be  stopped.  But  if  the 
stream  be  interrupted, 
the  fluid,  in  flowing  off 
through  the  radius  fg, 
will  impart  to  the  tube 
a  motional  impulse  in 
the  direction  of  its  own 
motion,  cdef,  and  the 
tube  will  turn  in  this  di- 
rection. All  these  phe- 
nomena are  easily  ex- 
plained by  the  law  of 

The  trade- winds,  the 
deviation  of  the  oceanic 
currents  and  of  rivers, 
Foucault's  pendulum 
experiment,  and  the 
like,*mayalso  be  treated 
'''*■  '"''■  as  examples  of  the  law 

1  of  areas.  Another  pretty  illustration  is  afforded  by 
bodies  with  variable  moments  of  inertia.  Let  a  body 
with  the  moment  of  inertia  &  rotate  with  the  angular 
velocity  a  and,  during  the  motion,  let  its  moment 
of  inertia  be  transformed  by  internal  forces,  say  by 
springs,  into  &,  a  will  then  pass  into  a",  where  a©  = 
a'©',  that  is  a'  =  a{&j&').  On  any  considerable  dimi- 
nution of  the  moment  of  inertia,  a  great  increase  of 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.  303 

angular  velocity  ensues.  The  principle  might  con- 
ceivably be  employed,  instead  of  Foucault's  method, 
to  demonstrate  the  rotation  of  the  earth,  [in  fact,  some 
attempts  at  this  have  been  made,  with  no  very  marked 
success] . 

A  phenomenon  which  substantially  embodies  the  RotatinR 
conditions  last  suggested  is  the  following.     A  glass  funnel, 
funnel,  with  its  axis  placed  in  a  vertical  position,  is 
rapidly  filled  with  a  liquid  in  such  a  manner  that  the 
stream  does  not  enter  in  the  direction  of  the  axis  but 
strikes  the  sides.     A  slow  rotatory  motion  is  thereby 
set  up  in  the  liquid  which  as  long  as  the  funnel  is  full,  is 
not  noticed.    But  when  the  fluid  retreats  into  the  neck 
of  the  funnel,  its  moment  of  inertia  is  so  diminished 
and  its  angular  velocity  so  increased  that  a  violent 
eddy  with  considerable  axial  depression  is  created. 
Frequently  the  entire  effluent  jet  is  penetrated  by  an 
axial  thread  of  air. 

8.   If  we  carefully  examine  the  principles  of  the  Both  pnn- 

,  .     ciples  are 

centre  of  gravity  and  of  the  areas,  we  shall  discover  in  simply  spe- 

,  ,  cialcasesof 

both  simply  convenient  ^  -,^  the  law  of 

^  ^  .  SQL  2cg^  action  and 

modes  of  expression,  for         Jt.  V-i2w      n^  [       ?2^      reaction, 
practical     purposes,     of 
a    well-known    property 
of  mechanical  phenom- 
ena.    To    the   accelera- 
tion   q}  of  one  mass  m  ^**-  ^^ 
there  always  corresponds  a  contrary  acceleration  <ff  of 
a  second  mass  tn\  where  allowing  for  the  signs  tnq}'\- 
m'  <p'  =  0.     To  the  force  m  (p  corresponds  the  equal 
and  opposite  force  m'<p\     When  any  masses  m  and 
2  m  describe  with  the  contrary  accelerations  2  (p  and  (p 
the  distances  iw  and  w  (Fig.  156),   the  position  of 
their  centre  of  gravity  S  remains  unchanged,  and  the 


304  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

sum  of  their  mass-areas  with  respect  to  any  point  O 
is,  allowing  for  the  signs,  2w./+w.2/=0.  This 
simple  exposition  shows  us,  that  the  principle  of  the 
centre  of  gravity  expresses  the  same  thing  with  respect 
to  parallel  coordinates  that  the  principle  of  areas  ex- 
presses with  respect  to  polar  coordinates.  Both  contain 
simply  the  fact  of  reaction. 
But  they  The  principles  in  question  admit  of  still  another 

construed    Simple  coustructiou.     Just  as  a  single  body  cannot, 
satfons%'f '  without  the  influence  of  external  forces,  that  is,  without 
inertia.       the  aid  of  a  second  body,  alter  its  uniform  motion  of 
progression  or  rotation,  so  also  a  system  of  bodies  can- 
not, without  the  aid  of  a  second  system,  on  which  it 
can,  so  to  speak,  brace  and  support  itself,  alter  what 
may  properly  and  briefly  be  called  its  mean  velocity  of 
progression  or  rotation.   Both  principles  contain,  thus, 
a  generalised  statement  of  the  law  of  inertia,  the  correct- 
ness of  which  in  the  present  form  we  not  only  see  but 
feel. 
Importance       This  feeling  is  not  unscientific;  much  less  is  it 
stinctive     detrimental.  Where  it  does  not  replace  conceptual  in- 
mechanicai  sight  but  exists  by  the  side  of  it,  it  is  really  the  funda- 

facts* 

mental  requisite  and  sole  evidence  of  a  complete  mastery 
of  mechanical  facts.  We  are  ourselves  a  fragment  of 
mechanics,  and  this  fact  profoundly  modifies  our  mental 
life.  *  No  one  will  convince  us  that  the  consideration 
of  mechanico-physiological  processes,  and  of  the  feel- 
ings and  instincts  here  involved,  must  be  excluded  from 
scientific  mechanics.  If  we  know  principles  like  those 
of  the  centre  of  gravity  and  of  areas  only  in  their  ab- 
stract mathematical  form,  without  having  dealt  with  the 
palpable  simple  facts,  which  are  at  once  their  applica- 

*  For  the  development  of  this  view,  see  E.  Mach,  Grundlinien  d*r  Lekrt. 
von  den  Bewegungsfm/ifindunfen,    (Leipsic :  Engelmann,  1875.) 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.  305 

« 

tion  and  their  source,  we  only  half  comprehend  them, 
and  shall  scarcely  recognise  actual  phenomena  as  ex- 
amples of  the  theory.  We  are  in  a  position  like  that 
of  a  person  who  is  suddenly  placed  on  a  high  tower 
but  has  not  previously  travelled  in  the  district  round 
about,  and  who  therefore  does  not  know  how  to  inter- 
pret the  objects  he  sees. 

IV. 
THE  LAWS  OF  IMPACT. 

I.  The  laws  of  impact  were  the  occasion  of  the  Historical 

,  position  of 

enunciation  of  the  most  important  principles  of  me-  the  Laws  of 
chanics,  and  furnished  also  the  first  examples  of  the 
application  of  such  principles.  As  early  as  1639,  a 
contemporary  of  Galileo,  the  Prague  professor,  Marcus 
Marci  (bom  in  1595),  published  in  his  treatise  De  Pro- 
portione  Motus  (Prague)  a  few  results  of  his  investiga- 
tions on  impact.  He  knew  that  a  body  striking  in 
elastic  percussion  another  of  the  same  size  at  rest,  loses 
its  own  motion  and  communicates  an  equal  quantity 
to  the  other.  He  also  enunciates,  though  not  always 
with  the  requisite  precision,  and  frequently  mingled 
with  what  is  false,  other  propositions  which  still  hold 
good.  Marcus  Marci  was  a  remarkable  man.  He  pos- 
sessed for  his  time  very  creditable  conceptions  regard- 
ing the  composition  of  motions  and  "impulses."  In 
the  formation  of  these  ideas  he  pursued  a  method  sim- 
ilar to  that  which  Roberval  later  employed.  He  speaks 
of  partially  equal  and  opposite  motions,  and  of  wholly 
opposite  motions,  gives  parallelogram  constructions, 
and  the  like,  but  is  unable,  although  he  speaks  of  an 
accelerated  motion  of  descent,  to  reach  perfect  clear- 
ness with  regard  to  the  idea  of  force  and  consequently 
also  with  regard  to  the  composition  of  forces.   In  spite 


3o6  rim  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

ere.       of  this,  howBver,  he  discovers  Galileo's  theorem  re- 
rciii       garding  the  descent  of  bodies  in  the  chords  of  circles, 


also  a  few  propositions  relating  to  the  motion  of  the 
pendulum,  and  has  knowledge  of  centrifugal  force  and 
so  on.     Although  Galileo's  Discourses  had  app>eared  a 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES. 


year  previously,  we  cannot,  in  view  of  the  condition  of 
things  produced  in  Central  Eutope  by  the  Thirty  Years' 


War,  assume  that  Marci  was  acquainted  with  them. 
Not  only  would  the  many  errors  in  Marci's  book  thus 
be  rendered  unintelligible,  but  it  would  also  have  to 


3o8  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

The  sources  be  explained  how  Marci,  as  late  as  1648,  in  a  continu- 

of  Marci's         ,  »   •  .  .  «  «  <  ,  *   . 

knowledge,  ation  of  his  treatise,  could  have  found  it  necessary  to 
defend  the  theorem  of  the  chords  of  circles  against  the 
Jesuit  Balthasar  Conradus.  An  imperfect  oral  com- 
munication of  Galileo's  researches  is  the  more  reason- 
able conjecture.*  When  we  add  to  all  this  that  Marci 
was  on  the  very  verge  of  anticipating  Newton  in  the 
discovery  of  the  composition  of  light,  we  shall  recog- 
nise in  him  a  man  of  very  considerable  parts.  His 
writings  are  a  worthy  and  as  yet  but  slightly  noticed 
object  of  research  for  the  historian  of  physics.  Though 
Galileo,  as  the  clearest-minded  and  most  able  of  his 
contemporaries,  bore  away  in  this  province  the  palm, 
we  nevertheless  see  from  writings  of  this  class  that  he 
was  not  by  any  means  alone  in  his  thought  and  ways 
of  thinking. 
There-  2.  Galileo  himsclf  made  several  experimental  at- 

Galileo,  tempts  to  ascertain  the  laws  of  impact ;  but  he  was  not 
in  these  endeavors  wholly  successful.  He  principally 
busied  himself  with  the  force  of  a  body  in  motion,  or 
with  the  "force  of  percussion,"  as  he  expressed  it, 
and  endeavored  to  compare  this  force  with  the  pressure 
of  a  weight  at  rest,  hoping  thus  to  measure  it.  To  this 
end  he  instituted  an  extremely  ingenious  experiment, 
which  we  shall  now  describe. 

A  vessel  I  (Fig.  157)  in  whose  base  is  a  plugged 
orifice,  is  filled  with  water,  and  a  second  vessel  H  is 
hung  beneath  it  by  strings ;  the  whole  is  fastened  to 
the  beam  of  an  equilibrated  balance.  If  the  plug  is 
removed  from  the  orifice  of  vessel  I,  the  fluid  will  fall 

*  I  have  been  convinced,  since  the  publication  of  the  first  edition  of  this 
work,  (see  E.  Wohlwill's  researches,  Die  Entdeckung  de»  Beharmngtgtutzes, 
in  the  Zeitsckri/ffUr  VdVterptyckoUgie^  1884,  XV,  page  387,)  that  Marcus  Marci 
derived  his  information  concerning  the  motion  of  falling  bodies,  from  Galileo's 
tarlitr  Dialogues. — AtUhar*s  Appendix  te  Second  Edition. 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.  309 

in  a  jet  into  vessel  II.  A  portion  of  the  pressure  due  Caiiiao'i 
to  the  resting  weight  of  the  water  in  I  is  lost  and  re-  man. 
placed  by  an  action  of  impact  on  vessel  II.  Galileo 
expected  a  depression  of  the  whole  scale,  by  which  he 
hoped  with  the  assistance  of  a  counter- weight  to  de- 
termine the  effect  of  the  impact.  He  was  to  some  ex- 
tent surprised  to  obtain  no  depression,  and  he  was  un- 
able, it  appears,  perfectly  to  clear  up  the  matter  in  his 
mind. 

3.  To-day,  of  course,  the  explanation  is  not  diffi- 
cult.    By  the  removal  of  the  plug  there  is  produced, 


first,  a  diminution  of  the  pressure.  This  consists  of  EipUna- 
two  factors:  (1)  The  weight  of  the  jet  suspended  ineiperi- 
the  air  is  lost ;  and  (2)  A  reaction-pressure  upwards  is 
exerted  by  the  efHueut  jet  on  vessel  I  (which  acts  like 
a  Segner's  wheel).  Then  there  is  an  increase  of  pres- 
sure (Factor  3)  produced  by  the  action  of  the  jet  on  the 
bottom  of  vessel  II.  Before  the  first  drop  has  reached 
the  bottom  of  II,  we  have  only  to  deal  with  a  diminu- 
tion of  pressure,  which,  when  the  apparatus  is  in  full 
operatjion,  is  immediately  compensated  for.  'Y\\\%  initial 


3IO  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

Deterraina-  depression  was,  in  fact,  all  that  Galileo  could  observe. 

tion  of  the    ^  •  •  t  •  •  11 

mechanical  LrCt  US  imagine  the  apparatus  m  operation,  and  denote 
voived.  the  height  the  fluid  reaches  in  vessel  I  by  //,  the  corre- 
sponding velocity  of  efflux  by  r,  the  distance  of  the 
bottom  of  I  from  the  surface  of  the  fluid  in  II  by  >t,  the 
velocity  of  the  jet  at  this  surface  by  w,  the  area  of  the 
basal  orifice  by  a,  the  acceleration  of  gravity  by  gy  and 
the  specific  gravity  of  the  fluid  by  s.  To  determine 
Factor  (i)  we  may  observe  that  v  is  the  velocity  ac- 
quired in  descent  through  the  distance  h.  We  have, 
then,  simply  to  picture  to  ourselves  this  motion  of  de- 
scent continued  through  k.  The  time  of  descent  of 
the  jet  from  I  to  II  is  therefore  the  time  of  descent 
through  h  '\'  k  less  the  time  of  descent  through  /i. 
During  this  time  a  cylinder  of  base  a  is  discharged 
with  the  velocity  v.  Factor  (i),  or  the  weight  of  the 
jet  suspended  in  the  air,  accordingly  amounts  to 


^^{m'^-m 


as. 


To  determine  Factor  (2)  we  employ  the  familiar 
equation  piv  =^/.  If  we  put  /  =  i,  then  pt7f  =p,  that 
is  the  pressure  of  reaction  upwards  on  I  is  equal  to  the 
momentum  imparted  to  the  fluid  jet  in  unit  of  time. 
We  will  select  here  the  unit  of  weight  as  our  unit  of 
force,  that  is,  use  gravitation  measure.  We  obtain  for 
Factor  (2)  the  expression  [^  v  {s/g)']  v  =  p,  (where  the 
expression  in  brackets  denotes  the  mass  which  flows 
out  in  unit  of  time,)  or 


s 


av^2g/i  .  - .  \/2g/i  =2ahs. 
i 

Similarly  we  find  the  pressure  on  II  to  be 


( 


av  .  ^^\w  =  q,  ox  factor  3  : 
g 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.         311 

J Mathemat' 

a      VtghVtg  {li  +  /')•  '^Zt 

^  toe  result. 

The  total  variation  of  the  pressure  is  accordingly 


-M^^P-4vh 


2a/ts 


as 


or,  abridged, 

—  2as[V^/i(^/i  +  J^)  —  //]  —  2aAs 

+  2asl/7i{/i  +  J^, 

— which  three  factors  completely  destroy  each  other.  In 
the  very  necessity  of  the  case,  therefore,  Galileo  could 
only  have  obtained  a  negative  result. 

We  must  supply  a  brief  comment  respecting  Fac-  a  comment 

sufjgested 

tor  (2).  It  might  be  supposed  that  the  pressure  on  the  by  the  ex- 

penmeiita 

basal  orifice  which  is  lost,  \^  ahs  and  not  2ahs,  But 
this  statical  conception  would  be  totally  inadmissible 
in  the  present,  dynamical  case.  The  velocity  v  is  not 
generated  by  gravity  instantaneously  in  the  effluent 
particles,  but  is  the  outcome  of  the  mutual  pressure 
between  the  particles  flowing  out  and  the  particles  left 
behind  ;  and  pressure  can  only  be  determined  by  the 
momentum  generated.  The  erroneous  introduction  of 
the  value  ahs  would  at  once  betray  itself  by  self-con- 
tradictions. 

If  Galileo's  mode  of  experimentation  had  been  less 
elegant,  he  would  have  determined  without  much  diffi- 
culty the  pressure  which  a  continuous  fluid  jet  exerts. 
But  he  could  never,  as  he  soon  became  convinced, 
have  counteracted  by  a  pressure  the  effect  of  an  instan- 
taneous impact.     Take — and  this  is  the  supposition  of 


312  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

Galileo's     Galileo — a  freely  falling,  heavy  body.     Its  final  veloc- 

reasoning.     ...  •  i  ,  . 

ity,  we  know,  increases  proportionately  to  the  time. 
The  very  smallest  velocity  requires  a  definite  portion 
of  time  to  be  produced  in  (a  principle  which  even  Mari- 
otte  contested).  If  we  picture  to  ourselves  a  body 
moving  vertically  upwards  with  a  definite  velocity,  the 
body  will,  according  to  the  amount  of  this  velocity, 
ascend  a  definite  time,  and  consequently  also  a  definite 
distance.  The  heaviest  imaginable  body  impressed 
in  the  vertical  upward  direction  with  the  smallest  im- 
aginable velocity  will  ascend,  be  it  only  a  little,  in 
opposition  to  the  force  of  gravity.  If,  therefore,  a 
heavy  body,  be  it  ever  so  heavy,  receive  an  instan- 
taneous upward  impact  from  a  body  in  motion,  be  the 
mass  and  velocity  of  that  body  ever  so  small,  and  such 
impact  impart  to  the  heavier  body  the  smallest  imagin- 
able velocity,  that  body  will,  nevertheless,  yield  and 
Compari-    move  somewhat  in  the  upward  direction.  The  sHMest 

son  of  the     .  . 

ideas  im-     impact,  therefore,  is  able  to  overcome  the  greatest  pres- 

pact  and  .  . 

pressure,  sure ;  or,  as  Galileo  says,  the  force  of  percussion  com- 
pared with  the  force  of  pressure  is  infinitely  great.  This 
result,  which  is  sometimes  attributed  to  intellectual  ob- 
scurity on  Galileo's  part,  is,  on  the  contrary,  a  bril- 
liant proof  of  his  intellectual  acumen.  We  should  say 
to-day,  that  the  force  of  percussion,  the  momentum, 
the  impulse,  the  quantity  of  motion  m  ?;,  is  a  quantity 
of  different  dimensions  from  the  pressure  /.  The  dimen- 
sions of  the  former  are  mlt'^^,  those  of  the  latter  mlt'~''^. 
In  reality,  therefore,  pressure  is  related  to  momentum 
of  impact  as  a  line  is  to  a  surface.  Pressure  is  /,  the 
momentum  of  impact  is /  /.  Without  employing  mathe- 
matical terminology  it  is  hardly  possible  to  express  the 
fact  better  than  Galileo  did.  We  now  also  see  why  it 
is  possible  to  measure  the  impact  of  a  continuous  fluid 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.         313 

jet  by  a  pressure.  We  compare  the  momentum  de- 
stroyed per  second  of  time  with  the  pressure  acting 
per  second  of  time,  that  is,  homogeneous  quantities  of 
the  form//. 

4.  The  first  systematic  treatment  of  the  laws  of  The  syste- 
matic treat- 
impact  was  evoked  in  the  year  1668  by  a  request  of  the  ment  of  the 

laws  of  iin- 

Royal  Society  of  London.  Three  eminent  physicists  pact. 
Wallis  (Nov.  26,  1668),  Wren  (Dec.  17,  1668),  and 
HuYGENS  (Jan.  4,  1669)  complied  with  the  invitation  of 
the  society,  and  communicated  to  it  papers  in  which, 
independently  of  each  other,  they  stated,  without  de- 
ductions, the  laws  of  impact.  Wallis  treated  only  of 
the  impact  of  inelastic  bodies.  Wren  and  Huygens  only 
of  the  impact  of  elastic  bodies.  Wren,  previously  to 
publication,  had  tested  by  experiments  his  theorems, 
which,  in  the  main,  agreed  with  those  of  Huygens. 
These  are  the  experiments  to  which  Newton  refers  in 
the  Principia,  Thfe  same  experiments  were,  soon  after 
this,  also  described,  in  a  more  developed  form,  by  Ma- 
riotte,  in  a  special  treatise,  Sur  le  Choc  des  Corps,  Ma- 
riotte  also  gave  the  apparatus  now  known  in  physical 
collections  as  the  percussion-machine. 

According  to  Wallis,  the  decisive  factor  in  impact  waiiis's  re- 
is  momentum^  or  the  product  of  the  mass  {pondus)  into 
the  velocity  {celeritas).  By  this  momentum  the  force 
of  percussion  is  determined.  If  two  inelastic  bodies 
which  have  equal  momenta  strike  each  other,  rest  will 
ensue  after  impact.  If  their  momenta  are  unequal, 
the  difference  of  the  momenta  will  be  the  momentum 
after  impact.  If  we  divide  this  momentum  by  the  sum 
of  the  masses,  we  shall  obtain  the  velocity  of  the  mo- 
tion after  the  impact.  Wallis  subsequently  presented 
his  theory  of  impact  in  another  treatise,  Mechanica  swe 
de  MotUy   London,    1671.     All  his  theorems  may  be 


314  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

brought  together  in  the  formula  now  in  common  use, 
u  =:  {mv  -\-  m'v')/{m  +  m"),  in  which  m,  m'  denote  the 
masses,  i',  v'  the  velocities  before  impact,  and  »  the 
velocity  after  impact. 
■n>'i  5,   Tbe  ideas  which  led  Huygens  to  his  results,  are 

Bsiii.  to  be  found  in  a  posthumous  treatise  of  his,  De  Motu 
Corporum  ex  Percusswne,  1703.  We  shall  examine  these 
in  some  detail.  The  assumptions  from  which  Huygens 


0.4    ^^^ 


proceeds  are:  (1)  the  law  of  inertia;  (3)  that  elastic 
bodies  of  equal  mass,  colliding  with  equal  and  oppo- 
site velocities,  separate  after  impact  with  the  same  ve- 
locities ;  (3)  that  all  velocities  are  relatively  estimated  ; 
(4)  that  a  larger  body  striking  a  smaller  one  at  rest 
imparts  to  the  latter  velocity,  and  loses  a  part  of  its 
own  ;  and  finally  (5)  that  when  one  of  the  colliding 
bodies  preserves  its  velocity,  this  also  is  the  case  with 
the  other. 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES,  315 

Huygens,  now,  imagines  two  equal  elastic  masses,  First,  equal 

clastic 

which  meet  with  equal  and  opposite  velocities  v.  After  masses  ex- 
the  impact  they  rebound  from  each  other  with  exactly  locUies. 
the  same  velocities.  Huygens  is  right  in  assuming  and 
not  deducing  this.  That  elastic  bodies  exist  which  re- 
cover their  forni  after  impact,  that  in  such  a  transac- 
tion no  perceptible  vis  viva  is  lost,  are  facts  which  ex- 
perience alone  can  teach  us.  Huygens,  now,  conceives 
the  occurrence  just  described,  to  take  place  on  a  boat 
which  is  moving  with  the  velocity  v.  For  the  specta- 
tor in  the  boat  the  previous  case  still  subsists  ;  but  for 
the  spectator  on  the  shore  the  velocities  of  the  spheres 
before  impact  are  respectively  2  v  and  0,  and  after  im- 
pact 0  and  2  V,  An  elastic  body,  therefore,  impinging 
on  another  of  equal  mass  at  rest,  communicates  to  the 
latter  its  entire  velocity  and  remains  after  the  impact 
itself  at  rest.  If  we  suppose  the  boat  affected  with  any 
imaginable  velocity,  u^  then  for  the  spectator  on  the 
shore  the  velocities  before  impact  will  be  respectively 
u  -\-  V  and  u  —  v,  and  after  impact  u  —  v  and  u  -(-  v. 
But  since  u  -{-  v  and  u  —  v  may  have  any  values  what- 
soever, it  may  be  asserted  as  a  principle  that  equal 
elastic  masses  exchange  in  impact  their  velocities. 

A  body  at  rest,  however  great,  is  set  in  motion  Second,  the 

,  relative  ve- 

by  a  body  which  strikes  it,  however  small;    as  Ga-»ocityofap- 

,  ,  proach  and 

lileo  pointed  out.     Huygens,  now,  recession  is 

j^        the  same. 

shows,    that  the    approach    of    the         « 
bodies    before    impact    and    their       ^ 


6 


recession   after  impact  take  place  * 

with  the  same  relative  velocity.     A  ^^^'  ^^ 

body  m  impinges  on  a  body  of  mass  M  at  rest,  to  which 
it  imparts  in  impact  the  velocity,  as  yet  undetermined, 
w.  Huygens,  in  the  demonstration  of  this  proposition, 
supposes  that  the  event  takes  place  on  a  boat  moving 


3i6  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

from  M  towards  m  with  the  velocity  w/2.  The  initial 
velocities  are,  then,  v  —  wJT,  and  —  wji, ;  and  the  final 
velocities,  x  and  -f~  ^Z^-  ^ut  as  M  has  not  altered 
the  value,  but  only  the  sign,  of  its  velocity,  so  »»,  if  a 
loss  of  vis  viva  is  not  to  be  sustained  in  elastic  impact, 
can  only  alter  the  sign  of  its  velocity.  Hence,  the  final 
velocities  are  —  {v  —  w/2)  and  +  wji.  As  a  fact, 
then,  the  relative  velocity  of  approach  before  impact 
is  equal  to  the  relative  velocity  of  separation  after  im- 
pact. Whatever  change  of  velocity  a  body  may  suffer, 
in  every  case,  we  can,  by  the  fiction  of  a  boat  in  mo- 
tion, and  apart  from  the  algebraical  signs,  keep  the 
value  of  the  velocity  the  same  before  and  after  impact. 
The  proposition  holds,  therefore,  generally. 
Third.if  the       If  two  masscs  M  and  m  collide,  with  velocities  V 

VfiloCltlfiS 

of  approach  and  v  inversely  proportional  \.o  the  masses,  J/ after  im- 
ly  propor-^  pact  will  rebouud  with  the  velocity  V  and  m  with  the 
massesrso  Velocity  V.  Let  us  suppose  that  the  Velocities  after 
focitie^s  oT  impact  are  F^  and  Vy^  ;  then  by  the  preceding  proposi- 
tion we  must  have  F'+  v  =^V^  +  z^j,  and  by  the  prin- 
ciple of  vis  viva 

MV^       mv^  _MV^^       mv^^ 
~"2        ^  T"~~  "^"~+  "2"* 

Let  us  assume,  now,  that  v^  =^v  -\-  w;  then,  neces- 
sarily, V^  =  F —  w;  but  on  this  supposition 

J/r2    ,    mv,^       MV^    .   mv^   .    ^ .,  .      .  w* 
-^-+-2      ="^-+'-2~+<^^+^)"2- 

And  this  equality  can,  in  the  conditions  of  the  case, 
only  subsist  if  «/  =  0  ;  wherewith  the  proposition  above 
stated  is  established. 

Huygens  demonstrates  this  by  a  comparison,  con- 
structively reached,  of  the  possible  heights  of  ascent 
of  the  bodies  prior  and  subsequently  to  impact.     If 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES,         317 

the  velocities  of  the  impinging  bodies  are  not  inversely  This  propo- 
proportional  to  the  masses,  they  may  be  made  such  by  the  fiction 
the  fiction  of  a  boat  in  motion.     The  proposition  thus  boat,  made 
includes  all  imaginable  cases.  aVcaUs/ 

The  conservation  of  vis  viva  in  impact  is  asserted 
by  Huygens  in  one  of  his  last  theorems  (ii),  which  he 
subsequently  also  handed  in  to  the  London  Society. 
But  the  principle  is  unmistakably  at  the  foundation  of 
the  previous  theorems. 

6.   In  taking  up  the  study  of  any  event  or  phenom-  Typical 

modes  of 

enon  Ay  we  may  acquire  a  knowledge  of  its  component  natural  in- 
elements  by  approaching  it  from  the  point  of  view  of  a 
different  phenomenon  B^  which  we  already  know ;  in 
which  case  our  investigation  of  A  will  appear  as  the 
application  of  principles  before  familiar  to  us.  Or,  we 
may  begin  our  investigation  with  A  itself,  and,  as  na- 
ture is  throughout  uniform,  reach  the  same  principles 
originally  in  the  co^Uemplation  of  A,  The  investiga- 
tion of  the  phenomena  of  impact  was  pursued  simul- 
taneously with  that  of  various  other  mechanical  pro- 
cesses, and  both  modes  of  analysis  were  really  pre- 
sented to  the  inquirer. 

To  begin  with,  we  may  convince  ourselves  that  the  impact  in 

.  the  New- 

problems  of  impact  can  be  disposed  of  by  the  New-  tonian 

tonian  principles,  with  the  help  of  only  a  minimum  of  view. 
new  experiences.  The  investigation  of  the  laws  of  im- 
pact contributed,  it  is  true,  to  the  discovery  of  New- 
ton's laws,  but  the  latter  do  not  rest  solely  on  this  foun- 
dation. The  requisite  new  experiences,  not  contained 
in  the  Newtonian  principles,  are  simply  the  informa- 
tion that  there  are  elastic  and  inelastic  bodies.  Inelastic 
bodies  subjected  to  pressure  alter  their  form  without 
recovering  it ;  elastic  bodies  possess  for  all  their /^rwj 
definite  systems  of  pressures,  so  that  every  alteration 


3i8 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 


First,  in- 
elastic 
masses. 


of  form  is  associated  with  an  alteration  of  pressure,  and 
vice  versa.  Elastic  bodies  recover  their  form  ;  and  the 
forces  that  induce  the  form -alterations  of  bodies  do  not 
come  into  play  until  the  bodies  are  in  contact. 

Let  us  consider  two  inelastic  masses  M  and  m  mov- 
ing respectively  with  the  velocities  V  and  v*  If  these 
masses  come  in  contact  while  possessed  of  these  un- 
equal velocities,  internal  form-altering  forces  will  be 
set  up  in  the  system  M,  tn.  These  forces  do  not  alter 
the  quantity  of  motion  of  the  system,  neither  do  they 
displace  its  centre  of  gravity.  With  the  restitution  of 
equal  velocities,  the  form -alterations  cease  and  in  in- 
elastic bodies  the  forces  which  produce  the  alterations 
vanish.  Calling  the  common  velocity  of  motion  after 
impact  «,  it  follows  that  Mu  -\-  mu  =  MV-\-  Mv,  or 
u  =  (MF+  mv)/(Af+  m),  the  rule  of  Wallis. 
Impact  in  Now  let  US  assume  that  we  are  investigating  the 

lent  point  phenomena  of  impact  without  a  previous  knowledge  of 
Newton's  principles.  We  very  soon  discover,  when 
we  so  proceed,  that  velocity  is  not  the  so/e  determina- 
tive factor  of  impact ;  still  another  physical  quality  is 
decisive — weight,  load,  msiss,  pon/fus,  moles y  massa.  The 
moment  we  have  noted  this  fact,  the  simplest  case  is 
easily  dealt  with.     If  two  bodies  of  equal  weight  or 

equal  mass  collide  with  equal  and 
opposite  velocities ;  if,  further,  the 
bodies  do  not  separate  after  impact 
but  retain  some  common  velocity, 
plainly    the    sole     uniquely    deter- 
mined velocity  after  the  collision  is  the  velocity  0.    If, 
further,  we  make  the  observation  that  only  the  dif- 
ference of  the  velocities,  that  is  only  relative  velocity, 
determines  the  phenomenon  of  impact,  we  shall,  by 
imagining  the  environment  to  move,  (which  experience 


O      O 


Fig.  x6x. 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES, 


319 


tells  US  has  no  influence  on  the  occurrence,)  also  readily 
perceive  additional  cases.  For  equal  inelastic  masses 
with  velocities  v  and  0  or  «;  and  v*  the  velocity  after 
impact  is  vji  or  {v  +  v*)!'!.  It  stands  to  reason  that 
we  can  pursue  such  a  line  of  reflection  only  after  ex- 
perience has  informed  us  what  the  essential  and  de- 
cisive features  of  the  phenomena  are. 

If  we  pass  to  unequal  masses,  we  must  not  only  The  expe- 

1  t  .1  „     •        r  riendaf 

know  from  experience  that  mass  generally  is  of  conse-  conditions 

of  this 

quence,  but  also  in  what  manner  its  influence  is  eflec-  method, 
tive.     If,  for  example,  two  bodies  of  masses  i  and  3 
with  the  velocities  v  and  F  collide,  we  might  reason 


(b 


v< 


V 


Fig.  163. 


Fig.  163. 


thus.  We  cut  out  of  the  mass  3  the  mass  i  (Fig.  162), 
and  first  make  the  masses  i  and  i  collide :  the  result- 
ant velocity  is  {v  +  O/^-  There  are  now  left,  to 
equalise  the  velocities  (z^  +  F)/2  and  V^  the  masses 
I  -f  I  =  2  and  2,  which  applying  the  same  principle 
gives 


-+  V 


2  ■"        4        "^    1  +  3  • 

Let  us  now  consider,  more  generally,  the  masses 
m  and  fn\  which  we  represent  in  Fig.  163  as  suitably 
proportioned  horizontal  lines.  These  masses  are  af- 
fected with  the  velocities  v  and  v\  which  we  represent 
by  ordinates  erected  on  the  mass-lines.  Assuming  that 


320 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 


Its  points  of /^  <  m*y  we  cut  off  from  m'  a  portion  tn.  The  offsetting 
with  the  of  ///  and  m  gives  the  mass  7.m  with  the  velocity  {v  + 
'  e'')/2.  The  dotted  line  indicates  this  relation.  We 
proceed  similarly  with  the  remainder  m* —  m.  We  cut 
off  from  7.m  2l  portion  m'  —  w,  and  obtain  the  mass 
7,m  —  {m' —  ni)  with  the  velocity  (7^  +  t'')/2  and  the 
mass  2(/;/' —  ni)  with  the  velocity  \{v  +  Z'')/2  +  z/']/2. 
In  this  manner  we  may  proceed  till  we  have  obtained 
for  the  whole  mass  m  -\'  tn*  the  same  velocity  u.  The 
constructive  method  indicated  in  the  figure  shows  very 
plainly  that  here  the  surface  equation  (m  +  «r')  u  = 
mv  -\'  m'v'  subsists.  We  readily  perceive,  however, 
that  we  cannot  pursue  this  line  of  reasoning  except  the 
sum  mv  -\-  m'v\  that  is  the  form  of  the  influence  of  m 
and  V,  has  through  some  experience  or  other  been  pre- 
viously suggested  to  us  as  the  determinative  and  de- 
cisive factor.  If  we  renounce  the  use  of  the  Newtonian 
principles,  then  some  o'ther  specific  experiences  con- 
cerning the  import  oi  mv  which  are  equivalent  to  those 
principles,  are  indispensable. 

7.  The  impact  of  elastic  masses  may  also  be  treated 
by  the  Newtonian  principles.  The  sole  observation 
here  required  is,  that  a  deformation  of  elastic  bodies 
calls  into  play  forces  of  restitutioriy  which  directly  de- 
pend on  the  deformation.  Furthermore,  bodies  pos- 
sess impenetrability ;  that  is  to  say,  when  bodies  af- 
fected with  unequal  velocities  meet  in  impact,  forces 
which  equalise  these  velocities  are  produced.  If  two 
elastic  masses  My  m  with  the  velocities  C,  c  collide,  a 
deformation  will  be  effected,  and  this  deformation  will 
not  cease  until  the  velocities  of  the  two  bodies  are 
equalised.  At  this  instant,  inasmuch  as  only  internal 
forces  are  involved  and  therefore  the  momentum  and 


Second,  the 
impact  of 
elastic 
masses  in 
Newton's 
view. 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.         321 

the  motion  of  the  centre  of  gravity  of  the  system  re- 
main unchanged,  the  common  equalised  velocity  will  be 

MC  -\-  mc 
M  -\-  m    ' 

Consequently,  up  to  this  time,  Af^s  velocity  has  suf- 
fered a  diminution  C —  u\  and  nCs  an  increase  u  —  c. 
But  elastic  bodies  being  bodies  that  recover  their 
forms,  in  perfectly  elastic  bodies  the  very  same  forces 
that  produced  the  deformation,  will,  only  in  the  in- 
verse order,  again  be  brought  into  play,  through  the 
very  same  elements  of  time  and  space.  Consequently, 
on  the  supposition  that  m  is  overtaken  by  J/,  M  will  a 
second  time  sustain  a  diminution  of  velocity  C —  «,  and 
m  will  a  second  time  receive  an  increase  of  velocity 
u  —  c.  Hence,  we  obtain  for  the  velocities  V,  v  after 
impact  the  expressions  Vz=^  2u  —  C  and  v  =  2u  —  r,  or 

AfC+m(2e—C)       _  mc  +  M(2C—c) 
If  in  these  formulae  we  put  J/ =w,  it  will  follow  T*>«  ?«*«?- 

'^  '  uon  by  this 

that  V=  c  and  t/  =  C ;  or,  if  the  impinging  masses  are  ^'^  <>' »» 
equal,  the  velocities  which  they  have  will  be  inter- 
changed. Again,  since  in  the  particular  case  Mjm  = 
—  cjC  or  MC -\-  mc:=i^  also  «  =  0,  it  follows  that 
V=i2u—  C=—  C  and  v=%u  —  €  =  —  c\  that  is, 
the  masses  recede  from  each  other  in  this  case  with  the 
same  velocities  (only  oppositely  directed)  with  which 
they  approached.  The  approach  of  any  two  masses 
J/,  m  affected  with  the  velocities  C,  r,  estimated  as 
positive  when  in  the  same  direction,  takes  place  with 
the  velocity  C  —  c\  their  separation  with  the  velocity 
V — V,  But  it  follows  at  once  from  F=2u — C, 
vt=2u  —  Cy  that  V —  v  =  —  (C —  c);  that  is,  the  rela- 
tive velocity  of  approach  and  recession  is  the  same. 


view. 


322  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

By  the  use  of  the  expressions  F=  2i^  —  Cand  v  = 
2  «  —  r,  we  also  very  readily  find  the  two  theorems 

MV -{-  mv  =  MC -\-  mc  and 

which  assert  that  the  quantity  of  motion  before  and 
after  impact,  estimated  in  the  same  direction,  is  the 
same,  and  that  also  the  7ns  viva  of  the  system  before 
and  after  impact  is  the  same.  We  have  reached,  thus, 
by  the  use  of  the  Newtonian  principles,  all  of  Huy- 
gens's  results. 
The  impii-  8.  If  we  consider  the  laws  of  impact  from  Huygens's 
Huygens'8  point  of  view,  the  following  reflections  immediately 
claim  our  attention.  The  height  of  ascent  which  the 
centre  of  gravity  of  any  system  of  masses  can  reach  is 
given  by  its  vis  viva,  ^2mv^.  In  every  case  in  which 
work  is  done  by  forces,  and  in  such  cases  the  masses 
follow  the  forces,  this  sum  is  increased  by  an  amount 
equal  to  the  work  done.  On  the  other  hand,  in  every 
case  in  which  the  system  moves  in  opposition  to  forces, 
that  is,  when  work,  as  we  may  say,  is  donf  upon  the 
system,  this  sum  is  diminished  by  the  amount  of  work 
done.  As  long,  therefore,  as  the  algebraical  sum  of 
the  work  done  on  the  system  and  the  work  done  by  the 
system  is  not  changed,  whatever  other  alterations  may 
take  place,  the  sum^^/w?'^  also  remains  unchanged. 
Huygens  now,  observing  that  this  first  property  of  ma- 
terial systems,  discovered  by  him  in  his  investigations 
on  the  pendulum,  also  obtained  in  the  case  of  impact, 
could  not  help  remarking  that  also  the  sum  of  the 
vires  viva  must  be  the.  same  before  and  after  im- 
pact. For  in  the  mutually  effected  alteration  of  the 
forms  of  the  colliding  bodies  the  material  system  con- 
sidered has  the  same  amount  of  work  done  on  it  as,  on 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.  323 

the  reversal  of  the  alteration,  is  done  by  it,  provided  al- 
ways the  bodies  develop  forces  wholly  determined  by 
the  shapes  they  assume,  and  that  they  regain  their 
original  form  by  mean&  of  the  same  forces  employed  to 
effect  its  alteration.  That  the  latter  process  takes 
place,  definite  experience  alone  can  inform  us.  This  law 
obtains,  furthermore,  only  in  the  case  of  so-called  per- 
fectly elastic  bodies. 

Contemplated  from  this  point  of  view,  the  majority  The  dedac- 
of  the  Huygenian  laws  of  impact  follow  at  once.  Equal  laws  of  im- 

.  ,  ,  pact  by  the 

masses,  which  strike  each  other  with  equal  but  oppo-  notion  of 

vis  viva  and 

site  velocities,  rebound  with  the  same  velocities.  The  work, 
velocities  are  uniquely  determined  only  when  they  are 
equals  and  they  conform  to  the  principle  of  vis  viva 
only  by  being  the  same  before  and  after  impact.  Fur- 
ther it  is  evident,  that  if  one  of  the  unequal  masses  in 
impact  change  only  the  sign  and  not  the  magnitude  of 
i  ts  velocity,  this  must  also  be  the  case  with  the  other. 
On  this  supposition,  however,  the  relative  velocity  of 
separation  after  impact  is  the  same  as  the  velocity  of 
approach  before  impact.  Every  imaginable  case  can 
be  reduced  to  this  one.  Let  c  and  c'  be  the  velocities 
of  the  mass  m  before  and  after  impact,  and  let  them  be 
of  any  value  and  have  any  sign.  We  imagine  the  whole 
system  to  receive  a  velocity  u  of  such  magnitude  that 
«  -f  r  =  —  {u-\-  c'^  or  u=l{c  —  ^')/2.  It  will  be  seen 
thus  that  it  is  always  possible  to  discover  a  velocity  of 
transportation  for  the  system  such  that  the  velocity  of 
one  of  the  masses  will  only  change  its  sign.  And  so 
the  proposition  concerning  the  velocities  of  approach 
and  recession  holds  generally  good. 

As  Huygens's  peculiar  group  of  ideas  was  not  fully 
perfected,  he  was  compelled,  in  cases  in  which  the  ve- 
locity-ratios of  the  impinging  masses  were  not  origin- 


324 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 


Hnygens's 
tacit  appro- 
priation of 
the  idea  of 
mass. 


Construc- 
tive com- 
parison of 
the  special 
and  general 
case  of  im- 
pact. 


ally  known,  to  draw  on  the  Galileo-Newtonian  system 
for  certain  conceptions,  as  was  pointed  out  above. 
Such  an  appropriation  of  the  concepts  mass  and  mo- 
mentum, is  contained,  although  not  explicitly  ex- 
pressed, in  the  proposition  according  to  which  the  ve- 
locity of  each  impinging  mass  simply  changes  its  sign 
when  before  impact  MIm  =  —  c/C,  If  Huygens  had 
wholly  restricted  himself  to  his  own  point  of  view,  he 
would  scarcely  have  discovered  this  proposition,  al- 
though, once  discovered,  he  was  able,  after  his  own 
fashion,  to  supply  its  deduction.  Here,  owing  to  the 
fact  that  the  momenta  produced  are  equal  and  oppo- 
site, the  equalised  velocity  of  the  masses  on  the  com- 
pletion of  the  change  of  form  will  be  »  =  0.  When  the 
alteration  of  form  is  reversed,  and  the  same  amount  of 
work  is  performed  that  the  system  originally  suffered, 
the  satfie  velocities  with  opposite  signs  will  be  restored. 
If  we  imagine  the  entire  system  affected  with  a  ve- 
locity of  translation^  this  particular  case  will  simulta- 
neously present  the^^«^rd:/case. 
Let  the  impii^ging  masses  be 
represented  in  the  figure  by 
M—BC  and  m  =  AC  (Fig. 
164),  and  their  respective  velo- 
cities by  C=  AD  and  c  =  BE. 
On  AB  erect  the  perpendicular 
CF,  and  through  F  draw  IK 
parallel  to  AB.  Then  ID  =  {m.  C—c)/{,M-\-  m)  and 
KB  =  {M.C —  c)/{^M-\-  m).  On  the  supposition  now 
that  we  make  the  masses  M  and  m  collide  with  the 
velocities  ID  and  KEj  while  we  simultaneously  impart 
to  the  system  as  a  whole  the  velocity 

u  =  AI=  KB  =  C—  {m  .  C—'~c)/{M-\-  m)  = 
c  +  {M.  C—c)J(^M-\-  m)  =  {MC+  mc)/(^M+  m), 


Fig.  164. 


THE  EXTENSION^  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.  325 

the  spectator  who  is  moving  forwards  with  the  velocity 
u  will  see  the  particular  case  presented,  and  the  spec- 
tator who  is  at  rest  will  see  the  general  case,  be  the 
velocities-  what  they  may.  The  general  formulae  of  im- 
pact, above  deduced,  follow  at  once  from  this  concep- 
tion.    We  obtain  : 

M  -^  m  M  -\-  m 

M  -\-  m  M  -\-  m 

Huygen*s  successful  employment  of  the  fictitious  signifi- 
motions  is  the  outcome  of  the  simple  perception  that  fictitious 

,  .  motions. 

bodies  not  affected  with  differences  of  velocities  do  not 
act  on  one  another  in  impact.  All  forces  of  impact  are 
determined  by  differences  of  velocity  (as  all  thermal 
effects  are  determined  by  differences  of  temperature). 
And  since  forces  generally  determine,  not  velocities, 
but  only  changes  of  velocities,  or,  again,  differences  of 
velocities,  consequently,  in  every  aspect  of  impact  the 
sole  decisive  factor  is  differences  of  velocity.  With  re- 
spect to  which  bodies  the  velocities  are  estimated,  is 
indifferent.  In  fact,  many  cases  of  impact  which  from 
lack  of  practice  appear  to  us  as  different  cases,  turn 
out  on  close  examination  to  be  one  and  the  same. 

Similarly,  the  capacity  of  a  moving  body  for  work,  velocity,  a 
whether  we  measure  it  with  respect  to  the  time  of  its  level, 
action  by  its  momentum  or  with  respect  to  the  distance 
through  which  it  acts  by  its  vis  viva,  has  no  signifi- 
cance referred  to  a  single  body.  It  is  invested  with 
such,  only  when  a  second  body  is  introduced,  and,  in 
the  first  case,  then,  it  is  the  difference  of  the  veloci- 
ties, and  in  the  second  the  square  of  the  difference  that 
is  decisive.  Velocity  is  a  physical  level,  like  tempera- 
ture, potential  function,  and  the  like. 


326  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

Possible  It  remains  to  be  remarked,  that  Huygens  could 

origin  of     have  reached,  originally,  in  the  investigation  of  the 

Huygens's       ,  ,    .  .  i  ,  , 

ideas.  phenomena  of  impact,  the  same  results  that  he  pre- 
viously reached  by  his  investigations  of  the  pendulum. 
In  every  case  there  is  one  thing  and  one  thing  only  to 
be  done,  and  that  is,  to  discover  in  all  the  facts  the  same 
elements^  or,  if  we  will,  to  rediscover  in  one  fact  the 
elements  of  another  which  we  already  know.  From 
which  facts  the  investigation  starts,  is,  however,  a 
matter  of  historical  accident. 
Conserva-  9.  Let  US  close  our  examination  of  this  part  of  the 
mentum  in-  subject  with  a  few  general  remarks.  The  sum  of  the 
momenta  of  a  system  of  moving  bodies  is  preserved  in 
impact,  both  in  the  case  of  inelastic  and  elastic  bodies. 
But  this  preservation  does  not  take  place  precisely  in 
the  sense  of  Descartes.  The  momentum  of  a  body  is 
not  diminished  in  proportion  as  that  of  another  is  in- 
creased ;  a  fact  which  Huygens  was  the  first  to  note. 
If,  for  example,  two  equal  inelastic  masses,  possessed 
of  equal  and  opposite  velocities,  meet  in  impact,  the 
two  bodies  lose  in  the  Cartesian  sense  their  entire  mo- 
mentum. If,  however,  we  reckon  all  velocities  in  a 
given  direction  as  positive,  and  all  in  the  opposite  as 
negative,  the  sum  of  the  momenta  is  preserved.  Quan- 
tity of  motion,  conceived  in  this  sense,  is  always  pre- 
served. 

The  vis  viva  of  a  system  of  inelastic  masses  is  al- 
tered in  impact  \  that  of  a  system  of  perfectly  elastic 
masses  is  preserved.  The  diminution  of  vis  viva  pro- 
duced in  the  impact  of  inelastic  masses,  or  produced 
generally  when  the  impinging  bodies  move  with  a  com- 
mon velocity,  after  impact,  is  easily  determined.  Let 
My  m  be  the  masses,  C,  c  their  respective  velocities  be- 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.  327 

fore  impact,  and  u  their  common  velocity  after  impact ;  Consenra- 

-      .        .        .  tion  of  vis 

then  the  loss  of  VtS  viva  is  viva  in  im- 

pact inter- 

iJ/^C2  +  Jw^a  — i(ilf +»l)«a, (l)Preted. 

which  in  view  of  the  fact  that  u  =  {MC  -\-  tn  c)/{M-\-  tn) 
may  be  expressed  in  the  form  {Mm/M  -{-  m)(^C —  r)*. 
Carnot  has  put  this  loss  in  the  form 

iM(C—uy-\-im(^u^cy (2) 

If  we  select  the  latter  form,  the  expressions  ^M^C —  u)^ 
and  im{u  —  r)^  will  be  recognised  as  the  vis  viva  gen- 
erated by  the  work  of  the  internal  forces.  The  loss  of 
vis  viva  in  impact  is  equivalent,  therefore,  to  the  work 
done  by  the  internal  or  so-called  molecular  forces.  If 
we  equate  the  two  expressions  (i)  and  (2),  remember- 
ing that  {M -|-  w) «  =:  MC -^  me,  we  shall  obtain  an 
identical  equation.  Carnot's  expression  is  important 
for  the  estimation  of  losses  due  to  the  impact  of  parts 
of  machines. 

In  all  the  preceding  expositions  we  have  treated  pbUque 
the  impinging  masses  as  points  which  moved  only  in  the 
direction  of  the  lines  joining  them.  This  simplifica- 
tion is  admissible  when  the  centres  of  gravity  and  the 
point  of  contact  of  the  impinging  masses  lie  in  one 
straight  line,  that  is,  in  the  case  of  so-called  direct  im- 
pact. The  investigation  of  what  is  called  oblique  im- 
pact is  somewhat  more  complicated,  but  presents  no 
especial  interest  in  point  of  principle. 

A  question  of  a  different  character  was  treated  by  The  centre 
Wallis.  If  a  body  rotate  about  an  axis  and  its  motion  aioS!*^*^"*^ 
be  suddenly  checked  by  the  retention  of  one  of  its 
points,  the  force  of  the  percussion  will  vary  with  the 
position  (the  distance  from  the  axis)  of  the  point  ar- 
rested. The  point  at  which  the  intensity  of  the  impact 
is  greatest  is  called  by  Wallis  the  centre  of  percussion. 


328  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

If  this  point  be  checked,  the  axis  will  sustain  no  pres- 
sure. We  have  no  occasion  here  to  enter  in  detail 
into  these  investigations  ;  they  were  extended  and  de- 
veloped by  Wallis's  contemporaries  and  successors  in 
many  ways. 
Thebaiiis-         lo.  We  will  uow  briefly  examine,  before  concluding 

tic  pendu-      -  .  , 

lam.  this  section,  an  interesting  application  of  the  laws  of 

impact  ;  namely,  the  determination  of  the  velocities  of 
projectiles  by  the  ballistic  pendulum,  A  mass  M\s  sus- 
pended by  a  weightless  and  massless 
string  (Fig.  165),  so  as  to  oscillate  as  a 
pendulum.  While  in  the  position  of 
equilibrium  it  suddenly  receives  the  hori- 
zontal velocity  V,  It  ascends  by  virtue 
of  this  velocity  to  an  altitude  //  =  (/) 
(1  —  cos  a)  =  V^ /2g,  where  /denotes  the 
length  of  the  pendulum,  a  the  angle  of 
elongation,  and  g  the  acceleration  of 
gravity.  As  the  relation  7'=  nV Ijg  subsists  between 
the  time  of  oscillation  T  and  the  quantities  /,  g^  we 
easily  obtain  F=  (^7y;r)l/2(l  —  cosa),  and  by  the 
use  of  a  familiar  trigonometrical  formula,  also 

r  r       2  or 

V=-gTsm-^^, 

Its  formula.       If  now  the  velocity  Fis  produced  by  a  projectile  of 

the  mass  m  which  being  hurled  with  a  velocity  v  and 

sinking  in  M  is  arrested  in  its  progress,  so  that  whether 

the  impact  is  elastic  or  inelastic,  in  any  case  the  two 

masses  acquire  after  impact  the  r^w»i<7«  velocity  K,  it 

follows  that  mv=^  (^-\-  ^)  ^\  or»  if  ^  be  sufficiently 

small  compared  with  M,  also  v  =  (^M/m)V\  whence 

finally 

2      M    -,     a 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.         329 

/ 

If  it  is  not  permissible  to  regard  the  ballistic  pen-  A  different 

deduction. 

dulum  as  a  simple  pendulum,  our  reasoning,  in  con- 
formity with  principles  before  employed,  will  take  the 
following  shape.  The  projectile  m  with  the  velocity  v 
has  the  momentum  mv^  which  is  diminished  by  the 
pressure/  due  to  impact  in  a  very  short  interval  of 
time  r  to  tnV.  Here,  then,  tn{v  —  F)  =/t,  or,  if  V 
compared  with  v  is  very  small,  mv  =pr.  With  Pon- 
celet,  we  reject  the  assumption  of  anything  like  in- 
stantaneous  forces,  which  generate  instanter  velocities. 
There  are  no  instantaneous  forces.  What  has  been 
called  such  are  very  great  forces  that  produce  per- 
ceptible velocities  in  very  short  intervals  of  time,  but 
which  in  other  respects  do  not  differ  from  forces  that 
act  continuously.  If  the  force  active  in  impact  cannot 
be  regarded  as  constant  during  its  entire  period  of  ac- 
tion, we  have  only  to  put  in  the  place  of  the  expression 
pr  the  expression  Cpdt,  In  other  respects  the  reason- 
ing is  the  same. 

A  force  equal  to  that  which  destroys  the  momentum  The  vis 

viva  ftnd 

of  the  projectile,  acts  in  reaction  on  the  pendulum.   If  work  of  the 

pendulum. 

we  take  the  line  of  projection  of  the  shot,  and  conse- 
quently also  the  line  of  the  force,  perpendicular  to  the 
axis  of  the  pendulum  and  at  the  distance  b  from  it,  the 
moment  of  this  force  will  be  bp^  the  angular  accelera- 
tion generated  bp/^mr^,  and  the  angular  velocity  pro- 
duced in  time  r 

b  .  pT  bmv 

The  m's  viva  which  the  pendulum  has  at  the  end  of 
time  r  is  therefore 

b^m^v^ 


iip^2mr^  =  i  ^ 


mr^ 


330  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

The  result,  By  virtuc  of  this  vis  viva  the  pendulum  performs 
the  excursion  a,  and  its  weight  Mg^  {a  being  the  dis- 
tance of  the  centre  of  gravity  from  the  axis,)  is  lifted 
the  distance  a(\  —  cos^f).  The  work  performed  here 
is  Mga{\ — cosflf),  which  is  equal  to  the  above-men- 
tioned vis  viva.  Equating  the  two  expressions  we 
readily  obtain 

1/2  Mga  2m  r^  (1  —  cos  a) 

mb  ' 

and  remembering  that  the  time  of  oscillation  is 


and  employing  the  trigonometrical  reduction  which 
was  resorted  to  immediately  above,  also 

2  M  a      _     ,    a 

V  =.  -.-  gT ,  sm-   . 

n  m   b  2 

interpreta-        This  formula  is  in  every  respect  similar  to  that  ob- 

tion  of  the  ''  '^ 

result.  tained  for  the  simple  case.  The  observations  requisite 
for  the  determination  of  v,  are  the  mass  of  the  pendu- 
lum and  the  mass  of  the  projectile,  the  distances  of 
the  centre  of  gravity  and  point  of  percussion  from  the 
axis,  and  the  time  and  extent  of  oscillation.  The  form- 
ula also  clearly  exhibits  the  dimensions  of  a  velocity. 
The  expressions  2/;r  and  sin  (a/2)  are  simple  num- 
bers, as  are  also  M/m  and  a/b,  where  both  numerators 
and  denominators  are  expressed  in  units  of  the  same 
kind.  But  the  factor  ^T'  has  the  dimensions  //"^,  and 
is  consequently  a  velocity.  The  ballistic  pendulum 
was  invented  by  Robins  and  described  by  him  at  length 
in  a  treatise  entitled  JV^w  Principles  of  Gunnery,  pub- 
lished in  1742. 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.         331 


V, 

d'alembert's  principle. 

1.  One  of  the  most  important  principles  for  the  History  of 
rapid  and  convenient  solution  of  the  problems  of  me-  cipie. 
chanics  is  the  principle  of  D^  A  Umber i.    The  researches 
concerning  the  centre  of  oscillation  on  which  almost  all 
prominent  contemporaries  and  successors  of  Huygens 

had  employed  themselves,  led  directly  to  a  series  of 
simple  observations  which  D'Alembert  ultimately  gen- 
eralised and  embodied  in  the  principle  which  goes  by 
his  name.  We  will  first  cast  a  glance  at  these  prelim- 
inary performances.  They  were  almost  without  excep- 
tion evoked  by  the  desire  to  replace  the  deduction  of 
Huygens,  which  did  not  appear  sufficiently  obvious,  by 
one  that  was  more  convincing.  Although  this  desire  was 
founded,  as  we  have  already  seen,  on  a  miscompre- 
hension due  to  historical  circumstances,  we  have,  of 
course,  no  occasion  to  regret  the  new  points  of  view 
which  were  thus  reached. 

2.  The  first  in  importance  of  the  founders  of  the  James  Ber- 

noulli's 

theory  of  the  centre  of  oscillation,  after  Huygens,  iscomribu- 

tions  to  the 

Tames  Bernoulli,  who  sought  as  early  as  1686  to  ex- theory  of 

,  the  centre 

plain  the  compound  pendulum  by  the  lever.  He  ar-  of  osdiu- 
rived,  however,  at  results  which  not  only  were  obscure 
but  also  were  at  variance  with  the  conceptions  of  Huy- 
gens. The  errors  of  Bernoulli  were  animadverted  on 
by  the  Marquis  de  L*Hopital  in  \h&  Journal  de  Rotter- 
dam^ in  1690.  The  consideration  of  velocities  acquired 
in  infinitely  small  intervals  of  time  in  place  of  velocities 
acquired  m  finite  times — a  consideration  which  the  last- 
named  mathematician  suggested — led  to  the  removal 


332  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

of  the  main  difficulties  that  beset  this  problem  ;  and  in 
1691,  in  the  Acta  ErudiUrum,  and,  later,  in  1703,  in  the 
Proceedings  of  the  Paris  Academy  James  Bernoulli  cor- 
rected his  error  and  presented  his  results  in  a  final  and 
complete  form.  We  shall  here  reproduce  the  essential 
points  of  his  final  deduction. 
James  Ber-        A  horizontal,  massless  bar  AB  (Fig.  166)  is  free  to 

noulli'sde-  >^       v^  y 

duction  of  rotate  about  A :  and  at  the  distances  r,  r'  from  A  the 

the  law  of  .  .  -  .    - 

the  com-     masses  m.  m*  are  attached.  The  accelerations  with  which 

pound  pen- 

duiumfrom  these  masses  as  thus  connected 

the  princi-       nUr'  X      fikr 

pie  of  the     g^ '^ —  [^>-^A      ^^^^  ^^^^  must  be  different  from 

the    accelerations  which   they 
„.     ^^  would  assume  if  their  connec- 

FlR.  166. 

tions  were  severed  and  they  fell 
freely.  There  will  be  one  point  and  one  only,  at  the 
distance  jc,  as  yet  unknown,  from  A  which  will  fall 
with  the  same  acceleration  as  it  would  have  if  it  were 
free,  that  is,  with  the  acceleration  g.  This  point  is 
termed  the  centre  of  oscillation. 

\i  m  and  ;«'  were  to  be  attracted  to  the  earth,  not 
proportionally  to  their  masses,  but  m  so  as  to  fall  when 
free  with  the  acceleration  cp  =  grjx  and  m*  with  the 
acceleration  <p'  =  gr^/x,  that  is  to  say,  if  the  natural 
accelerations  of  the  masses  were  proportional  to  their 
distances  from  A^  these  masses  would  not  interfere  with 
one  another  when  connected.  In  reality,  however,  m 
sustains,  in  consequence  of  the  connection,  an  upward 
component  acceleration  g  —  ^,  and ;//'  receives  in  virtue 
of  the  same  fact  a  downward  component  acceleration 
cp'  —  g\  that  is  to  say,  the  former  suffers  an  upward 
force  of  nt(^g  —  9?)  =  g{x  —  r/a*)  m  and  the  latter  a 
downward  force  of  m'  i^cp'  —  g)  ==  g{P  —  x/x)  m\ 

Since,  however,  the  masses  exert  what  influence 
they  have  on  each  other  solely  through  the  medium  of 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.  333 

the  lever  by  which  they  are  joined,  the  upward  force  The  lawof 
upon  the  one  and  the  downward  force  upon  the  other  bution  of 

the  effects 

must  satisfy  the  law  of  the  lever.     If  m  in  conse- of  the  im- 
quence  of  its  being  connected  with  the  lever  is  held  forces,  in 
back  by  a  force /from  the  motion  which  it  would  take,  nouiii's  ex- 
if  free,  it  will  also  exert  jthe  same  force /on  the  lever- 
arm  r  by  reaction.     It  is  this  reaction  pull  alone  that 
can  be  transferred  to  m  and  be  balanced  there  by  a 
pressure /*=  {r/r')/,  and  is  therefore  equivalent  to  the 
latter  pressure.     There  subsists,  therefore,  agreeably 
to  what  has  been  above  said,  the  relation  g(y  —  -^A) 
///'  =  r//  *  g{x  —  r/x)  m  or,  {x  —  r)mr  =  (y  —  x)  m'r^, 
from  which  we  obtain  x=^{mr^  +  m'/^)/{mr  -[-  wV), 
exactly  as  Huygens  found  it.     The  generalisation  of 
this  reasoning,  for  any  number  of  masses,  which  need 
not  lie  in  a  single  straight  line,  is  obvious. 

3.  John  Bernoulli  (in  1712)  attacked  in  a  different  The  prin- 
manner  the  problem  of  the  centre  of  oscillation.     Hisjc£nBer- 
performances  are  easiest  consulted  in  his  Collected  inUon  of 
Works  iOperay  Lausanne  and  Geneva,  1762,  Vols.  IIof^tEecen" 
and  IV).     We  shall  examine  in  detail  here  the  main  lation. 
ideas  of  this  physicist.     Bernoulli  reaches  his  goal  by 
conceiving  the  masses  ^n^  forces  separated. 

First y  let  us  consider  two  simple  pendulums  of  dif-  The  first 
ferent  lengths  /,  /'  whose  bobs  are  affected  with  gravi-  BernouiH" 
tational  accelerations  proportional  to  the  lengths  of  the 
pendulums,  that  is,  let  us  put  ///'  z=ig/g\  As  the  time 
of  oscillation  of  a  pendulum  is  2"=  nV  l/g,  it  follows 
that  the  times  of  oscillation  of  these  pendulums  will  be 
the  same.  Doubling  the  length  of  a  pendulum,  ac- 
cordingly, while  at  the  same  time  doubling  the  accel- 
eration of  gravity  does  not  alter  the  period  of  oscilla- 
tion. 

Second,  though  we  cannot  directly  alter  the  accel- 


334  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

The  second  eration  of  gravity  at  any  one  spot  on  the  earth,  we 

step  in  John  .  ,i  i  •         r«i  •  • 

Bernoulli's  can  do  what  amounts  virtually  to  this.    Thus,  imagine 
a  straight  massless  bar  of  length  2a,  free  to  rotate  about 
its  middle  point;  and  attach  to  the  one  ex- 
m'     tremity  of  it  the  mass  m  and  to  the  other  the 
a       mass  m\     Then  the  total  mass  is  m  -(-  m*  at 
the  distance  a  from  the  axis.     But  the  force 
«       which  acts  on  it  is  {m  —  m'^  gy  and  the  ac- 
m      celeration,   consequently,   {m  —  tn' jm  +  w')  g. 
Fig.  167.    Hence,  to  find  the  length  of  the  simple  pen- 
dulum,   having   the   ordinary  acceleration  of 
gravity  gy  which  is  isochronous  with  the  present  pen- 
dulum of  the  length  «,  we  put,  employing  the  preced- 
•      ing  theorem, 

/  g  m-{-  m 

=  ,  ox  l  =  a  -  -       -, 

a       tn  —  ft  I  m  —  m 

m  -\-  m'^ 

The  third  Thirds  we  imagine  a  simple  pendulum  of  length  i 

step,  or  the       .  ,       ,  .  n-»i 

detennina-  With  the  mass  tn  at  its  extremity.  The  weight  of  tn 
centre  of  produces,  by  the  principle  of  the  lever,  the  same  ac- 
celeration as  half  this  force  at  a  distance  2  from  the 
point  of  suspension.  Half  the  mass  m  placed  at  the 
distance  2,  therefore,  would  suffer  by  the  action  of  the 
force  impressed  at  i  the  same  acceleration,  and  a  fourth 
of  the  mass  m  would  suffer  double  the  acceleration  ;  so 
that  a  simple  pendulum  of  the  length  2  having  the  orig- 
inal force  at  distance  i  from  the  point  of  suspension 
and  one-fourth  the  original  mass  at  its  extremity  would 
be  isochronous  with  the  original  one.  Generalising 
this  reasoning,  it  is  evident  that  we  may  transfer  any 
force  /  acting  on  a  compound  pendulum  at  any  dis- 
tance r,  to  the  distance  i  by  making  its  value  r/,  and 
any  and  every  mass  placed  at  the  distance  r  to  the 
distance  i  by  making  its  value  r^m^  without  changing 


gyration. 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.  335 

the  time  of  oscillation  of  the  pendulum.     If  a  force  / 
act  on  a  lever-arm  a  (Fig.  i$8)  while  at  the  distance  r 
from  the  axis  a  mass  m  is  attached,  /  will  be  equiva- 
lent to  a  force  afjr  impressed  on 
m  and  will  impart  to  it  the  linear       ^  ^ 


acceleration  a//m  r  and  the  angu-  ^ 

lar  acceleration  aflmr^.   Hence, 

to  find  the  angular  acceleration 

of  a   compound   pendulum,   we  ^^' ' 

divide  the  sum  of  the-  statical  moments  by  the  sum  of 

the  moments  of  inertia.   .  .  n  ''/  / 

Brook  Taylor,  an  Englishman,*  also  developed  The  re- 

CAar^nAc  of 

this  idea,  on  substantially  the  same  principles,  but  Brook  Tay 
quite  independently  of  John  Bernoulli.     His  solution, 
however,  was  not  published  until  some  time  later,  in 
1 7 15,  in  his  work,  Methodus  Increment  or  um. 

The  above  are  the  most  important  attempts  to  solve 
the  problem  of  the  centre  of  oscillation.  We  shall  see 
that  they  contain  the  very  same  ideas  that  D'Alembert 
enunciated  in  a  generalised  form. 

4.  On  a  system  of  points  J/",  M\  M*\  .  .  .  connected  Motion  of  a 
with  one  another  in  any  way,t  the  forces  P,  F^  F",  .  .  .  pSmTsub- 
are  impressed.     (Fig.  169.)     These  forces  would  im-strainto. 
part  to  Xh^free  points  of  the  system  certain  determinate 
motions.     To  the  connected  points,  however,  different 
motions  are  usually  imparted — motions  which  could 
be  produced  by  the  forces  IV,  W,  IV*\  ,  .  ,    These 
last  are  the  motions  which  we  shall  study. 

Conceive  the  force  F  resolved  into  W  and  V,  the 
force  F'  into  W  and  V\  and  the  force  F"  into  W" 

*  Author  of  Taylor's  theorem,  and  also  of  a  remarkable  work  on  perspec- 
tive.—Traiw. 

t  In  precise  technical  language,  they  are  subject  to  constraints,  that  is. 
forces  regarded  as  infinite,  which  compel  a  certain  relation  between  their 
motions. — TrAn*. 


FiR.  169. 


336  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

Statement  and  V*\  aod  SO  on.     Since,  owing  to  the  connections, 
berfs  prin-  Only  the  Components  W^  W\   W*\  .  .  .   are  effective, 

ciplc* 

therefore,  the  forces  K,  V,  V'\  .  .  .  must  be  equilib- 
rated by  the  connections.  We  will  call  the  forces  P,  P\ 

P"  the    impressed  forces, 

the  forces  M^,  ^,  W^" , 

which  produce  the  ac- 
tual motions,  the  effective 
forces,  and  the  forces  V, 
V\  F" .  .  .  .  the  forces 
gained  and  lost,  or  the 
equilibrated  forces.  We 
perceive,  thus,  that  if  we 
resolve  the  impressed  forces  into  the  effective  forces 
and  the  equilibrated  forces,  the  latter  form  a  system 
balanced  by  the  connections.  This  is  the  principle  of 
D'Alembert.  We  have  allowed  ourselves,  in  its  expo- 
sition, only  the  unessential  modification  of  putting 
forces  for  the  momenta  generated  by  the  forces.  In  this 
form  the  principle  was  stated  by  D'Alembert  in  his 
Traits  de  dynamique J  published  in  1743. 
Various  As  the  system  K,  V\  V*\  ...  is  in  equilibrium,  the 

forms  in  .       .    ,        /     . 

which  the    principle  of  Virtual  displacements  is  applicable  thereto. 

may  be  ex-  This  gives  a  secoud  form  of  D'Alembert*s  principle. 

A  third  form  is  obtained  as  follows  :  The  forces  P,  P* 

are  the  resultants  of  the  components  W,  W\  .  .  .  and 
F,  F'.  .  .  .     If,  therefore,  we  combine  with  the  forces 

W,  W and  V,  V the  forces  — P,  —P' , 

equilibrium  will  obtain.  The  force-system  —  P,  W^  V 
is  in  equilibrium.  But  the  system  V  is  independently 
in  equilibrium.  Therefore,  also  the  system  — /*,  W\% 
in  equilibrium,  or,  what  is  the  same  thing,  the  system 
Py  —  W^  is  in  equilibrium.  Accordingly,  if  the  effective 
forces  with  opposite  signs  be  joined  to  the  impressed 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES. 


337 


Fig.  vjo. 


forces,  the  two,  owing  to  the  connections,  will  balance. 
The  principle  of  virtual  displacements  may  also  be  ap- 
plied to  the  system  Py  —  W,  This  Lagrange  did  in  his 
Mecanique  analytique^  1788. 

The  fact  that  equilibrium  subsists  between  the  sys- 
tem P  and  the  system  —  W^  may  be  expressed  in  still 
another  way.    We  may  say  that 
the  system  ^is  equivalent  to  the         _p 
system  P.     In  this  form  Her-     ' 
MANN  (Phoronotniay    1716)    and 
EuLER  {Comment,  Acad,  Petrop,y 
Old  Series,  Vol.  VII,  1740)  employed  the  principle. 
It  is  substantially  not  different  from  that  of  D*  Alembert. 

5.  We  will  now  illustrate  D'Alembert's  principle  by 
one  or  two  examples. 

On  a  massless  wheel  and  axle  with  the  radii  R^  r  the 
loads  P  and  Q  are  hung,  which  are  not  in  equilibrium. 
We  resolve  the  force  P  into  (i)  W 
(the  force  which  would  produce  the 
actual  motion  of  the  mass  if  this  were 
free)  and  (2)  F,  that  is,  we  put 
P=  W-\r  ^and  also  Q  =  IV' +  F'; 
it  being  evident  that  we  may  here 
neglect  all  motions  that  are  not  in 
the  perponoiculwf.  We  have,  accord- 
ingly, V=P—W  and  F'=  Q  —  W\  ^''^' '''" 
and,  since  the  forces  F,  V  are  in  equilibrium,  also 
V,R=  V\  r.  Substituting  for  V,  V  in  the  last  equa- 
tion their  values  in  the  former,  we  get 


An  equiva- 
lent princi- 
ple em- 
Rloyed  by 
[ermann 
and  Euler. 


Illustration 
of  D'AIem- 
bert'8  prin- 
ciple by  the 
motion  of  a 
wheel  and 
axle. 


{P—  IV)J{  =  {Q—  W')r 


(1) 


which  may  also  be  directly  obtained  by  the  employ- 
ment of  the  second  form  of  D'Alembert's  principle. 
From  the  conditions  of  the  problem  we  readily  perceive 


338  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

that  we  have  here  to  deal  with  a  uniformly  accelerated 
motion,  and  that  all  that  is  therefore  necessary  is  to 
ascertain  the  acceleration.  Adopting  gravitation  meas- 
ure, we  have  the  forces  W  and  W\  which  produce  in 
the  masses  Pjg  and  ^/f  the  accelerations  y  ^^^  y''> 
wherefore,  lV={P/g)y  and  W={Q/g)y\  But  we 
also  know  that  y*=  —  yirjR).  Accordingly,  equation 
(i)  passes  into  the  form 

whence  the  values  of  the  two  accelerations  are  ob- 
tained 

PR—Qr.  ,      ,  PR—Qr 


^       PR^  +  Qr^     ""  ^  PR^  +  Qr^ 

These  last  determine  the  motion. 
Employ-  It  will  be  Seen  at  a  glance  that  the  same  result  can 

ideas  stat-  be  obtained  by  the  employment  of  the  ideas  of  statical 
ment  and    moment  and  moment  of  inertia.  We  get  by  this  method 

moment  of  ,  .  . 

inertia,  to    for  the  angular  acceleration 

obtain  this 

'«*^*-  _    PR—Qr    __^Rj^Qr 

g  g 

and  as  y  =  R<p  and  y'=  —  np^fe,  re-obtain  the  pre- 
ceding expressions. 

When  the  masses  and  forces  are  given,  the  problem 
of  finding  the  motion  of  a  system  is  determinate.  Sup- 
pose, however,  only  the  acceleration  y  is  given  with 
which  P  moves,  and  that  the  problem  is  to  find  the  loads 
P  and  Q  that  produce  this  acceleration.  We  obtain 
easily  from  equation  (2)  the  result  P=  Q{Rg-\-  ry) 
r/{g — y)R^,  that  is,  a  relation  between  /'and  Q. 
One  of  the  two  loads  therefore  is  arbitrary.  The  prob- 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES. 


339 


lem  in  this  form  is  an  indeterminate  one,  and  may  be 
solved  in  an  infinite  number  of  different  ways. 

The  following  may  serve  as  a  second  example. 

A  weight  P  (Fig.  1 72)  free  to  Inove  on  a  vertical  a  second  n 
straight  line  ABy  is  attached  to  a  cord 


CX  A 

©x 


passing  over  a  pulley  and  carrying  a 
weight  Q  at  the  other  end.  The  cord 
makes  with  the  line  AB  the  variable 
angle  or.  The  motion  of  the  present 
case  cannot  be  uniformly  accelerated. 
But  if  we  consider  only  vertical  mo- 
tions we  can  easily  give  for  every 
value  of  a  the  momentary  accelera- 
tion {y  and  ^ ')  oi  P  and  Q.  Proceeding  exactly  as 
we  did  in  the  last  case,  we  obtain 

P=  lV-\-  F, 


r    . 


Fig.  172, 


A 


of  the  prin- 
ciple. 


also 


F'  cos  a  =  F,  or,  since  y'  =  —  ^  cos  or, 

Q  \  P 

Q  +      cos ar^  1  cosor  =  P  —      y;  whence 

6  /  o 


r= 


P  —  Q  cos  a 


g 


y    =  — 


Qcos^a-^-P 
P —  ^  cos  or 


cos  a  g. 


Qcos^a  +  P 

Again  the  same  result  may  be  easily  reached  by  the  solution  of 
employment  of  the  Ideas  of  statical  moment  and  mo-aisoby^Sie 
ment  of  inertia  in  a  more  generalised  form.     The  fol-  statical  mo- 
lowing  reflexion  will  render  this  clear.     The  force,  or  moment  of 
statical  moment,  that  acts  on  P  is  P  —  Q  cos  a.     But  eraiiiSdf*'" 
the  weight  Q  moves  cos  a  times  as  fast  as  P;  conse- 
quently its  mass  is  to  be  taken  cos  ^a  times.     The  ac- 
celeration which  P  receives,  accordingly  is. 


340  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

P —  ^  COS  or  P —  ^cosa 

^"'  ^        \      ~P^ 'Qco^^cr-\-~P  ^' 

g  g 

In  like  manner  the  corresponding  expression  for  y  may 

be  found. 

The  foregoing  procedure  rests  on  the  simple  re- 
mark, that  not  the  circular  path  of  the  motion  of  the 
masses  is  of  consequence,  but  only  the  relative  veloci- 
ties or  relative  displacements.  This  extension  of  the 
concept  moment  of  inertia  may  often  be  employed  to 
advantage. 
Import  and        6.  Now  that  the  application  of  D*Alembert*s  prin- 

character  .    *         ,  .         .  , 

of  D'Aiem-  ciplc  has  been  sufficiently  illustrated,  it  will  not  be  diffi- 

bert'sprizi-       '^  .      "^  .  ' 

cipie.  cult  to  obtain  a  clear  idea  of  its  significance.  Problems 
relating  to  the  motion  of  connected  points  are  here  dis- 
posed of  by  recourse  to  experiences  concerning  the 
mutual  actions  of  connected  bodies  reached  in  the  in- 
vestigation of  problems  of  equilibrium.  Where  the  last 
mentioned  experiences  do  not  su£Bce,  D*Alembert*s 
principle  also  can  accomplish  nothing,  as  the  examples 
adduced  will  amply  indicate.  We  should,  therefore, 
carefully  avoid  the  notion  that  D'Alembert's  principle 
is  a  general  one  which  renders  special  experiences  su- 
perfluous. Its  conciseness  and  apparent  simplicity  are 
wholly  due  to  the  fact  that  it  refers  us  to  experiences 
already  in  our  possession.  Detailed  knowledge  of  the 
subject  under  consideration  founded  on  exact  and  mi- 
nute experience,  cannot  be  dispensed  with.  This  knowl- 
edge we  must  obtain  either  from  the  case  presented, 
by  a  direct  investigation,  or  we  must  previously  have 
obtained  it,  in  the  investigation  of  some  other  subject, 
and  carry  it  with  us  to  the  problem  in  hand.  We  learn, 
in  fact,  from  D'Alembert's  principle,  as  our  examples 
show,  nothing  that  we  could  not  also  have  learned  by 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.         341 

Other  methods.  The  principle  fulfils  in  the  solution 
of  problems,  the  office  of  a  routine-form  which,  to  a 
certain  extent,  spares  us  the  trouble  of  thinking  out 
each  new  case,  by  supplying  directions  for  the  employ- 
ment of  experiences  before  known  and  familiar  to  us. 
The  principle  does  not  so  much  promote  our  insight 
into  the  processes  as  it  secures  us  2i  practical  mastery  of 
them.  The  value  of  the  principle  is  of  an  economical 
character. 

When  we  have  solved  a  problem  by  D'Alembert's  The  reia- 

^  ^  .  tion  of 

principle,  we  may  rest  satisfied  with  the  experiences  D'Aiem- 
previously  made  concerning  equilibrium,  the  applica-  cipie  to  the 
tion  of  which  the  principle  implies.     But  if  we  wish  cipiea  of 

mechanics. 

clearly  and  thoroughly  to  apprehend  the  phenomenon, 
that  is,  to  rediscover  in  it  the  simplest  mechanical  ele- 
ments with  which  we  are  familiar,  we  are  obliged  to 
push  our  researches  further,  and  to  replace  our  expe- 
riences concerning  equilibrium  either  by  the  Newtonian 
or  by  the  Huygenian  conceptions,  in  some  way  similar 
to  that  pursued  on  page  266.  If  we  adopt  the  former 
alternative,  we  shall  mentally  see  the  accelerated  mo- 
tions enacted  which  the  mutual  action  of  bodies  on  one 
another  produces  ;  if  we  adopt  the  second,  we  shall  di- 
rectly contemplate  the  work  done,  on  which,  in  the 
Huygenian  conception,  the  vis  viva  depends.  The  latter 
point  of  view  is  particularly  convenient  if  we  employ 
the  principle  of  virtual  displacements  to  express  the 
conditions  of  equilibrium  of  the  system  V  ox  P  —  W. 
D'Alembert*s  principle  then  asserts,  that  the  sum  of 
the  virtual  moments  of  the  system  V^  or  of  the  system 
P  —  Wy  is  equal  to  zero.  The  elementary  work  of  the 
equilibrated  forces,  if  we  leave  out  of  account  the  strain- 
ing of  the  connections,  is  equal  to  zero.  The  total 
work  done,  then,  is  performed  solely  by  the  system  /*, 


342  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

and  the  work  performed  by  the  system  ^must,  accord- 
ingly, be  equal  to  the  work  done  by  the  system  P.  All 
the  work  that  can  possibly  be  done  is  due,  neglecting 
the  strains  of  the  connections,  to  the  impressed  forces. 
As  will  be  seen,  D'Alembert's  principle  in  this  form  is 
not  essentially  difierent  from  the  principle  of  vis  viva. 
Form  of  ap-  7.  In  practical  applications  of  the  principle  of 
D'Aiem-      D'Alembcrt  it  is  convenient  to  resolve  every  force  P 

bert'sprin-   .  ,  ,    ,  •    .  ,  ., 

cipie,  and    impressed  on  a  mass  m  of  the  system  mto  the  mutually 
inRequa-     perpendicular  components  Xy  V,  Z  parallel  to  the  axes 

tionS  of  mo-  '  . .  rr  ' 

tion.  of  a  system  of  rectangular  coordinates ;  every  effective 

force  ^into  corresponding  components  m^y  mrfy  m^, 
where  S,  ?j,  5  denote  accelerations  in  the  directions  of 
the  coordinates ;  and  every  displacement,  in  a  similar 
manner,  into  three  displacements  Sx^  dy,  dz.  As  the 
work  done  by  each  component  force  is  effective  only  in 
displacements  parallel  to  the  directions  in  which  the 
components  act,  the  equilibrium  of  the  system  (/*, —  W) 
is  given  by  the  equation 

2\(^X^mS)Sx  +  (^V—mrf)dy+{Z—m^6z\  =  0  (1) 

or 

2(,X6x  +  VSy  +  ZSz)  =  2m(S6x+f^6y+^6z).   .   (2) 

These  two  equations  are  the  direct  expression  of  the 
proposition  above  enunciated  respecting  the  possible 
work  of  the  impressed  forces.  If  this  work  be  =  0,  the 
particular  case  of  equilibrium  results.  The  principle 
of  virtual  displacements  flows  as  a  special  case  from 
this  expression  of  D'Alembert's  principle ;  and  this  is 
quite  in  conformity  with  reason^  since  in  the  general 
as  well  as  in  the  particular  case  the  experimental  per- 
ception of  the  import  of  work  is  the  sole  thing  of  con- 
sequence. 

Equation  (i)  gives  the  requisite  equations  of  mo- 


THE  RXTENSfON  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.         343 

tion ;  we  have  simply  to  express  as  many  as  possible 
of  the  displacements  Sx^  dy,  Sz  by  the  others  in  terms 
of  their  relations  to  the  latter,  and  put  the  coefficients 
of  the  remaining  arbitrary  displacements  =  0,  as  was 
illustrated  in  our  applications  of  the  principle  of  vir- 
tual displacements. 

The  solution  of  a  very  few  problems  by  D'Alem-  conve- 

...  •if/v*  •  "irii  oicnce  and 

bert  s  pnnciple  will  sumce  to  impress  us  with  a  full  atiiity  of 
sense  of  its  convenience.     It  will  also  give  us  the  con-  bert's  pnn- 

ciplc. 

viction  that  it  is  possible,  in  every  case  in  which  it  may 
be  found  necessary,  to  solve  directly  and  with  perfect 
insight  the  very  same  problem  by  a  consideration  of 
elementary  mechanical  processes,  and  to  arrive  thereby 
at  exactly  the  same  results.  Our  conviction  of  the 
feasibility  of  this  operation  renders  the  performance  of 
it,  in  cases  in  which  purely  practical  ends  are  in  view, 
unnecessary* 

VI. 
THE  PRINCIPLE  OF  VIS  VIVA. 

I.  The  principle  of  ins  viva,  as  we  know,  was  first  The  oiifc- 
employed  by  Huvgens.    John  and  Daniel  Bernoulli  icarform  of 
had  simply  to  provide  for  a  greater  generality  of  ex-  cipief"* 

pression ;  they  added  little.   If  /,  /,/" are  weights, 

niy  m\  m".  .  .  .  their  respective  masses,  A,  h\  K\  .  .  .  the 
distances  of  descent  of  the  free  or  connected  masses, 
and  r,  v\  v".  .  .  .  the  velocities  acquired,  the  relation 
obtains 

If  the  initial  velocities  are  not  =  0,  but  are  v^,  v^, 
v^\  .  .  .,  the  theorem  will  refer  to  the  increment  of  the 
7)is  viva  by  the  work  and  read 

:Sph  =  :^:Sm[v^  —  v^^), 


344 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 


Theprinci-        The  principle  still  remains  applicable  when  / .  .  .  . 

pie  applied  •    i  « 

to  forces  of  are,  not  weights,  but  any  constant  forces,  and  A .  .  . 
not  the  vertical  spaces  fallen  through,  but  any  paths  in 
the  lines  of  the  forces.  If  the  forces  considered  are 
variable,  the  expressions /^, /'^'.  .  .  .  must  be  replaced 
by  the  expressions  Cp  ds^  Cp'  ds* .  .  .  . ,  in  which  /  de- 
notes the  variable  forces  and  ds  the  elements  of  dis- 
tance described  in  the  lines  of  the  forces.     Then 


The  princi- 
ple illus- 
trated hy 
the  motion 
of  a  wheel 
and  axle. 


or 


^Jpds  =  ^2m(j)^  —  rj^) 


(1) 


2.   In  illustration  of  the  principle  of  vts  viva  we 
shall  first  consider  the  simple  problem  which  we  treated 

by  the  principle  of  D'Alembert.  On 
a  wheel  and  axle  with  the  radii  R,  r 
hang  the  weights  P^  Q.  When  this 
machine  is  set  in  motion,  work  is  per- 
formed by  which  the  acquired  vis  viva 
is  fully  determined.  For  a  rotation  of 
the  machine  through  the  angle  or,  the 
work  is 

P,Ra—Q.  ra  =  a{PR  —  Qr), 
Calling   the    angular   velocity  which 
corresponds  to  this  angle  of  rotation,  ^,  the  vis  viva 
generated  will  be 

Consequently,  the  equation  obtains 


Fig.  173. 


^> 


2 


a(PR  -  Qr)  =  T^-  {PJi^  +  Qr^) 


(1) 


Now  the  motion  of  this  case  is  a  uniformly  accelerated 
motion ;  consequently,  the  same  relation  obtains  here 
between  the  angle  a,  the  angular  velocity  ^,  and  the 


N. 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES. 


345 


angular  acceleration  ^%  as  obtains  in  free  descent  be- 
tween X,  7/,  g.     If  in  free  descent  s  =  v^  /2gy  then  here 

Introducing  this  value  of  a  in  equation  (i),  we  get 
for  the  angular  acceleration  of  P^  ^  =  (-P^ — Qr/ 
m^  -j-  Qr^)g,  and,  consequently,  for  its  absolute  ac- 
celeration y  =  {FR^^QrlPR'^  +  ~Qr'^)  Rg,  exactly  as 
in  the  previous  treatment  of  the  problem. 

As  a  second  example  let  us  consider  the  case  of  a  a  rpiiinR 

.  ,  cylinder  on 

massless  cylinder  of  radius  r,  in  the  surface  of  which,  an  inclined 

plane. 

diametrically  opposite  each  other,  are  fixed  two  equal 
masses  m,  and  which  in  consequence  of  the  weight  of 


Fig.  174. 

these  masses  rolls  without  sliding  down  an  inclined 
plane  of  the  elevation  or.  First,  we  must  convince  our- 
selves, that  in  order  to  represent  the  total  vis  viva  of 
the  system  we  have  simply  to  sum  up  the  vis  viva  of 
the  motions  of  rotation  and  progression.  The  axis  of 
the  cylinder  has  acquired,  we  will  say,  the  velocity  u 
in  the  direction  of  the  length  of  the  inclined  plane,  and 
we  will  denote  by  v  the  absolute  velocity  of  rotation  of 
the  surface  of  the  cylinder.  The  velocities  of  rotation  v 
of  the  two  masses  ni  make  with  the  velocity  of  progres- 
sion u  the  angles  B  and  d*  (Fig.  175),  where  6^-1-  6^' 
=  i8o^  The  compound  velocities  w  and  z  satisfy 
therefore  the  equations 

W'  =  «2  _j_  ^2  —  2uvcosB 

«a  =«2  +  z;a  —  2uvcosd', 


346  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

The  law  of         But  since  COS  6  =  —  COS  S'y  it  follows  that 

motion  of 

If  the  cylinder  moves  through  the  angle  <p,  m  describes 
in  consequence  of  the  rotation  the  space  r  q>y  and  the 
axis  of  the  cylinder  is  likewise  displaced  a  distance  r<p. 
As  the  spaces  traversed  are  to  each  other,  so  also 
are  the  velocities  v  and  «,  which  therefore  are  equal. 
The  total  vis  viva  may  accordingly  be  expressed  by 
2«r//2.  If /is  the  distance  the  cylinder  travels  along 
the  length  of  the  inclined  plane,  the  work  done  is 
2»i^. /sinar  =  2/^«2j  whence  «  =  v/^/.  sin  or.  If  we 
compare  with  this  result  the  velocity  acquired  by  a  body 
in  sliding  down  an  inclined  plane,  namely,  the  velocity 
V  7,gl  sin^,  it  will  be  observed  that  the  contrivance  we 
are  here  considering  moves  with  only  one-half  the  ac- 
celeration of  descent  that  (friction  neglected)  a  sliding 
body  would  under  the  same  circumstances.  The  rea- 
soning of  this  case  is  not  altered  if  the  mass  be  uni- 
formly distributed  over  the  entire  surface  of  the  cylin- 
der. Similar  considerations  are  applicable  to  the  case 
of  a  sphere  rolling  down  an  inclined  plane.  It  will  be 
seen,  therefore,  that  Galileo's  experiment  on  falling 
bodies  is  in  need  of  a  quantitative  correction. 
A  modifica-  Ncxt,  let  US  distribute  the  mass  m  uniformly  over 
preceding   the  surface  of  a  cylinder  of  radius  R^  which  is  coaxal 

case* 

with  and  rigidly  joined  to  a  massless  cylinder  of  radius 
r,  and  let  the  latter  roll  down  the  inclined  plane.  Since 
here  vfu  =  R/r,  the  principle  of  vis  viva  gives  mgl 
sina  =  ^mu^(l  +  R^/r^),  whence 

2g/  sin  a 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.  347 

For  Rjr  =  i  the  acceleration  of  descent  assumes  its 
previous  value  gji.     For  very  large  values  of  Rjr  the 
acceleration  of  descent  is  very  small.  When  Rjr  =  00 
it  will  be  impossible  for  the  machine  to  roll  down  the 
inclined  plane  at  all. 

As  a  third  example,  we  will  consider  the  case  of  a  The  motion 

.  .  of  a  chain 

chain,  whose  total  length  is  /,  and  which  lies  partly  on  on  an  in- 
a  horizontal  plane  and  partly  on  a  plane  having  the  plane, 
angle  of  elevation  a.     If  we  imagine  the  surface  on 
which     the     chain 
rests    to    be    very 
smooth,    any   very 
small     portion     of 
the  chain  left  hang- 

.        .  Fig.  176. 

mg  over  on  the  m- 

clined  plane  will  draw  the  remainder  after  it.  If  /i  is 
the  mass  of  unit  of  length  of  the  chain  and  a  portion  x 
is  hanging  over,  the  principle  of  vis  viva  will  give  for 
the  velocity  v  acquired  the  equation 


ixlv'^  X     .  X 


2 


or  V  =^x\/ g  ^v^oLJL  In  the  present  case,  therefore, 
the  velocity  acquired  is  proportional  to  the  space  de- 
scribed. The  very  law  holds  that  Galileo  first  con- 
jectured was  the  law  of  freely  falling  bodies.  The 
same  reflexions,  accordingly,  are  admissible  here  as  at 
page  248. 

3.   Equation  (i),  the  equation  of  vis  viva,  can  always  Extension 
be  employed,  to  solve  problems  of  moving  bodies,  dpie%?"?i 
when  the  total  distance  traversed  and  the  force  that*"*"*' 
acts  in  each  element  of  the  distance  are  known.   It  was 
disclosed,  however,  by  the  labors  of  Euler,  Daniel  Ber- 
noulli, and  Lagrange,  that  cases  occur  in  which  the 


348  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

principle  of  vis  viva  can  be  employed  without  a  knowl- 
edge of  the  actual  path  of  the  motion.     We  shall  see 
later  on  that  Clairaut  also  rendered  Important  services 
in  this  field, 
inen-  Galileo,  even,  knew  that  the  velocity  of  a  heavy 

Enier.        falling  body  depended  solely  on  the  vertical  height  de- 
scended through,  and  not  on  the  length  ox/orm  of  the 
path  traversed.     Similarly,  Hu)^ens  finds  that  the  vis 
viva  of  a  heavy  material  system  is  dependent  on  the 
vertical  heights  of  the  masses  of 
the  system.    Euler  was  able  to 
make  a  further  step  in  advance. 
If  a  body  K  (Fig.   177)  is  at- 
tracted towards  a  fixed  centre 
C  in  obedience  to  some  given 
law,  the  increase  of  the  vis  viva 
in    the  case  of    rectilinear  ap- 
proach is   calculable  from  the 
initial  and    terminal    distances 
pj^  ,^_  (r^,  r,).    But  the  increase  is  the 

same,  if  ^passes  at  all  from  the 
position  fg  to  the  position  r„  independently  of  the 
form  of  its  path,  KB.  For  the  elements  of  the  work 
done  must  be  calculated  from  the  projections  on  the 
radius  of  the  actual  displacements,  and  are  thus  ulti- 
mately the  same  as  before. 
Tiie  te-  UK  is  attracted  towards  several  fixed  centres  C, 

Daniel  Ber-  C,  C".  .  ,  ,,  the  increase  of  its  vis  viva  depends  on  the 

noulUBnd     ...,,.  ,         „  ,  .  -       , 

Lagrange,  initial  distances  r^,  r^,  r^  .  .  .  .  and  on  the  terminal 
distances  r„  r,',  r".  .  .  .,  that  is  on  the  initial  and  \x^t- 
rciYRsX  positions  of  K.  Daniel  Bernoulli  extended  this 
idea,  and  showed  further  that  where  movable  bodies 
are  in  a  state  of  mutual  attraction  the  change  of  I'is  viva 
is  determined  solely  by  their  initial  and  terminal  dis- 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.         349 

tances  from  one  another.  The  analytical  treatment  of 
these  problems  was  perfected  by  Lagrange.  If  we  join 
a  point  having  the  coordinates  a,  by  c  with  a  point  hav- 
ing the  coordinates  x^  y,  z,  and  denote  by  r  the  length 
of  the  line  of  junction  and  by  a,  /3,  y  the  angles  that 
line  makes  with  the  axes  of  x,  y,  z,  then,  according  to 
Lagrange,  because 

ra  =  (j^  —  «)»  +  Cr  —  by  +  {z  —  cY, 

X  —  a       dr           -       y  —  b       dr 
cosa  = = -^   ,cosp=    =-^f 

r  dx  r  dy 

z  —  c      dr 

cos  Y  =ae =:  — -. 

'  r  dz 

Accordingly,  it/(r)  =  — -^-J-  is  the  repulsive  force,  or  The  force 

af  compo- 

nents, par- 

the  negative  of  the  attractive  force  acting  between  the  tiai  diser- 

.  ential  coef- 

two  points,  the  components  will  be  fidentsof 

the  same 

•^  ^  ^  dr     dx  dx  "^^•«- 

y=/(r)cos^  =  -^-^^^=-^^-^ 

_        . ,  ^      *  dF{r)  dr      dF{f) 

Z  =/{r)  cosy  =      ,^^  -,-  =     -,- -. 
"^  ^  ^        '^  dr     dz  dz 

The  force-components,  therefore,  are  the  partial' 
difierential  coefficients  of  one  and  the  same  function  of 
r,  or  of  the  coordinates  of  the  repelling  or  attracting 
points.     Similarly,  if  several  points  are  in  mutual  ac- 
tion, the  result  will  be 

dx 
dU 
~  dy 
^_dU 
dz' 


350  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

The  force-  wherc  6^  is  a  function  of  the  coordinates  of  the  points. 
This  function  was  subsequently  called  by  Hamilton* 
the  force-function. 

Transforming,  by  means  of  the  conceptions  here 
reached,  and  under  the  suppositions  given,  equation 
(i)  into  a  form  applicable  to  rectangular  coordinates, 
we  obtain 

^C{Xdx  +  Ydy  +  Zdz)  =  2\m{v^  —  v,^)  or, 

since  the  expression  to  the  left  is  a  complete  differen- 
tial, 

2JdU=2(,U,—  U:)  =  2im(^v^  —  v^^), 

where  C/^  is  a  function  of  the  terminal  values  and  ^ 
the  same  function  of  the  initial  values  of  the  coordi- 
nates. This  equation  has  received  extensive  applica- 
tions, but  it  simply  expresses  the  knowledge  that  under 
the  conditions  designated  the  work  done  and  therefore 
also  the  vis  viva  of  a  system  is  dependent  on  the  posi- 
tions^ or  the  coordinates,  of  the  bodies  constituting  it. 
If  we  imagine  all  masses  fixed  and  only  a  single 
one  in  motion,  the  work  changes  only  as  U  changes. 
The  equation  6^=  (constant  defines  a  so-called  level 
surface,  or  surface  of  equal  work.  Movement  upon 
such  a  surface  produces  no  work.  U  increases  in  the 
direction  in  which  the  forces  tend  to  move  the  bodies. 

VII. 

THE  PRINCIPLE  OF  LEAST  CONSTRAINT. 

I.  Gauss  enunciated  (in  Cxe\\e*s  Journal fUr  Mathe^ 
matikj  Vol.  IV,  1829,  p.  233)  a  new  law  of  mechanics, 
the  principle  of  least  constraint.     He  observes,  that,  in 

*  On  a  General  Method  in  Dynamics,  PhiL  Trans,  for  1834.    See  also  C.  G. 
J.  Jacobi,  VorUsungen  Uber  Dynamik^  edited  by  Clebsch,  1866. 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.  351 

the  form  which  mechanics  has  historically  assumed,  dy-  History  of 
namics  is  founded  upon  statics,  (for  example,  D'Alem-  pie  of  least 
bert's  principle  on  the  principle  of  virtual  displace- 
ments,) whereas  one  naturally  would  expect  that  in 
the  highest  stage  of  the  science  statics  would  appear 
as  a  particular  case  of  dynamics.  Now,  the  principle 
which  Gauss  supplied,  and  which  we  shall  discuss  in 
this  section,  includes  both  dynamical  and  statical  cases. 
It  meets,  therefore,  the  requirements  of  scientific  and 
logical  aesthetics.  We  have  already  pointed  out  that  this 
is  also  true  of  D'Alembert's  principle  in  its  Lagrangian 
form  and  the  mode  of  expression  above  adopted. 
No  essentially  new  principle ^  Gauss  remarks,  can  now  be 
established  in  mechanics ;  but  this  does  not  exclude 
the  discovery  of  new  points  of  view,  from  which  mechan- 
ical  phenomena  may  be  fruitfully  contemplated.  Such 
a  new  point  of  view  is  afforded  by  the  principle  of 
Gauss. 

2.  Let  m,  >»,....  be  masses,  connected  in  any  man-  statement 
ner  with  one  another.  These  masses,  if/r^^,  would,  under  cipie. 
the  action  of  the  forces  im- 
pressed on  them,  describe  in  a 
very  short  element  of  time  the 
spaces  a  b,  a,  bf ,  ,  .  ,\  but  in 
consequence  of  their  connec- 
tions they  describe  in  the  same 
element  of  time  the  spaces  a  r, 

tff  r/.  .  .  .  Now,  Gauss's  principle  asserts,  that  the  mo- 
tion of  the  connected  points  is  such  that,  for  the  motion 
actually  taken,  the  sum  of  the  products  of  the  mass  of 
each  material  particle  into  the  square  of  the  distance  of 
its  deviation  from  the  position  it  would  have  reached  if 
free,  namely  »i(^r)2  -|-  m,\b'y,y  -f  .  .  .  .=  2m{bcyy  is 
a  minimum,  that  is,  is  smaller  for  the  actual  motion 


352  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

than  for  any  other  conceivable  motion  in  the  same  con- 
flections.     If  this  sum,  2m(Jfc)^f   is  less  for  rest  than 
for  any  motion,  equilibrium  will  obtain.   The  principle 
includes,  thus,  both  statical  and  dynamical  cases. 
Definition         The  sum  2 m(fie)^  is  called  the  "constraint.***    In 

of  "con-  ,  ^  , 

straint."  formmg  this  sum  it  is  plain  that  the  velocities  present 
in  the  system  may  be  neglected,  as  the  relative  posi- 
tions of  a,  d,  c  are  not  altered  by  them. 

3.  The  new  principle  is  equivalent  to  that  of 
D' Alembert ;  it  may  be  used  in  place  of  the  latter ;  and, 
as  Gauss  has  shown,  can  also  be  deduced  from  it.  The 
impressed  forces  carry  the  free  mass  m  in  an  element  of 
time  through  the  space  a  by  the  effective  forces  carry  the 
same  mass  in  the  same  time  in  consequence  of  the  con- 
nections through  the  space  a  c.    We  resolve  a  b  into  a  c 

and  cb\  and  do  the  same  for  all  the 
masses.     It  is   thus  evident  that 
forces  corresponding  to  the   dis- 
tances c  bf  Cfbf  ,  ,  ,  ,   and  propor- 
tional thereto,  do  not,  owing  to  the 
connections,  become  effective,  but 
form  with  the  connections  an  equilibrating  system.    If, 
accordingly,  we  erect  at  the  terminal  positions  c,  c„ 
c,,  ..  .  .  the  virtual  displacements  cy,  c,y, .  .  .  ,,  form- 
ing with  cb,  c,b,  ,  ,  .  .  the  angles  0,  0,  ,  ,  .  ,  we  may 
apply,  since  by  D'Alembert's  principle  forces  propor- 
tional to  cby  c,bf  ,  .  ,  ,  are  here  in  equilibrium,  the 
principle  of  virtual  velocities.   Doing  so,  we  shall  have 

*  Professor  Mach's  term  is  Abwetchun^ssumme.  The  AdweicAung-  is  the 
declination  or  departure  from  free  motion,  called  by  Gauss  the  Ablenkung. 
(See  DQhring,  Principien  der  Mechanik^  KS  168,  169 ;  Routh,  Rigid  Dynamics^ 
Part  I,  II  390-394.)  The  quantity  2  m  {bc)9  is  called  by  Gauss  the  Zwang;  and 
German  mathematicians  usually  follow  this  practice.  In  English,  the  term 
constraint  is  established  in  this  sense,  although  it  is  also  used  with  another* 
hardly  quantitative  meaning,  for  the  force  which  restricts  a  body  absolutely 
to  moving  in  a  certain  way. — Trans, 


THE  EX  TENS  10 ^r  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.         353 

"Zcb  ,  CY  CO%B^^ (l')Thc  dednc- 

'^  ^  ^   ^  tion  of  the 

But  principle 

of  least 

{byy  =  {bey  +  {Cyy  —2bc,CyCOSe,  constraint, 

IPyY  —  \bcy  =(cyy  —  2bc.cycose,  and 
2m{byy—2m{bcy=2m{cyy—22mbc.cycose(2) 

Accordingly,  since  by  (i)  the  second  member  of 
the  right-hand  side  of  (2)  can  only  be  =  0  or  negative, 
that  is  to  say,  as  the  sum  2m(cyy  can  never  be  dimin- 
ished by  the  subtraction,  but  only  increased,  therefore 
the  left-hand  side  of  (2)  must  also  always  be  positive 
and  consequently  2m(byy  always  greater  than  2  m 
{bey,  which  is  to  say,  every  conceivable  constraint 
from  unhindered  motion  is  greater  than  the  constraint 
for  the  actual  motion. 

4.  The  declination,  be,  for  the  very  small  element  various 

r  •       1  1      forms  in 

of  time  r,  may,  for  purposes  of  practical  treatment,  be  which  the 
designated  by  j,  and  following  Scheffler  (Schlomilch's  may  be  ex- 
Zeitschrift  fiir  Mathematik  und  Physik,  1858,  Vol.  Ill, 
p.  197),  we  may  remark  that  s  =  yr^  ji,  where  y  de- 
notes acceleration.     Consequently,  2ms^  may  also  be 
expressed  in  the  forms 

2 

where/  denotes  the  force  that  produces  the  declination 
from  free  motion.  As  the  constant  factor  in  no  wise 
affects  the  minimum  condition,  we  may  say,  the  actual 
motion  is  always  such  that 

2ms^ (1) 

or 

2P^ (2) 

or 

2my^ (3) 

is  a  minimum. 


2m,s,s  =  ^^-2my,s=     -2p.s=       2my^^ 


354 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 


The  motion 
of  a  wheel 
and  axle. 


5.  We  will  first  employ,  in  our  illustrations,  the 
third  form.  Here  again,  as  our  first  example,  we  se- 
lect the  motion  of  a  wheel  and  axle  by 
the  overweight  of  one  of  its  parts 
and  shall  use  the  designations  above 
frequently  employed.  Our  problem 
is,  to  so  determine  the  actual  accel- 
erations   y  ol  P  and  y,  of  Q,  that 

i^U)  U  -  yy  +  ^Q/g)  U  -  YfY 

shall  be  a  minimum,  or,  since  y,  = 
—  yir/R),    so    that    P  {g  —  yy  + 

Qis  +  Y'^/-^^  =  ^  shall  assume  its  smallest  value. 

Putting,  to  this  end. 


Fig.  i8a 


we  get  y  =  {^PR—  Qr/PR^  +  Qr^)Rg,  exactly  as  in 
the  previous  treatments  of  the  problem. 
Descent  on        As  our  secoud  example,  the  motion  of  descent  on 
plane.        ^^  inclined  plane  may  be  taken.    In  this  case  we  shall 

employ  the  first  form,  2ms^. 
Since  we  have  here  only  to 
deal  with  one  mass,  our  in- 
quiry will  be  directed  to  find- 
ing that  acceleration  of  de- 
scent y  for  the  plane  by 
which  the  square  of  the  de- 
clination (j^)  is  made  a  minimum.  By  Fig.  181  we 
have 

and  putting  d(^s^)/dy  =  0,  we  obtain,  omitting  all 
constant  factors,  2y —  2^  sin  or  =  0  or  y  =  g.  sin  or,  the 
familiar  result  of  Galileo's  researches. 


Fig.  x8x. 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES, 


355 


4J 


JiL 


i 


Fig.  182. 


The  following  example  will  show  that  Gauss's  prin-  a  case  of 
ciple  also  embraces  cases  of  equilibrium.  On  the  arms  num. 
a,  a'  of  a  lever  (Fig.  182)  are  hung  the  heavy  masses 
m,  m\  The  principle  requires  that  m(^g — y)^ -{■ 
m'(jr  —  y ')a  shall  be  a  minimum.  But  y'=  —  y(a'/a). 
Further,  if  the  masses  are  in- 
versely ^  proportional  to  the 
lengths  of  the  lever-arms,  that 
is  to  say,  if  m/m'  =  a' /a,  then 
y'  =  —  y  (, m/m ' ).  Conse- 
quently, m{g  —  y)  *  +  m\g  +  y  •  fft/m)^  =  N  must 
be  made  a  minimum.  Putting  dNjdy  =  0,  we  get 
m{i  -\-  m/m')y  =  0  or  y  =  0.  Accordingly,  in  this  case 
equiiibrium  presents  the  least  constraint  from  free  mo- 
tion. 

Every  new  cause  of  constraint,  or  restriction  upon  New  caasea 
the  freedom  of  motion,  increases  the  quantity  of  con-  straint  in- 

,  ,  crease  tho 

Straint,  but  the  increase  is  always  the  least  possible,  deparmre 

from  free 

If  two  or  more  systems  be  connected,  the  motion  of  motion, 
least  constraint  from  the  motions  of  the  unconnected 
systems  is  the  actual  motion. 

If,  for  example,  we  join  together  several  simple 
pendulums  so  as  to  form  a  compound  linear  pendulum, 
the  latter  will  oscillate  with  the  motion 
of  least  constraint  from  the  motion  of  the 
single  pendulums.  The  simple  pendulum, 
for  any  excursion  a,  receives,  in  the  di- 
rection  of    its   path,    the   acceleration  g 
sin  or.    Denoting,  therefore   by  y  sin  a  the 
acceleration  corresponding  to  this  excur- 
sion at  the  axial  distance  i  on  the  com- 
pound pendulum,  2m  (g  sin  a  —  rysina)^  or  2m  (g  — 
ry)^  will  be  the  quantity  to  be  made  a  minimum.  Conse- 
quently, 2m(^g — ry)r  =  0,  and  y  =  g(2mr/2mr^). 


Fig.  183. 


356 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 


The  problem  is  thus  disposed  of  in  the  simplest  man- 
ner. But  this  simple  solution  is  possible  only  because 
the  experiences  that  Huygens,  the  Bemoullis,  and  oth- 
ers long  before  collected,  are  implicitly  contained  in 
Gauss's  principle, 
iiiustra-  6.  The  increase  of  the  quantity  of  constraint,  or 

preceding   declination,  from  free  motion  by  new  causes  of  con- 
straint may  be  exhibited  by  the  following  examples. 

Over  two  stationary  pulleys  A^  B^  and  beneath  a 
movable  pulley  C  (Fig.  184),  a  cord  is  passed,  each 


TBwff? 


Fig.  184. 

extremity  of  which  is  weighted  with  a  load  P\  and  on 
C  a  load  7,P  -f  /  is  placed.  The  movable  pulley  will 
now  descend  with  the  acceleration  (J>/\P  +  /)  g*  But 
if  we  make  the  pulley  A  fast,  we  impose  upon  the 
system  a  new  cause  of  constraint,  and  the  quantity  of 
constraint,  or  declination,  from  free  motion  will  be  in- 
creased. The  load  suspended  from  B,  since  it  now 
moves  with  double  the  velocity,  must  be  reckoned  as 
possessing  four  times  its  original  mass.  The  mova- 
ble pulley  accordingly  sinks  with  the  acceleration 
{p/^P  +  p)g'  A  simple  calculation  will  show  that  the 
constraint  in  the  latter  case  is  greater  than  in  the  former. 


1 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES, 


357 


A  number,  «,  of  equal  weights,  /,  lying  on  a  smooth 
horizontal  surface,  are  attached  to  n  small  movable 
pulleys  through  which  a  cord  is  drawn  in  the  manner 
indicated  in  the  figure  and  loaded  at  its  free  extremity 
with  /.  According  as  all  the  pulleys  are  movable  or  all 
except  one  zx^fixedy  we  obtain  for  the  motive  weight/, 
allowing  for  the  relative  velocities  of  the  masses  as  re- 
ferred to  /,  respectively,  the  accelerations  (4  «/i  +  4«)^ 
and  (4/5)  g'  If  all  the  «  +  i  masses  are  movable,  the 
deviation  assumes  the  value/^/4«  +  i,  which  increases 
as  n,  the  number  of  the  movable  masses,  is  decreased. 


V 

w        ^^ 

u 

.^^ 

^ 

Fig.  186. 

7.   Imagine  a  body  of  weight  Q,  movable  on  rollers  Treatment 

of  A  me* 

on  a  horizontal  surface,  and  having  an  inclined  plane  chanicai 

problein  by 

face.     On  this  inclined  face  a  body  of  weight  P  isdiflferent 

.  mechanical 

placed.  We  now  perceive  instinctively  that  P  will  de-  principles, 
scend  with  quicker  acceleration  when  Q  is  movable 
and  can  give  way,  than  it  will  when  Q  is  fixed  and  /"s 
descent  more  hindered.  To  any  distance  of  descent  h 
of  jP  a  horizontal  velocity  v  and  a  vertical  velocity  u  of 
P  and  a  horizontal  velocity  w  ot  Q  correspond.  Owing 
to  the.  conservation  of  the  quantity  of  horizontal  mo- 
tion, (for  here  only  internal  forces  act,)  we  have  Pv  = 
Qw,  and  for  obvious  geometrical  reasons  (Fig.  186) 

also 

u  =  (v  -{-  w)  tan  a 

The  velocities,  consequently,  are 


u^=u 


358  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

Q 
First,  by  the  7;=   ^  ^-     -COtOT.  », 

principles  ■«     "f'  C: 

of  the  con- 
servation  of  p 

viva.  ■'     ~r  ^ 

For  the  work  Fh  performed,  the  principle  of  vis 
viva  gives 

_^       Pu^       P(      Q  \^«^    . 

2^2 


cot 


«)■ 


Multiplying  by  — ,  we  obtain 

J       (^    ,     _Q cos^aN  »a 

To  find  the  vertical  acceleration  y  with  which  the 
space  h  is  described,  be  it  noted  that  h=:u^ /2  y.  In- 
troducing this  value  in  the  last  equation,  we  get 

_(P+  0sin»a 

For  Q  =  00,  y  =g sin  ^  a,  the  same  as  on  a  sta- 
tionary inclined  plane.  For  Q  =  0,  y  =g,  as  in  free 
descent.     For  finite  values  of  Q  =  mP,y/e  get, 

1  -\-  PI  , 

smce  -.-_         —  >  1, 
sm^a  -f-  m 

(1  +  m)sin^a  .   „ 

The  making  of  Q  stationary,  being  a  newly  imposed 
cause  of  constraint,  accordingly  increases  the  quantity 
of  constraint,  or  declination,  from  free  motion. 

To  obtain  y,  in  this  case,  we  have  employed  the 
principle  of  the  conservation  of  momentum  and  the 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.         359 

principle  of  vis  viva.     Employing  Gauss's  principle,  Second,  by 
we  should  proceed  as  follows.     To  the  velocities  de-  cipie  of 

Gauss. 

noted  as  »,  v^  w  the  accelerations  y^  ^>  ^  correspond. 
Remarking  that  in  the  free  state  the  only  acceleration 
is  the  vertical  acceleration  of  jP,  the  others  vanishing, 
the  procedure  required  is,  to  make 

P  P  O 

a  minimum.  As  the  problem  possesses  significance 
only  when  the  bodies  P  and  Q  touch,  that  is  only  when 
y  =  ((J  -j-  £)  tan  or,  therefore,  also 

Forming  the  differential  coefficients  of  this  expression 
with  respect  to  the  two  remaining  independent  vari- 
ables 6  and  f,  and  putting  each  equal  to  zero,  we  ob- 
tain 

_  \g—{d  +  €)  tana]  Ptantf  +  P6  =  ^  and 

From  these  two  equations  follows  immediately 
P6 —  ^€  =  0,  and,  ultimately,  the  same  value  for  y 
that  we  obtained  before. 

We  will  now  look  at  this  problem  from  another 
point  of  view.  The  body  P  describes  at  an  angle  § 
with  the  horizon  the  space  s,  of  which  the  horizontal 
and  vertical  components  are  v  and  1/,  while  simulta- 
neously Q  describes  the  horizontal  distance  w.  The 
force-component  that  acts  in  the  direction  of  s  is  jPsin  §y 
consequently  the  acceleration  in  this  direction,  allow- 
ing for  the  relative  velocities  of  P  and  Q,  is 

/^.sin/? 


36o  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

m 

Third,  by  Employing  the  following  equations  which  are  di- 

tended  con-  rectly  deducible, 

cept  of  mo- 

ment  of  in-  Qw  =  Pv 

ertia. 

V  =^  S  COS  fS 

u=^v  tan  ft, 

the  acceleration  in  the  direction  of  s  becomes 

Qsmft 

and  the  vertical  acceleration  corresponding  thereto  is 

^  '^'Q'+Pcos^'  ^' 

an  expression,  which  as  soon  as  we  introduce  by  means 
of  the  equation  «  =  (z;  -(-  w)  tan  or,  the  angle-func- 
tions of  a  for  those  of  ft,  again  assumes  the  form  above 
given.  By  means  of  our  extended  conception  of  mo- 
ment of  inertia  we  reach,  accordingly,  the  same  result 
as  before. 
Fourth,  b^  Finally  we  will  deal  with  this  problem  in  a  direct 
cip?es.^""  manner.  The  body  P  does  not  descend  on  the  mova- 
ble inclined  plane  with  the  vertical  acceleration  g,  with 
which  it  would  fall  if  free,  but  with  a  different  vertical 
acceleration,  y.  It  sustains,  therefore,  a  vertical  coun- 
terforce  {P/g){g — y)-  But  as  P  and  Q,  friction 
neglected,  can  only  act  on  each  other  by  means  of  a 
pressure  S,  normal  to  the  inclined  plane,  therefore 

P 

—  {g —  y)  =  Scosa  and 

o 

0       P 

5sin  a  =  --  f  ==  -  6, 
g  g 

From  this  is  obtained 

-(g—y)  =  j€cota, 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.         361 

and  by  means  of  the  equation  ^  ==  (tf  -[-  0  ^^^  ^»  ^^^' 
mately,  as  before, 

(/'+  0sin2a 


PsvQ^a-^  Q 


g (1) 


^^sinacosor 

Psm^a^  <2       

P  sin  or  cos  or  ,^ 

*'~?sin2a+  e^ ^  ^ 

If  we  put  P  ^=^  Q  and  or  =  45°,  we  obtain  for  this  Discusaion 
*^  ^  ^•^  of  the  re- 

particular  case  y  =  ^^,  6  =  ^gf  €z=^g.     For  P/g  =  suiu. 

Q/g=  I  we  find  the  ** constraint,* 'or  declination  from 

free  motion,  to  be  ^  ^  73.    If  we  make  the  inclined  plane 

stationary,  the  constraint  will  be  g^/2.   If  -Amoved  on 

a   stationary   inclined    plane  of    elevation   /3,    where 

tan  /3  =  y/d,  that  is  to  say,  in  the  same  path  in  which 

it  moves  on  the  movable  inclined  plane,  the  constraint 

would  only  be  ^2/5.     And,  in  that  case  it  would,  in 

reality,  be  less  impeded  than  if  it  attained  the  same 

acceleration  by  the  displacement  of  Q. 

8.  The  examples  treated  will  have  convinced  us  that  Gauss's 

,  .         .  principle 

no  substantially  new  insight  or  perception  is  afforded  by  affords  no 

new  insisli^ 

Gauss's  principle.  ^  Employing  form  (3)  of  the  prin- 
ciple and  resolving  all  the  forces  and  accelerations  in 
the  mutually  perpendicular  coordinate- directions,  giv- 
ing here  the  letters  the  same  significations  as  in  equa- 
tion (i)  on  page  342,  we  get  in  place  of  the  declination, 
or  constraint,  2my^,  the  expression 

2-] 


N=^m 


—  <? 


(4) 


and  by  virtue  of  the  minimum  condition 


362  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 


=  0. 

or  2[(Ar— w  ^  ^/^  +  (  K— »i  7) //^  +  (Z— OT  <?y  <2]  =  0. 
Gauss's  and        If  no  Connections  exist,  the  coefficients  of  the  (in 

D'Alem-  .  ^ 

berfs  prin-  that  case  arbitrary)  //^,  dti.  d^,  severally  made  =  0, 

ciples  com-     .  ,  , 

mutable,  give  the  equations  of  motion.  But  if  connections  do 
exist,  we  have  the  same  relations  between  dSt  drfy  dSi 
as  above  in  equation  (i),  at  page  342,  between  rfjc,  d}\ 
dz.  The  equations  of  motion  come  out  the  same  ;  as 
the  treatment  of  the  same  example  by  D'Alembert's 
principle  and  by  Gauss's  principle  fully  demonstrates. 
The  first  principle,  however,  gives  the  equations  of 
motion  directly,  the  second  only  after  differentiation. 
If  we  seek  an  expression  that  shall  give  by  differentia- 
tion D'Alembert's  equations,  we  are  led  perforce  to  the 
principle  of  Gauss.  The  principle,  therefore,  is  new 
only  in  form  and  not  in  matter.  Nor  does  it,  further, 
possess  any  advantage  over  the  Lagrangian  form  of 
D'Alembert's  principle  in  respect  of  competency  to  com- 
prehend both  statical  and  dynamical  problems,  as  has 
been  before  pointed  out  (page  342). 

The  phys-  There  is  no  need  of  seeking  a  mystical  or  metaphys- 

ical  basis  ,       .  , 

of  the  prin-  /Va/reason  for  Gauss's  principle.  The  expression  '  *  least 

ciple.  ...  .  1  .  i.      , 

constramt"  may  seem  to  promise  somethmg  of  the 
sort ;  but  the  name  proves  nothing.  The  answer  to  the 
question,  *'/«  what  does  this  constraint  consist  ?  "  can- 
not be  derived  from  metaphysics,  but  must  be  sought 
in  the  facts.  The  expression  (2)  of  page  353,  or  (4)  of 
page  361,  which  is  made  a  minimum,  represents  the 
work  done  in  an  element  of  time  by  the  deviation  of  the 
constrained  motion  from  the  free  motion.  This  work, 
the  work  due  to  the  constraint,  is  less  for  the  motion 
actually  performed  than  for  any  other  possible  motion. 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES, 


363 


Once  we  have  recognised  work  as  the  factor  deter-  Rdie  of  the 

factor  work. 

minative  of  motion,  once  we  have  grasped  the  mean- 
ing of  the  principle  of  virtual  displacements  to  be,  that 
motion  can  never  take  place  except  where  work  can  be 
performed,  the  following  converse  truth  also  will  in- 
volve no  difficulty,  namely,  that  all  the  work  that  can 
be  performed  in  an  element  of  time  actually  is  per- 
formed. Consequently,  the  total  diminution  of  work 
due  in  an  element  of  time  to  the  connections  of  the 
system's  parts  is  restricted  to  the  portion  annulled  by 
the  counter-work  of  those  parts.  It  is  again  merely  a 
new  aspect  of  a  familiar  fact  with  which  we  have  here 
to  deal. 

This  relation  is  displayed  in  the  very  simplest  cases.  The  foun- 

dations  of 

Let  there  be  two  masses  m  and  m  2X  A^  the  one  im-  the  princi- 
ple reccg- 

pressed  with  a  force  /,  the  other  with  nisabie  m 

the  force  q.     If  we  connect  the  two,  we         .       ,.  ^0  piest  cases, 
shall  have  the  mass  2  m  acted  on  by  a 
resultant  force  r.   Supposing  the  spaces 
described  in  an  element  of  time  by  the 
free  masses  to  be  represented  by  A  C, 
A  By  the  space  described  by  the  con- 
joint,  or  double,  mass  will  be  AO  = 
^AD,     The   deviation,    or  constraint, 
is    m(^OB^  +  OC^).     It   is  less   than 
it  would  be  if  the  mass  arrived  at  the  end  of  the  ele- 
ment of  time  in  M  or  indeed  in  any  point  lying  out- 
side of  B  Cy  say  N,  as  the  simplest  geometrical  con- 
siderations will  show.     The  deviation  is  proportional 
to  the  expression  p^  -\-  q^  -\-  '^pq  cos  ^/2,  which  in  the 
case  of  equal  and  opposite  forces  becomes  2/2^  and  in 
the  case  of  equal  and  like-directed  forces  zero. 

Two  forces  /  and  q  act  on  the  same  mass.     The 
force  q  we  resolve  parallel  and  at  right  angles  to  the 


Fig.  187. 


364  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

Even  in  the  direction  of  /  in  r  and  s.  The  work  done  in  an  element 

principle  of  .  . 

the  compo-  of  time  is  proportional  to  the  squares  of  the  forces,  and 

sition  of  ,  .  .  .,  1      « 

forces  its    if  there  be  no  connections  is  expressible  by  /^  _|_  ^3  _-. 

properties 

are  found,  ^a  -[-  r  ^  -(-  j-^.  If  now  r  act  directly  counter  to  the 
force  /,  a  diminution  of  work  will  be  effected  and  the 
sum  mentioned  becomes  (/  —  r)^  +  j^.  Even  in  the 
principle  of  the  composition  of  forces,  or  of  the  mutual 
independence  of  forces,  the  properties  are  contained 
which  Gauss's  principle  makes  use  of.  This  will  best 
be  perceived  by  imagining  all  the  accelerations  simul- 
taneously performed.  If  we  discard  the  obscure  verbal 
form  in  which  the  principle  is  clothed,  the  metaphysical 
impression  which  it  gives  also  vanishes.  We  see  the 
simple  fact ;  we  are  disillusioned,  but  also  enlightened. 
The  elucidations  of  Gauss's  principle  here  presented 
are  in  great  part  derived  from  the  paper  of  SchefHer 
cited  above.  Some  of  his  opinions  which  I  have  been 
unable  to  share  I  have  modified.  We  cannot,  for  ex- 
ample, accept  as  new  the  principle  which  he  himself 
propounds,  for  both  in  form  and  in  import  it  is  identical 
with  the  D'Alembert-Lagrangian. 


VIII. 
THE  PRINCIPLE  OF    LEAST  ACTION. 

Theorig-  I.    Maupertuis  enunciated,   in   1747,   a  principle 

scurefortn  which  he  Called  **  le  principe  de  la  moindre  quantity  d'ac- 

dpie*o?""  iion,^^  the  principle  of  least  action.     He  declared  this 

'  principle  to  be  one  which  eminently  accorded  with  the 

wisdom  of  the  Creator.     He  took  as  the  measure  of 

the  "action"  the  product  of  the  mass,  the  velocity, 

and  the  space  described,  or  m%)s,      Why^  it  must  be 

confessed,  is  not  clear.    By  mass  and  velocity  definite 

quantities  may  be  understood ;  not  so,  however,  by 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.         365 

space,  when  the  time  is  not  stated  in  which  the  space 
is  described.  If,  however,  unit  of  time  be  meant,  the 
distinction  of  space  and  velocity  in  the  examples  treated 
by  Maupertuis  is,  to  say  the  least,  peculiar.  It  appears 
that  Maupertuis  reached  this  obscure  expression  by  an 
unclear  mingling  of  his  ideas  of  vis  viva  and  the  prin- 
ciple of  virtual  velocities.  Its  indistinctness  will  be 
more  saliently  displayed  by  the  details. 

2.  Let  us  see  how  Maupertuis  applies  his  principle.  Determina- 

If  My  m  be  two  inelastic  masses,  Cand  c  their  velocities  laws  of  im- 
pact by  this 

before  impact,  and  u  their  common  velocity  after  im-  principle, 
pact,  Maupertuis  requires,  (putting  here  velocities  for 
spaces,)  that  the  "action"  expended  in  the  change  of 
the  velocities  in  impact  shall  be  a  minimum.  Hence, 
M{C  —  u)^  '\-  m{c  —  «)  2  is  a  minimum \  that  is, 
m\c—  »)  +  w  (r  —  «)  ==  0 ;  or 

MC  -\-  mc 

For  the  impact  of  elastic  masses,  retaining  the  same 
designations,  only  substituting  Kand  v  for  the  two  ve- 
locities after  impact,  the  expression  M{C —  ^)^  + 
in{c — ^^7^)2  is  a  minimum;  that  is  to  say, 

M{^C—V)dV^m{c  —  v^dv  =  ^ (1) 

In  consideration  of  the  fact  that  the  velocity  of  ap- 
proach before  impact  is  equal  to  the  velocity  of  reces- 
sion after  impact,  we  have 

C—c  =  —  (^V—v)  or 

C-^  r-(r  +  rO  =  0 (2) 

and 

d  V—  dv  =  0 (3) 

The  combination  of  equations  (i),  (2),  and  (3) 
readily  gives  the  familiar  expressions  for  ^  and  v. 
These  two  cases  may,  as  we  see,  be  viewed  as  pro- 


366  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

cesses  in  which  the  least  change  of  vis  viva  by  reaction 
takes  place,  that  is,  in  which  the  Uast  counter-work  is 
done.     They  fall,   therefore,   under  the  principle  of 
Gauss. 
Maupcr-  3.   Peculiar  is  Maupertuis's  deduction  of  the  law  of 

tuis;sde-  •'  .  _. 

ductionof  the  lever.     Two  masses  M  and  m  (Fig.  188)  rest  on  a 

the  law  of  .  .  . 

the  lever  by  bar  <z,  which  the  fulcrum  divides  into  the  portions 

this  pnn-  1  1       • 

cipie.  X  and  a  —  jc.  If  the  bar  be  set  in  rotation^  the  veloci- 
ties and  the  spaces  described  will  be  proportional  to 
the  lengths  of  the  lever-arms,  and  Mx^  •\-  m{a  —  x)'^ 
is  the  quantity  to  be  made  a  minimum,  that  is  Mx  — 
m{a  —  jc)  =  0  ;  whence  x  =  majM  +  /«, — a  condition 

that  in  the  case  of  equilib- 

, rium  is  actually  fulfilled.  In 

^' • -w       criticism  of  this,  it  is  to  be 

^  ^_^  remarked,  first,  that  masses 

Fig.  188.  not    subject  to  gravity   or 

other  forces,  as  Maupertuis 
here  tacitly  assumes,  are  always  in  equilibrium,  and, 
secondly,  that  the  inference  from  Maupertuis*s  deduc- 
tion is  that  the  principle  of  least  action  is  fulfilled 
only  in  the  case  of  equilibrium,  a  conclusion  which  it 
was  certainly  not  the  author's  intention  to  demonstrate. 
The  correc-  If  it  Were  sought  to  bring  this  treatment  into  ap- 
pertuis's  proximatc  accord  with  the  preceding,  we  should  have 
to  assume  that  the  heavy  masses  M  and  m  constantly 
produced  in  each  other  during  the  process  the  least 
possible  change  of  vis  viva.  On  that  supposition,  we 
should  get,  designating  the  arms  of  the  lever  briefly  by 
tf,  b^  the  velocities  acquired  in  unit  of  time  by  u^  v,  and 
the  acceleration  of  gravity  by  g,  as  our  minimum  ex- 
pression, M{g —  «)2  -|-  m{g —  v)^\  whence  Af{g —  «) 
du  +  m(^g —  v)dv  =  0.  But  in  view  of  the  connection 
of  the  masses  as  lever, 


deduction. 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES. 


367 


u 
a 

du 


7' 


whence  these  equations  correctly  follow 

Afa  —  md  Afa  —  mfi 

and  for  the  case  of  equilibrium,  where  u  =  v  =  0, 

Ma  —  mb  =  0. 

Thus,  this  deduction  also,  when  we  come  to  rectify 
it,  leads  to  Gauss's  principle. 

4.   Following  the  precedent  of  Fermat  and  Leib-  Trcatmeni 

of  the  mo- 

nitz,  Maupertuis  also  treats  by  his  method  the  motion rAonoiw^x 

by  the  pnn- 

of  light.     Here  again,  however,  cfpie  of 

•  he  employs  the  notion  *'  least  ac- 
tion "  in  a  totally  different  sense. 
The   expression   which   for    the 
case  of  refraction  shall  be  a  min- 
imum,    is    m  ,  AR    +    «  •  RB^ 
where  AR  and  RB  denote  the 
paths  described  by  the  light  in 
the  first  and  second  media  re- 
spectively,   and    m    and   n   the    corresponding   velo- 
cities.    True,  we  really  do  obtain  here,  if  R  be  de- 
termined in  conformity  with  the  minimum  condition, 
the  result  sma /sin  ft  =  n/m  =^  const.     But  before,  the 
* '  action  "  consisted  in  the  change  of  the  expressions 
mass  X  velocity  X  distance ;  now,  however,  it  is  con- 
stituted of  the  sum  of  these  expressions.     Before,  the 
spaces  described  in  unit  of  time  were  considered  ;  in 
the  present  case  the  total  spaces  traversed  are  taken. 
Should  not  m,  AR  —  n.  RB  or  [m  —  n){AR  —  RB) 
be  taken  as  a  minimum,  and  if  not,  why  not?     But 


Fig.  189. 


368  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

even  if  we  accept  Maupertuis's  conception,  the  recip- 
rocal values  of  the  velocities  of  the  light  are  obtained, 
and  not  the  actual  values, 
characteri-        It  wiU  thus  be  Seen  that  Maupertuis  really  had  no 
Manper-     principle,  properly  speaking,  but  only  a  vague  form- 
cipie.         ula,  which  was  forced  to  do  duty  as  the  expression  of 
different  familiar  phenomena  not  really  brought  under 
one  conception.     I  have  found  it  necessary  to  enter 
into  some  detail  in  this  matter,  since  Maupertuis's  per- 
formance, though  it  has  been  unfavorably  criticised  by 
all  mathematicians,  is,  nevertheless,  still  invested  with 
a  sort  of  historical  halo.     It  would  seem  almost  as  if 
something  of  the  pious  faith  of  the  church  had  crept 
into  mechanics.     However,  the  mere  endeavor  to  gain 
a  more  extensive  view,  although  beyond  the  powers  of 
the  author,  was  not  altogether  without  results.    Euler, 
at  least,  if  not  also  Gauss,  was  stimulated  by  the  at- 
tempt of  Maupertuis. 
Euier'scon-        5.   Euler's  vicw  is,   that  the  purposes  of  the  phe- 

tributions  tt       ■%  j  •  r 

to  this  sub-  nomena  of  nature  afford  as  good  a  basis  of  explana- 

ject.  , 

tion  as  their  causes.  If  this  position  be  taken,  it  will 
be  presumed  a  priori  that  all  natural  phenomena  pre- 
sent a  maximum  or  minimum.  Of  what  character  this 
maximum  or  minimum  is,  can  hardly  be  ascertained 
by  metaphysical  speculations.  But  in  the  solution  of 
mechanical  problems  by  the  ordinary  methods,  it  is 
possible,  if  the  requisite  attention  be  bestowed  on  the 
matter,  to  find  the  expression  which  in  all  cases  is 
made  a  maximum  or  a  minimum.  Euler  is  thus  not 
led  astray  by  any  metaphysical  propensities,  and  pro- 
ceeds much  more  scientifically  than  Maupertuis.  He 
seeks  an  expression  whose  variation  put  =  0  gives  the 
ordinary  equations  of  mechanics. 

For  a  single  body  moving  under  the  action  of  forces 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.  369 

Euler  finds  the  requisite  expression  in  the  formula  The  form 

which  the 

Cv  dsy  where  ds  denotes  the  element  of  the  path  and  principle 
V  the  corresponding  velocity.  This  expression  is  sm  aller  Euier's 
for  the  path  actually  taken  than  for  any  other  infinitely 
adjacent  neighboring  path  between  the  same  initial 
and  terminal  points,  which  the  body  may  be  constrained 
to  take.  Conversely,  therefore,  by  seeking  the  path  that 
makes  Cv  ds  a  minimum,  we  can  also  determine  the 
path.  The  problem  of  minimising  Cv  d's  is,  of  course, 
as  Euler  assumed,  a  permissible  one,  only  when  v  de- 
pends on  the  position  of  the  elements  ds,  that  is  to 
say,  when  the  principle  of  vis  viva  holds  for  the  forces, 
or  a  force-function  exists,  or  what  is  the  same  thing, 
when  Z7  is  a  simple  function  of  coordinates.  For  a  mo- 
tion in  a  plane  the  expression  would  accordingly  as- 
sume the  form 


^  .  ,  c^y 


In  the  simplest  cases  Euler 's  principle  is  easily  veri- 
fied.    If  no  forces  act,  v  is  constant,  and  the  curve  of 
motion  becomes  a  straight  line,  for  which     Cvds^=^ 
V  C  ds  is  unquestionably  shorter  than  for  any  other 
curve  between  the  same  terminal  points. 
Also,  a  body  moving  on  a  curved  surface 
without  the  action  of  forces  or  friction, 
preserves  its  velocity,  and  describes  on 
the  surface  a  shortest  line. 

The  consideration  of  the  motion  of  a       |  \^      euIct's 

projectile  in  a  parabola  ^^C  (Fig.  190)  n^     SppulS^to 

will  also  show  that  the  quantity  Jv  ds    d  AC  S^Trofec- 

is  smaller  for  the  parabola  than  for  any  „.  ****' 

Other  neighboring  curve ;  smaller,  even, 
than  for  the  straight  line  ABC  between  the  same  ter- 
minal points.  The  velocity,  here,  depends  solely  on  the 


370  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

Mathemat-  vertical  space  described  by  the  body,  and  is  therefore 

ical  dcvel-  j  -j  * 

opmentof  the  Same  for  all  curves  whose  altitude  above  OC  is  the 
same.  If  we  divide  the  curves  by  a  system  of  horizontal 
straight  lines  into  elements  which  severally  correspond, 
the  elements  to  be  multiplied*  by  the  same  t^'s,  though 
in  the  upper  portions  smaller  for  the  straight  line  AD 
than  for  AB,  are  in  the  lower  portions  just  the  reverse ; 
and  as  it  is  here  that  the  larger  v^s  come  into  play,  the 
sum  upon  the  whole  is  smaller  iox  ABC  than  for  the 
straight  line. 

Putting  the  origin  of  the  codrdinates  at  Ay  reckon- 
ing the  abscissas  x  vertically  downwards  as  positive, 
and  calling  the  ordinates  perpendicular  thereto  y^  we 
obtain  for  the  expression  to  be  minimised 

0 

where  g  denotes  the  acceleration  of  gravity  and  a  the 
distance  of  descent  corresponding  to  the  initial  velocity. 
As  the  condition  of  minimum  the  calculus  of  variations 
gives 


V 


=  C  or 


4 


' + m 


dy 


dx  ^  —^  -' °' 


Vlg\a  +  *)  -  C» 

/Cdx 
l/2g(a  +  x)-^^C^ 
and,  ultimately, 


y  = 


y=-\/2g(a-^x)—C^^C\ 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES,         371 

where  C  and  C*  denote  constants  of  integration  that 
pass  into  C=^V  7,ga  and  C=  0,  if  for  jt  =  0,  dx/dy  =  0 
and  j^  =  0  be  taken.  Therefore,  y  =  21/ ax.  By  this 
method,  accordingly,  the  path  of  a  projectile  is  shown 
to  be  of  parabolic  form. 

6.-  Subsequently,  Lagrange  drew  express  attention  The  addi- 
to  the  fact  that  Euler's  principle  is  applicable  only  in  Rrange  and 
cases  in  which  the  principle  of  vis  viva  holds.  Jacobi 
pointed  out  that  we  cannot  assert  that  Cv  ds  for  the  ac- 
tual motion  is  a  minimum^  but  simply  that  the  variation  of 
this  expression,  in  its  passage  fo  an  infinitely  adjacent 
neighboring  path,  is  =  0.  Generally,  indeed,  this  con- 
dition coincides  with  a  maximum  or  minimum,  but  it 
is  possible  that  it  should  occur  without  such ;  and  the 
minimum  property  in  particular  is  subject  to  certain 
limitations.  For  example,  if  a  body,  constrained  to 
move  on  a  spherical  surface,  is  set  in  motion  by  some 
impulse,  it  will  describe  a  great  circle,  generally  a 
shortest  line.  But  if  the  length  of  the  arc  described 
exceeds  1 80°,  it  is  easily  demonstrated  that  there  exist 
shorter  infinitely  adjacent  neighboring  paths  between 
the  terminal  points. 

7.   So  far,  then,  this  fact  only  has  been  pointed  out,  Baler's, 
that  the  ordinary  equations  of  motion  are  obtained  by  but  one  of 
equating  the  variation  of   Cv  ds  to  zero.    But  since  the  give^he  * 
properties  of  the  motion  of  bodies  or  of  their  paths  may  oJmoUon. 
always  be  defined  by  differential  expressions  equated 
to  zero,  and  since  furthermore  the  condition  that  the 
variation  of  an  integral  expression  shall  be  equal  to 
zero  is  likewise  given  by  differential  expressions  equated 
to  zero,  unquestionably  various  other  integral  expres- 
sions may  be  devised  that  give  by  variation  the  ordi- 
nary equations  of  motion,  without  its  following  that  the 


372  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

integral  expressions  in  question  must  possess  on  that 
account  any  particular  physical  significance. 
Yet  the  ex-         8.  The  Striking  fact  remains,  however,  that  so  simple 
must  pos-    an  expression  as  fr  ds  does  possess  the  property  men- 
icai  import,  tioued,  and  we  will  now  endeavor  to  ascertain  its  phys- 
ical import.     To  this  end  the  analogies  that  exist  be- 
tween the  motion  of  masses  and  the  motion  of  light,  as 
well  as  between  the  motion  of  masses  and  the  equilib- 
rium of  strings — analogies  noted  by  John  Bernoulli 
and  by  Mobius — will  stand  us  in  stead. 

A  body  on  which  'ho  forces  act,  and  which  there- 
fore preserves  its  velocity  and  direction  constant,  de- 
scribes a  straight  line.  A  ray  of  light  passing  through 
a  homogeneous  medium  (one  having  everywhere  the 
same  index  of  refraction)  describes  a  straight  line.  A 
string,  acted  on  by  forces  at  its  extremities  only,  as- 
sumes the  shape  of  a  straight  line. 
Elucidation       A  body  that  moves  in  a  curved  path  from  a  point 

Of  this  im-  •  r»  «         1  1        • 

port  by  the  ^  to  a  point  B  and  whose  velocity  7f  =^  fl>(^,  y,  z)  is  a 

motion  of  a  .  ,  , 

mass,  the    function  of  Coordinates,  describes  between  A  and  B  a 

motion  of  a  ,  •    i  n        /•       ,     •  •     •  a 

ray  of  light,  curve  f or  which  generally   H'  as  is  a  minimum.    A  ray 
eauiiibrium  of  light  passing  from  A  to  B  describes  the  same  curve, 
if  the  refractive  index  of  its  medium,  «  =  ^(jc,  y,  z), 
is  the  same  function  of  coordinates ;  and  in  this  case 
fnds  is  a  minimum.     Finally,  a  string  passing  from 
A  to  B  will  assume  this  curve,   if  its  tension  S  = 
<P  (p^f  y*  ^)  is  the  same  above-mentioned  function  of  co- 
ordinates ;  and  for  this  case,  also,    CSds  is  a  minimum. 
The  motion  of  a  mass  may  be  readily  deduced  from 
the  equilibrium  of  a  stringy  as  follows.     On  an  element 
ds  oidL.  string,  at  its  two  extremities,  the  tensions  S,  S' 
act,  and  supposing  the  force  on  unit  of  length  to  be  P^ 
in  addition  a  force  P.  ds.     These  three  forces,  which 
we  shall  represent  in  magnitude  and  direction  by  BA, 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES. 


373 


BC^  BD  (Fig.  191),  are  in  equilibrium.  If  now,  a  body,  The  moUon 
with  a  velocity  ly  represented  in  magnitude  and  diiec-  deduced 
tion  by  AB^  enter  the  element  of  the  path  ds^  and  re-  eauiiibriun 
ceive  within  the  same  the  velocity  component  BF  = 
—  BD,  the  body  will  proceed  on- 
ward with  the  velocity  v'  =  BC. 
Let   Q  be   an  accelerating  force 
whose  action  is  directly  opposite 
to  that  of  B;  then  for  unit  of  time 
the  acceleration  of  this  force  ^11 
be  Q,  for  unit  of  length  of  the 
string  Q/v,  and  for  the  element 
of  the  string  (Q/v)ds,  The  body  will  move,  therefore, 
in  the  curzfe  of  the  string,  if  we  establish  between  the 
forces  P  and  the  tensions  S,  in  the  case  of  the  string, 
and  the  accelerating  forces  Q  and  the  velocity  v  in  the 
case  of  the  mass,  the  relation 


Fig.  Z9Z. 


V 

The  minus  sign  indicates  that  the  directions  of  P  and 
Q  are  opposite. 

A  closed  circular  string  is  in  equilibrium  when  be-  The  eqm- 

,  librinm  ox 

tween  the  tension  S  of  the  strmg,  everywhere  constant,  closed 

strings. 

and  the  force  P  falling  radially  outwards  on  unit  of 
length,  the  relation  P  =  Sjr  obtains,  where  r  is  the 
radius  of  the  circle.  A  body  will  move  with  the  con- 
stant velocity  v  in  a  circle,  when  between  the  velocity 
and  the  accelerating  force  Q  acting  radially  inwards 
the  relation 

Q 


7f 


71 


a 


=   -  or  ^  =   -   obtains. 
V        r  r 

A  body  will  move  with  constant  velocity  v  in  any  curve 
when  an  accelerating  force  Qz=v^/r  constantly  acts 


374 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 


on  it  in  the  direction  of  the  centre  of  curvature  of  each 
element.  A  string  will  lie  under  a  constant  tension  S 
in  any  curve  if  a  force  P  =  Sjr  acting  outwardly  from 
the  centre  of  curvature  of  the  element  is  impressed  on 
unit  of  length  of  the  string. 
The  deduc*  No  concept  aualogous  to  that  of  force  is  applicable 
motion  of    to  the  tnotioTi  of  light.     Consequently,  the  deduction  of 

light  froni 

the  motions  the  motion  of  light  from  the  equilibrium  of  a  string  or 

of  masses  , 

and  the,     the  motion  of  a  mass  must  be  differently  effected.     A 

equilibnnm  ,  ,  , 

of  strings,    mass,  let  us  say,  is  moving  with  the  velocity  AB  =  v. 

(Fig.  192.)  A  force  in  the  direction 
B£>  is  impressed  on  the  mass  which 
produces  an  increase  of  velocity  B£, 
so  that  by  the  composition  of  the  ve- 
locities BC  =  AB  and  B£  the  new 
velocity  BP  =  v'  is  produced.  If  we 
resolve  the  velocities  v,  v*  into  com- 
ponents parallel  and  perpendicular  to 
the  force  in  question,  we  shall  per- 
ceive that  the  parallel  components  alone 
are  changed  by  the  action  of  the  force. 
This  being  the  case,  we  get,  denoting 
by  k  the  perpendicular  component,  and  by  a  and  c^ 
the  angles  v  and  v*  make  with  the  direction  of  the 


Fig.  193. 


force. 


k^=v  sin  a 
k  =  7/  sin  a'  or 


sm^ 
sin  a* 


V 
V 


If,  now,  we  picture  to  ourselves  a  ray  of  light  that 
penetrates  in  the  direction  of  v  a  refracting  plane  at 
right  angles  to  the  direction  of  action  of  the  force,  and 
thus  passes  from  a  medium  having  the  index  of  refrac- 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES,         375 
tion  n  into  a  medium  having  the  index  of  refraction  ri^  Develop- 

,  mentor  this 

where  «/«'  =  7^7^',  this  ray  of  light  will  describe  the  illustration, 
same  path  as  the  body  in  the  case  above.  If,  there- 
fore, we  wish  to  imitate  the  motion  of  a  mass  by  the 
motion  of  a  ray  of  light  (in  the  same  curve),  we  must 
everywhere  put  the  indices  of  refraction,  «,  proportional 
to  the  velocities.  To  deduce  the  indices  of  refraction 
from  the  forces,  we  obtain  for  the  velocity 


a 


//  I -^  1  =  Pdq,  and 
for  the  index  of  refraction,  by  analogy. 


where  P  denotes  the  force  and  dg  a  distance-element 
in  the  direction  of  the  force.  If  ds  is  the  element  of 
the  path  and  a  the  angle  made  by  it  with  the  direction 
of  the  force,  we  have  then 

d[  (,-]  =  Pcosa.  ds 

(n^\ 
d\      ]  =  Pcosa.  ds. 

For  the  path  of  a  projectile,  under  the  conditions  above 
assumed,  we  obtained  the  expression y  =  2yax.  This 
same  parabolic  path  will  be  described  by  a  ray  of  light, 
if  the  law  n  ==  \/2g(a  -}-  x)  be  taken  as  the  index  of 
refraction  of  the  medium  in  which  it  travels. 

9.  We  will  now  more  accurately  investigate  the  Relation  of 
manner  in  which  this  minimum  property  is  related  to  mum  prop- 
the/^r»f  of  the  curve.     Let  us  take,  first,  (Fig.  193)  afoimof 
broken  straight  line  ABC,  which  intersects  the  straight 
line  MJV,  put  AB  =  s,  BC  =  s',  and  seek  the  condition 
that  makes  vs  -f  7'V  a  minimum  for  the  line  that  passes 


376 


7'HE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 


First,  de- 
duction of 
the  mini- 
mum condi' 
tion. 


through  the  fixed  points  A  and  B^  where  v  and  v'  are 
supposed  to  have  different,  though  constant,  values 
above  and  below  MN,  If  we  displace  the  point  B  an 
infinitely  small  distance  to  D^  the  new  line  through  A 
and  C  will  remain  parallel  to  the  original  one,  as  the 
drawing  symbolically  shows.  The  expression  vs  -\-  v's' 
is  increased  hereby  by  an  amount 

—  timsma  +  v'ms\na\ 

where  m  ^=  DBj  or  by  an  amount  —  v  sin  a  +  7/  sin  or'. 
The  condition  of  the  minimum,  consequently,  is  that 

—  V  sin  a  +  v'  sin  or'  =  0 


s\na 

or  -T      ,= 

smar 


7f 
V 


R       N 


FiR.  193. 


ri«.  19,. 


If  the  expression  sjv  -{■  s  ji^'  is  to  be  made  a  minimum, 
we  have,  in  a  similar  way, 


/• 


smo:  V 

sin «'       V* 

Second,  the        If,  next,  we  Consider  the  case  of  a  string  stretched 

SfoiU^con*?  in  the  direction  ABC,  the  tensions  of  which  .Sand  ^S" 

eauiiibrium  are  different  above  and  below  MN,  in  this  case  it  is 

the  minimum  of  Ss  -f  S*s*  that  is  to  be  dealt  with.   To 

obtain  a  distinct  idea  of  this  case,  we  may  imagine  the 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES. 


yn 


motion  of  a 
ray  of  light. 


String  stretched  once  between  A  and  B  and  thrice  be- 
tween B  and  C,  and  finally  a  weight  P  attached.  Then 
S=  P  and  5'  =  3 -P.  If  we  displace  the  point  B  a  dis- 
tance m,  any  diminution  of  the  expression  Ss -{- S's' 
thus  effected,  will  express  the  increase  of  work  which 
the  attached  weight  P  performs.  If  — Sm  sin  a -^ 
S'm  sin  a'  =  0,  no  work  is  performed.  Hence,  the  mini- 
mum of  Ss  -\-  S's'  corresponds  to  a  maximum  of  work. 
In  the  present  case  the  principle  of  least  action  is  sim- 
ply a  different  form  of  the  principle  of  virtual  displace- 
ments. 

Now  suppose  that  ABC  is  a  ray  of  light,  whose  ve-  Third,  the 

application 

locities  V  and  v'  above  and  below  MN  are  to  each  other  of  thi«  con- 
dition to  the 
as  3  to  I.     The  motion  of  light  be- 
tween two  points  A  and  B  is  such 
that  the  light  reaches  ^  in  a  mini- 
mum of  time.     The  physical  reason 
of  this  is  simple.     The  light  travels 
from  A  to  B^   in  the  form    of  ele- 
mentary waves,  by  different  routes. 
Owing  to  the  periodicity  of  the  light, 
the    waves    generally  destroy  each 
other,  and  only  those  that  reach  the 
designated  point  in  equal  times,  that  is,  in  equal  phases, 
produce  a  result.     But  this  is  true  only  of  the  waves 
that  arrive  by  the  minimum  path  and  its  adjacent  neigh- 
boring paths.     Hence,  for  the  path  actually  taken  by 
the  light  s/v  +  j'/p'  is  a  minimum.     And  since  the  in- 
dices of  refraction  n  are  inversely  proportional  to  the 
velocities  v  of  the  light,  therefore  also  ns  ■\-  n*s*  is  a 
minimum. 

In  the  consideration  of  the  motion  of  a  mass  the  con- 
dition that  vs  -\-  v's*  shall  be  a  minimum,  strikes  us  as 
something  novel.   (Fig.  195.)  If  a  mass,  in  its  passage 


Fig-  195- 


378  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

Fourth,  it:!  through  a  plane  MN^  receive,  as  the  result  of  the  action 
fo  the  m<^"  of  a  force  impressed  in  the  direction  DB,  an  increase  of 
mass.         velocity,  by  which  v,  its  original  velocity,  is  made  v' y  we 
have  for  the  path  actually  taken  by  the  mass  the  equa- 
tion 7/  sin  a  =  z/'  sin  a'  =  k.    This  equation^  which  is  also 
the  condition  of  minimum,  simply  states  that  only  the  ve- 
locity-component parallel  to  the  direction  of  the  force  is 
altered,  but  that  the  component  k  at  right  angles  thereto  re- 
mains unchanged.    Thus,  in  this  case  also,  Euler's  prin- 
ciple simply  states  a  familiar  fact  in  a  new  form. 
Formofthe        lo.  The  minimum  condition  —  t^sinar+ e^'sina'sTrO 
condition    may  also  be  written,  if  we  pass  from  a  finite  broken 
to  curves.    Straight  line  to  the  elements  of  curves,  in  the  form 

—  V  sin  a  -\-  (y  -\-  dv)  sin(a  +  dd)  =  0 
or 

d(v  sin  «)  =  0 

or,  finally, 

tf  sin  a  =  const. 

In  agreement  with  this,  we  obtain  for  the  motion 

of  light 

d  {n  sin  «)  =  0,  n  sin  a  =  const, 

\      ^'      J  V 

and  for  the  equilibrium  of  a  string 

d{Ssmd)  =  0,  ^sina  =  const. 

To  illustrate  the  preceding  remarks  by  an  ex- 
ample,  let  us  take  the  parabolic  path  of  a  projectile, 
where  a  always  denotes  the  angle  that  the  element  of 
the  path  makes  with  the  perpendicular.  Let  the  ve- 
locity he  7f  =  \/2g(^a  -\-  x),  and  let  the  axis  of  the_y-or- 
dinates  be  horizontal.  The  condition  v.  sin  a  =  const, 
or  V  2g{a  -f-  A*)  .  dy/ds  =  const,  is  identical  with  that 
which  the  calculus  of  variation  gives,  and  we  now  know 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES, 


yi^ 


Fig.  xgC 


its  xww^/^/^w/Va/ significance.  If  we  picture  to  ourselves  niustration 

.  ,  T        .  / >-  of  the  three 

a  string  whose  tension  is  5  =  k  2r  («  +  x\  an  arrange-  typical 

...  caaea  by 

ment  which  might  be  effected  by  fixing  frictionless  curvilinear 

.  .        motiona. 

pulleys  on  horizontal  parallel  rods  placed  in  a  vertical 
plane,  then  passing  the  string  through  these  a  sufficient 
number  of  times,  and  finally  attaching 
a  weight  to  the  extremity  of  the  string, 
we  shall  obtain  again,  for  equilibrium, 
the  preceding  condition,  the  phys- 
ical significance  of  which  is  now  ob- 
vious. When  the  distances  between 
the  rods  are  made  infinitely  small  the 
string  assumes  the  parabolic  form. 
In  a  medium,  the  refractive  index  of 
which  varies  in  the  vertical  direction 
by  the  law  n  =  \^2g{a  +  x),  or  the  velocity  of  light  in 
which  similarly  varies  by  the  law  v  =  \/\/'2g{a  +  x)^ 
a  ray  of  light  will  describe  a  path  which  is  a  parabola. 
If  we  should  make  the  velocity  in  such  a  medium 
V  =  \/2g{a-\-x),  the  ray  would  describe  a  cycloidal  path, 
for  which,  not  CV2g{a  +  x).  ds,  but  the  expression 
Cds/\/2g{a  +  x)  would  be  a  minimum. 

II.   In  comparing  the  equilibrium  of  a  string  with 
the  motion  of  a  mass,  we  may  employ  in  place  of  a 
string  wound  round  pulleys, 
a  simple  homogeneous  cord, 
provided  we  subject  the  cord 
to  an  appropriate  system   of 
forces.     We  readily    observe 
that    the    systems    of    forces 
that   make    the    tension,    or, 
as  the  case  may  be,   the  ve- 
locity,  the  same  function    of   coordinates,   are   differ- 
ent.   If  we  consider,  for  example,  the  force  of  gravity. 


Fig.  197. 


38o  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 


The  condi-  V  =  V igia  +  x\     A  String,  howcver,  subjected  to  the 

tionsand  ...  -  -x  •  t 

conse-        action  of  gravity,  forms  a  catenary,  the  tension   ot 
Oiepreced-  which  IS  given  by  the  formula  S  =  m  —  nx^  where  m 

ing  analo- 
gies- and  n  are  constants.     The  analogy  subsisting  between 

the  equilibrium  of  a  string  and  the  motion  of  a  mass  is 
substantially  conditioned  by  the  fact  that  for  a  string 
subjected  to  the  action  of  forces  possessing  a  force- 
function  U,  there  obtains  in  the  case  of  equilibrium 
the  easily  demonstrable  equation  U  -\-  S=  const.  This 
physical  interpretation  of  the  principle  of  least  action 
is  here  illustrated  only  for  simple  cases ;  but  it  may 
also  be  applied  to  cases  of  greater  complexity,  by 
imagining  groups  of  surfaces  of  equal  tension,  of  equal 
velocity,  or  equally  refractive  indices  constructed  which 
divide  the  string,  the  path  of  the  motion,  or  the  path 
of  the  light  into  elements,  and  by  making  a  in  such  a 
case  represent  the  angle  which  these  elements  make 
with  the  respective  surface- normals.  The  principle  of 
least  action  was  extended  to  systems  of  masses  by  La- 
grange, who  presented  it  in  the  form 

62m  Czfds  =  0. 

If  we  reflect  that  the  principle  of  vis  viva,  which  is  the 
real  foundation  of  the  principle  of  least  action,  is  not 
annulled  by  the  connection  of  the  masses,  we  shall 
comprehend  that  the  latter  principle  is  in  this  case  also 
valid  and  physically  intelligible. 

IX. 

Hamilton's  principle. 

I.  It  was  above  remarked  that  various  expressions 
can  be  devised  whose  variations  equated  to  zero  give 
the  ordinary  equations  of  motion.  An  expression  of 
this  kind  is  contained  in  Hamilton's  principle 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.  381 

S  f(C/'+  T)  dt  =  0,  or  The  points 

J  ^         '  ^  '  of  identity 

'0  of  Hamil- 

tx  ton's  and 

/q  ciples. 

where  <^C/'and  c^T' denote  the  variations  of  the  work 
and  the  vis  viva^  vanishing  for  the  initial  and  terminal 
epochs.  Hamilton's  principle  is  easily  deduced  from 
D'Alembert's,  and,  conversely,  D'Alembert's  from 
Hamilton's ;  the  two  are  in  fact  identical,  their  differ- 
ence being  merely  that  of  form.  * 

2.  We  shall  not  enter  here  into  any  extended  in-  Hamilton's 

.    .  pnncipie 

vestigation  of  this  subject,  but  simply  exhibit  the  iden-  applied  to 

°  .       .     •*        '  '^  •*  the  motion 

tity  of  the  two  principles  by  an  example —  of  a  wheel 

the  same  that  served  to  illustrate  the  prin- 
ciple  of  D'Alembert :  the  motion  of  a  wheel 
and  axle  by  the  over-weight  of  one  of  its 
parts.    In  place  of  the  actual  motion,  we 
may  imagine,  performed  in  the  same  inter- 
val of  time,  a  different  motion,  varying  in- 
finitely little  from  the  actual  motion,  but         p.    ^^ 
coinciding  exactly  with  it  at  the  beginning 
and  end.     There  are  thus  produced  in  every  element 
of  time  dtf  variations  of  the  work  (SU)  and  of  the  vis 
viva  (^ST);  variations,  that  is,  of  the  values  C/'and  T 
realised  in  the  actual  motion.     But  for  the  actual  mo- 
tion, the  integral  expression,  above  stated,  is  =  0,  and 
may  be  employed,  therefore,  to  determine  the  actual 
motion.     If  the  angle  of  rotation  performed  varies  in 
the  element  of  time  di  an  amount  a  from  the  angle  of 
the  actual  motion,  the  variation  of  the  work  corre- 
sponding to  such  an  alteration  will  be 

6C/=  {PR  —Qr)a  =  Ma. 

*  Compare,  for  example,  Kirchhoff,  VarUtungtn  Mber  matkematitche  Pky- 
siky  Meekanik,  p.  aj  et  teqg.^  and  Jacobi,  VorUsungtn  Mhtr  DynamiA,  p.  58. 


382  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

Mathemat-  The  vis  viva,  for  any  given  angular  velocity  a?,  is 

ical  devel- 
opment of  ,^         1    X  ^  ^^  ^  00)^ 
tfiiscase.                                          T=^    -  {PR'^  +  ^/-a)  --, 

and  for  a  variation  dco  of  this  velocity  the  variation  of 
the  vis  viva  is 

But  if  the  angle  of  rotation  varies  in  the  element  <//  an 
amount  a, 

dcD:^--  and 

a/ 

The  form  of  the  integral  expression,  accordingly,  is 


fUa  +  N'^'' 


<//  =  0. 


/( 


But  as 

d  ,j.^   .       dN  da 

therefore, 

'o 

The  second  term  of  the  left-hand  member,  though, 
drops  out,  because,  by  hypothesis,  at  the  beginning 
and  end  of  the  motion  a  =  0.     Accordingly,  we  have 

'o 

an  expression  which,  since  a  in  every  element  of  time 
is  arbitrary,  cannot  subsist  unless  generally 

--  '1= »■ 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.  383 

Substituting  for  the  symbols  the  values  they  represent, 
we  obtain  the  familiar  equation 

//«_    PR—Qr 
d't  '^  PR^  ^r  Qr^^' 
D'Alembert*s  principle  gives  the  equation  The  same 

results  ob- 
'^       (iN\  .  Uinedby 

/  bert's  prin- 

which  holds  for  every  possible  displacement.  We  might,  *^*^*®' 
in  the  converse  order,. have  started  from  this  equation, 
have  thence  passed  to  the  expression 


/(^_^)«^,  =  0. 


dt 

to 

and,  finally,  from  the  latter  proceeded  to  the  same  re- 
sult 


/( 


f(Ma  +  JSr^]  di  =  0. 


d^ 

to 

3.  As  a  second  and  more  simple  example  let  us  ninstration 
consider  the  motion  of  vertical  descent.  .For  every  Sy  the  rnc^ 
infinitely  small  displacement  s  the  equation  subsists  ticai  de- 

SCCDt 

[ntg — m(^dv/diy]s  =  0f  in  which  the  letters  retain 
their  conventional  significance.  Consequently,  this 
equation  obtains 

tt 

w  VT  ]s .di  =  0, 

to 

which,  as  the  result  of  the  relations 


'1 
f[mg  - 


.(mvs)  dv     ,         ds       ^ 


384  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 


J.  fit  =  (m  7'  s)    =  0, 


provided  ^  vanishes  at  both  limits,  passes  into  the  form 

mgs  +  mv  ,\tf/=  0, 


to     ^ 
that  is,  into  the  form  of  Hamilton's  principle. 

Thus,  through  all  the  apparent  differences  of  the 
mechanical  principles  a  common  fundamental  same- 
ness is  seen.  These  principles  are  not  the  expression 
of  different  facts,  but,  in  a  measure,  are  simply  views 
of  different  aspects  of  the  same  fact. 

X. 

SOME  APPLICATIONS  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  MECHANICS  TO 
HYDROSTATIC  AND  HYDRODYNAMIC  QUESTIONS. 

Method  of  I.  We  will  now  supplement  the  examples  which 

the  action    we  have  given  of  the  application  of  the  principles 

of  Ersivitv 

onliquid     of  mechanics,  as  they  applied  to  rigid  bodies,  by  a 

xnflsscs. 

few  hydrostatic  and  hydrodynamic  illustrations.  We 
shall  first  discuss  the  laws  of  equilibrium  of  a  weightless 
liquid  subjected  exclusively  to  the  action  of  so-called 
molecular  forces.  The  forces  of  gravity  we  neglect  in 
our  considerations.  A  liquid  may,  in  fact,  be  placed 
in  circumstances  in  which  it  will  behave  as  if  no  forces 
of  gravity  acted.  The  method  of  this  is  due  to  Pla- 
teau.* It  is  effected  by  immersing  olive  oil  in  a  mix- 
ture of  water  and  alcohol  of  the  same  density  as  the 
oil.  By  the  principle  of  Archimedes  the  gravity  of  the 
masses  of  oil  in  such  a  mixture  is  exactly  counterbal- 
anced, and  the  liquid  really  acts  as  if  it  were  devoid  of 
weight. 

*  Statigue  expirimentale  et  thiorique  des  Itqutdet,  1873. 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.  385 

2.  First,  let  us  imagine  a  weightless  liquid  mass  The  work  of 
free  in  space.     Its  molecular  forces,  we  know,  act  only  forces  de- 

....  rry   \  *  i»  !*•      pcndcnt  on 

at  very  small  distances.    Takmg  as  our  radius  the  dis-  a  change  in 

,  .    ,        ,  ,  ,         r  theliauid's 

tance  at  which  the  molecular  forces  cease  to  exert  a  superficial 

area. 

measurable  influence,  let  us  describe  about  a  particle 
fl,  ^,  c  in  the  interior  of  the  mass  a  sphere — the  so- 
called  sphere  of  action.  This  sphere  of  action  is  regu- 
larly and  uniformly  filled  with  other  particles.  The 
resultant  force  on  the  central  particles  a^  b^  c  is  there- 
fore zero.  Those  parts  only  that  lie  at  a  distance  from 
the  bounding  surface  less  than  the  radius  of  the  sphere 
of  action  are  in  different  dynamic  conditions  from  the 
particles  in  the  interior.     If  the  radii  of  curvature  of 


Fig.  199-  F»K-  aoo. 

the  surface-elements  of  the  liquid  mass  be  all  regarded 
as  very  great  compared  with  the  radius  of  the  sphere 
of  action,  we  may  cut  off  from  the  mass  a  superficial 
stratum  of  the  thickness  of  the  radius  of  the  sphere  of 
action  in  which  the  particles  are  in  different  physical 
conditions  from  those  in  the  interior.  If  we  convey 
a  particle  a  in  the  interior  of  the  liquid  from  the  posi-. 
tion  a  to  the  position  b  or  c^  the  physical  condition 
of  this  particle,  as  well  as  that  of  the  particles  which 
take  its  place,  will  remain  unchanged.  No  work  can 
be  done  in  this  way.  Work  can  be  done  only  when  a 
particle  is  conveyed  from  the  superficial  stratum  into 
the  interior,  or,  from  the  interior  into  the  superficial 
stratum.     That  is  to  say,  work  can  be  done  only  by  a 


/ 


386 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 


change  of  size  of  the  surface.  The  consideration  whether 
the  density  of  the  superficial  stratum  is  the  same  as 
that  of  the  interior,  or  whether  it  is  constant  through- 
out the  entire  thickness  of  the  stratum,  is  not  primarily 
essential.  As  will  readily  be  seen,  the  variation  of  the 
surface-area  is  equally  the  condition  of  the  perform- 
ance of  work  when  the  liquid  mass  is  immersed  in  a 
second  liquid,  as  in  Plateau's  experiments. 
Diminurion       We  now  inquire  whether  the  work  which  by  the 

of  super-  ,  -  ...  ...  „ 

ficiai  area^  transportation  of  particles  mto  the  interior  effects  a 
tivework.   diminution  of  the  surface-area  is  positive  or  negative, 
that  is,  whether  work  is  performed  or  work  is  ex- 
pended.    If  we  put  two  fluid  drops  in  contact,  they 

will  coalesce  of  their  own  accord; 
and  as  by  this  action  the  area 
of  the  surface  is  diminished,  it 
follows  that  the  work  that  pro- 
duces a  diminution  of  superfi- 
Fig.  aoi.  ^^^^  ^TQ^.  in  a  liquid  mass  is  posi- 

tive. Van  der  Mensbrugghe  has 
demonstrated  this  by  a  very  pretty  experiment.  A 
square  wire  frame  is  dipped  into  a  solution  of  soap  and 
water,  and  on  the  soap-film  formed  a  loop  of  moistened 
thread  is  placed.  If  the  film  within  the  loop  be  punc- 
tured, the  film  outside  the  loop  will  contract  till  the 
thread  bounds  a  circle  in  the  middle  of  the  liquid  sur- 
face. But  the  circle,  of  all  plane  figures  of  the  same 
circumference,  has  the  greatest  area  ;  consequently, 
the  liquid  film  has  contracted  to  a  minimum, 
conscguent       The   following  wiU  now  be  clear.     A  weightless 

condition       ,       .  ,  . 

of  liquid     Hquid,  the  forces  acting  on  which  are  molecular  forces, 

equiubrinm      ,  ,  .  .  . 

will  be  in  equilibrium  in  all  forms  in  which  a  system  of 
virtual  displacements  produces  no  alteration  of  the 
liquid's  superficial  area.   But  all  infinitely  small  changes 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES  387 

of  form  may  be  regarded  as  virtual  which  the  liquid 
admits  without  alteration  of  its  volume.  Consequently, 
equilibrium  subsists  for  all  liquid  forms'  for  which  an 
infinitely  small  deformation  produces  a  superficial  va- 
riation =  0.  For  a  given  volume  a  minimum  of  super- 
ficial area  gives  stable  equilibrium;  a  maximum  un- 
stable equilibrium. 

Among  all  solids  of  the  same  volume,  the  sphere 
has  the  least  superficial  area.  Hence,  the  form  which 
a  free  liquid  mass  will  assume,  the  form  of  stable  equi- 
librium, is  the  sphere.  For  this  form  a  maximum  of 
work  is  done ;  for  it,  no  more  can  be  done  If  the 
liquid  adheres  to  rigid  bodies,  the  form  assumed  is  de- 
pendent on  various  collateral  conditions,  which  render 
the  problem  more  complicated. 

3.  The  connection  between  the  sise  and  the/i^rm  of  Hodeofde- 
the  liquid  surface  may  be  investigated  as  follows.  We  the  connec- 
tmagine  the  closed  outer  sur-  liieand 

face  of   the  liquid  to  receive  «  liquid  lu- 

without  alteration  of  the  li- 
quid's volume  an  infinitely 
small  variation.  By  two  sets  of 
mutually  perpendicular  lines 
of  curvature,  we  cut   up  the 

original  surface  into  infinitely  small  rectangular  ele- 
ments. At  the  angles  of  these  elements,  on  the  original 
surface,  we  erect  normals  to  the  surface,  and  determine 
thus  the  angles  of  the  corresponding  elements  of  the 
varied  surface.  To  every  element  dO  of  the  original 
surface  there  now  corresponds  an  element  dO'  of  the 
varied  surface  ;  by  an  infinitely  small  displacement,  Sn, 
along  the  normal,  outwards  or  inwards,  t/0  passes  into 
40'  and  into  a  corresponding  variation  of  magnitude. 

Let  dfi,  dq  be  the  sides  of  the  element  dO.  For  the 


388 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 


The  mathe- sides  dp\  dq'  of  the  element  dO\  then,  these  relations 

velopment    obtain 
of  this 

method.  f  ^     ^     Sn 

dp'  =  dp\\+-^- 


dq'  =  dg[l-{- 


Sn 


where  r  and  r  are  the  radii  of  curvature  of  the  princi- 
pal sections  touching  the  elements  of  the  lines  of  cur- 
vature /,  q,  or  the  so-called  principal  radii  of  curva- 
ture. *  The  radius  of  curvature  of  an  outwardly  convex 
element  is  reckoned  as  positive,  that  of  an  outwardly 
concave  element  as  negative,  in  the  usual  manner.  For 
the  variation  of  the  element  we  obtain,  accordingly. 


6.dO  =  dO'  —  dO  =  dpdg[l+~ 


6  n 


Neglecting  the  higher  powers  of  <y«  we 
get 

6.dO  =  y    +~A6n,dO, 

The   variation   of    the   whole   surface, 
then,  is  expressed  by 


60 


=/(i+i 


Sn.dO 


(1) 


Fig.  203. 


Furthermore,  the  normal  displacements 
must  be  so  chosen  that 

J6n.dO  =  ^ (2) 

that  is,  they  must  be  such  that  the  sum  of  the  spaces 
produced  by  the  outward  and  inward  displacements  of 

*  The  normal  at  any  point  of  a  surface  is  cut  by  normals  at  infinitely  neigh- 
boring  points  that  lie  in  two  directions  on  the  surface  from  the  original  point, 
these  two  directions  being  at  right  angles  to  each  other ;  and  the  distances 
from  the  surface  at  which  these  normals  cut  are  the  two  principal,  or  extreme, 
radii  of  curvature  of  the  surface. — Trans. 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES,  389 

the  superficial  elements  (in  the  latter  case  reckoned  as 
negative)  shall  be  equal  to  zero,  or  the  volume  remain 
constant. 

Accordingly,  expressions  (i)  and  (2)  can  be  put  a  condition 

on  whicli 

simultaneously  =  0  only  if  i/r  +  i/r'  \i^s  the  same  value  ^^ffiXiet7L\- 
for  all  points  of  the  surface.    This  will  be  readily  seen  pressions 
from  the  following  consideration.     Let  the  elements  depends.' 
dO  of  the  original  surface  be  symbolically  represented 
by  the  elements  of  the  line  AX  (Fig.  204)  and  let  the 
normal   displacements   (^/r  be   erected    as    ordinates 
thereon  in  the  plane  E^  the  outward  displacements  up- 
wards as  positive  and  the  inward  displacements  down- 
wards  as    negative. 
Join  the  extremities  E 

of  these  ordinates  so 
as  to  form  a  curve, 
and  take  the  quadra- 
ture of    the    curve, 
reckoning    the    sur- 
face above  AX  sls  positive  and  that  below  it  as  nega- 
tive.    For  all  systems  oi  dn  for  which  this  quadra- 
ture =  0,  the  expression  (2)  also  :=  0,  and  all  such 
systems  of  displacements  are  admissible,  that  is,  are 
virtual  displacements. 

Now  let  us  erect  as  ordinates,  in  the  plane  E',  the 
values  of  i  /^  +  i  /^  that  belong  to  the  elements  dO.  A 
case  may  be  easily  imagined  in  which  the  expressions 
(i)  and^2)  assume  coincidently  the  value  zero.  Should, 
however,  i  /r  -f  ^/^  have  different  values  for  different 
elements,  it  will  always  be  possible  without  altering 
the  zero-value  of  the  expression  (2),  so  to  distribute 
the  displacements  6n  that  the  expression  (i)  shall  be 
different  from  zero.  Only  on  the  condition  that  i/r  -\- 
i/r'  has  the  same  value  for  all  the  elements,  is  expres- 


Fig.  ao4. 


390  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

sion  (i)  necessarily  and   universally  equated   to  zero 
with  expression  (2). 
The  sum  Accordingly,  from  the  two  conditions  (i)  and  (2)  it 

which  for      ,    ,,  i         ^   /       ,     ^   /    ,  i         •  , 

equilibrium  follows  that  l/r  +  1/r  =  const  \  that  IS  to  say,  the  sum 
constant  for  of  the  reciprocal  values  of  the  principal  radii  of  curva- 
surface.      ture,  or  of  the  radii  of  curvature  of  the  principal  nor- 
mal sections,  is,  in  the  case  of  equilibrium,  constant 
for  the  whole  surface.  By  this  theorem  the  dependence 
of  the  area  of  a  liquid  surface  on  its  superficial /^rm  is 
defined.     The  train  of   reasoning  here  pursued  was 
first  developed  by  Gauss,*  in  a  much  fuller  and  more 
special  form.     It  is  not  difficult,  however,  to  present 
its  essential  points  in  the  foregoing  simple  manner. 
Application       4.  A  liquid  mass,  left  wholly  to  itself,  assumes,  as 

of  this  gen- 

erai  condi-  we  have  Seen,  the  spherical  form,  and  presents  an  ab- 
interrupted  solute  minimum  of  superficial  area.     The  equation 

liquid  mas-  ,  ,    .  , 

ses.  V''  +  1/r'  =  const  is  here  visibly  fulfilled  in  the  form 

7.IR  =  const,  Jl  being  the  radius  of  the  sphere.  If  the 
free  surface  of  the  liquid  mass  be  bounded  by  two  solid 
circular  rings,  the  planes  of  which  are  parallel  to  each 
other  and  perpendicular  to  the  line  joining  their  mid- 
dle points,  the  surface  of  the  liquid  mass  will  assume 
the  form  of  a  surface  of  revolution.  The  nature  of  the 
meridian  curve  and  the  volume  of  the  enclosed  mass 
are  determined  by  the  radius  of  the  rings  J?,  by  the 
distance  between  the  circular  planes,  and  by  the  value 
of  the  expression  1/r  +  V'''  ^^^  *^®  surface  of  revolu- 
tion.    When 

r^  r'        r  ^00  ""7?' 

the  surface  of  revolution  becomes  a  cylindrical  surface. 
For  1/r  +  l/r'=  0,  where  one  normal  section  is  con- 

*  Principia  Generalia   Theoria  Figura  Flnidorutn  in  Statu  /Sguilibrii, 
GOttingen,  1830 ;  Werkt,  Vol.  V,  29,  GAttingen,  2867. 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.  391 

vex  and  the  other  concave,  the  meridian  curve  assumes 
the  form  of  the  catenary;  Plateau  visibly  demonstrated 
these  cases  by  pouring  oil  on  two  circular  rings  of  wire 
fixed  in  the  mixture  of  alcohol  and  water  above  men- 
tioned. 

Now  let   us   picture  to  ourselves  a   liquid    mass  Liquid  mas- 
ses whose 
bounded   by  surface-parts  for  which  the  expression  surfaces  are 

partly  con- 

1/r -f  lA'  has  a  positive  value,  and  by  other  parts  cave  and 
for  which  the  same  expression  has  a  negative  value,  vex. 
or,  more  briefly  expressed,  by  convex  and  concave  sur- 
faces. It  will  be  readily  seen  that  any  displacement 
of  the  superficial  elements  outwards  along  the  normal 
will  produce  in  the  concave  parts  a  diminution  of  the 
superficial  area  and  in  the  convex  parts  an  increase. 
Consequently,  work  is  performed  when  concave  surfaces 
move  outwards  and  convex  surfaces  inwards.  Work 
also  is  performed  when  a  superficial  portion  moves 
outwards  for  which  1/r  -|-  1/r'  =  -|-  a,  while  simulta- 
neously an  equal  superficial  portion  for  which  1  /r  -f 
1/r'  >  tf  moves  inwards. 

Hence,  when  differently  curved  surfaces  bound  a 
liquid  mass,  the  convex  parts  are  forced  inwards  and 
the  concave  outwards  till  the  condition  1/r  +  l/r'  = 
const  is  fulfilled  for  the  entire  surface.  Similarly,  when 
a  connected  liquid  mass  has  several  isolated  surface- 
parts,  bounded  by  rigid  bodies,  the  value  of  the  ex- 
pression 1/r  +  1/r'  must,  for  the  state  of  equilibrium 
be  the  same  for  all  free  portions  of  the  surface. 

For  example,  if  the  space  between  the  two  circular  Experi- 
rings  in  the  mixture  of  alcohol  and  water  above  re-  illustration 
ferred  to,  be  filled  with  oil,  it  is  possible,  by  the  use  conditions. 
of  a  sufficient  quantity  of  oil,  to  obtain  a  cylindrical 
surface  whose  two  bases  are  spherical  segments.    The 
curvatures  of  the  lateral  and  basal  surfaces  will  accord- 


392  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

ingly  fulfil  the  condition  1/^  -|-  l/oo  =  1/p  -f  l/p>  or 
p  =  2R^  where  p  is  the  radius  of  the  sphere  and  R  that 
of  the  circular  rings.  Plateau  verified  this  conclusion 
by  experiment. 
Liquidmas-  5.  Let  US  now  studv  a  weightless  liquid  mass  which 
ing  a  hoi-    eucloses  a  hollow  space.  The  condition  that  1/r  -(-  1/r' 

low  space.      ,     ,,   ,  ,  1         r         1       •  •  •% 

shall  have  the  same  value  for  the  mtenor  and  exterior 
surfaces,  is  here  not  realisable.  On  the  contrary,  as 
this  sum  has  always  a  greater  positive  value  for  the 
closed  exterior  surface  than  for  the  closed  interior  sur- 
face, the  liquid  will  perform  work,  and,  flowing  from 
the  outer  to  the  inner  surface,  cause  the  hollow  space 
to  disappear.  If,  however,  the  hollow  space  be  occu- 
pied by  a  fluid  or  gaseous  substance  subjected  to  a  de- 
terminate pressure,  the  work  done  in  the  last-men- 
tioned process  can  be  counteracted  by  the  work  ex- 
pended to  produce  the  compression,  and  thus  equilib- 
rium may  be  produced. 
The  me-  Let  US  picture  to  ourselves  a  liquid  mass  confined 

chaDical 

properties  between  two  similar  and  similarly  situated  surfaces 

very  near  each  other.     A  bubble  is  such 
a  system.    Its  primary  condition  of  equi- 
librium is  the  exertion  of  an  excess  of 
pressure  by  the  inclosed    gaseous   con- 
tents.    If  the  sum   1/r  -|-  1/r'  has  the 
value  -4-  a  for  the  exterior  surface,  it  will 
have  for  the  interior  surface  very  nearly 
the  value  —  a,     A  bubble,  left  wholly  to  itself,  will  al- 
ways assume  the  spherical  form.    If  we  conceive  such 
a  spherical  bubble,  the  thickness  of  which  we  neglect, 
the  total    diminution  of  its  superficial  area,   on  the 
shortening  of  the  radius  r  by  dr^  will  be  16 rndr.     If, 
therefore,   in  the  diminution  of  the  surface  by  unit 
of  area  the  work  A  is  performed,  then  A  .i6mdr  will 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES,         393 

be  the  total  amount  of  work  to  be  compensated  for 
by  the  work  of  compression  /.4r2;r//r  expended  by 
the  pressure  /  on  the  inclosed  contents.  From  this 
follows  ^Ajr  :=/  ;  from  which  A  may  be  easily  calcu- 
lated if  the  measure  of  r  is  obtained  and  /  is  found  by 
means  of  a  manometer  introduced  in  the  bubble. 

An  open  spherical  bubble  cannot  subsist.      If  an  open 

bubbles. 

open  bubble  is  to  become  a  figure  of  equilibrium,  the 
sum  1/r  4-  1/r'  must  not  only  be  constant  for  each  of 
the  two  bounding  surfaces,  but  must  also  be  equal  for 
both.  Owing  to  the  opposite  curvatures  of  the  sur- 
faces, then,  1/r  -|-  1/r'  =  0.  Consequently,  r  =  —  r' 
for  all  points.  Such  a  surface  is  called  a  minimal  sur- 
face ;  that  is,  it  has  the  smallest  area  consistent  with 
its  containing  certain  closed  contours.  It  is  also  a  sur- 
face of  zero-sum  of  principal  curvatures ;  and  its  ele- 
ments, as  we  readily  see,  are  saddle-shaped.  Surfaces 
of  this  kind  are  obtained  by  constructing  closed  space- 
curves  of  wire  and  dipping  the  wire  into  a  solution  of 
soap  and  water.*  The  soap-film  assumes  of  its  own 
accord  the  form  of  the  curve  mentioned. 

6.  Liquid  figures  of  equilibrium,  made  up  of  thin  Plateau's 
films,  possess  a  peculiar  property.  The  work  of  the  uresofequi- 
forces  of  gravity  affects  the  entire  mass  of  a  liquid ; 
that  of  the  molecular  forces  is  restricted  to  its  super- 
ficial  film.  Generally,  the  work  of  the  forces  of  grav- 
ity preponderates.  But  in  thin  films  the  molecular 
forces  come  into  very  favorable  conditions,  and  it  is 
possible  to  produce  the  figures  in  question  without 
difficulty  in  the  open  air.  Plateau  obtained  them  by 
dipping  wire  polyhedrons  into  solutions  of  soap  and 
water.    Plane  liquid  films  are  thus  formed,  which  meet 

*  The  mathematical  problem  of  determining  such  a  surface,  when  the 
forms  of  the  wires  are  given,  is  called  Piattau's  Problem, — TVans. 


394  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS.  . 

one  another  at  the  edges  of  the  framework.  When 
thin  plane  films  are  so  joined  that  they  meet  at  a  hol- 
low edge,  the  law  1/r  +  1/r'  =  const  no  longer  holds 
for  the  liquid  surface,  as  this  sum  has  the  value  zero 
for  plane  surfaces  and  for  the  hollow  edge  a  very  large 
negative  value.  Conformably,  therefore,  to  the  views 
above  reached,  the  liquid  should  run  out  of  the  films, 
the  thickness  of  which  would  constantly  decrease,  and 
escape  at  the  edges.  This  is,  in  fact,  what  happens. 
But  when  the  thickness  of  the  films  has  decreased  to  a 
certain  point,  then,  for  physical  reasons,  which  are,  as 
it  appears,  not  yet  perfectly  known,  a  state  of  equilib- 
rium is  effected. 

Yet,  notwithstanding  the  fact  that  the  fundamental 
equation  l/r+l/^'  =  const  is  not  fulfilled  in  these  fig- 
ures, because  very'  thin  liquid  films,  especially  films  of 
viscous  liquids,  present  physical  conditions  somewhat 
different  from  those  on  which  our  original  suppositions 
were  based,  these  figures  present,  nevertheless,  in  all 
cases  a  minimum  of  superficial  area.  The  liquid  films, 
connected  with  the  wire  edges  and  with  one  another, 
always  meet  at  the  edges  by  threes  at  approximately 
equal  angles  of  120°,  and  by  fours  in  comers  at  approxi- 
mately equal  angles.  And  it  is  geometrically  demon- 
strable that  these  relations  correspond  to  a  minimum 
of  superficial  area.  In  the  great  diversity  of  phenom- 
ena here  discussed  but  one  fact  is  expressed,  namely 
that  the  molecular  forces  do  work,  positive  work,  when 
the  superficial  area  is  diminished. 
The  reason        7-  The  figurcs  of  equilibrium  which  Plateau  ob- 

the  forms  of.»jij.        •_         •  ii_j  •  i^*  t 

equilibrium  tamed  by  dippmg  wire  polyhedrons  m  solutions  of 
metrical,     soap,  form  Systems  of  liquid  films   presenting  a  re- 
markable symmetry.     The  question  accordingly  forces 
itself  upon  us.  What  has  equilibrium  to  do  with  sym- 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES. 


395 


metry  and  regularity  ?  The  explanation  is  obvious. 
In  every  symmetrical  system  every  deformation  that 
tends  to  destroy  the  symmetry  is  complemented  by  an 
equal  and  opposite  deformation  that  tends  to  restore  it. 
In  each  deformation  positive  or  negative  work  is  done. 
One  condition,  therefore,  though  not  an  absolutely 
sufficient  one,  that  a  maximum  or  minimum  of  work 
corresponds  to  the  form  of  equilibrium,  is  thus  sup- 
plied by  symmetry.  Regularity  is  successive  symme- 
try. There  is  no  reason,  therefore,  to  be  astonished 
that  the  forms  of  equilibrium  are  often  symmetrical 
and  regular. 

.    8.  The  science  of  mathematical  hydrostatics  arose  The  fiRTire 
in  connection  with  a  special  problem — that  of  the  figure 


FiR.  2o6. 

of  the  earth.  Physical  and  astronomical  data  had  led 
Newton  and  Huygens  to  the  view  that  the  earth  is  an 
oblate  ellipsoid  of  revolution.  Newton  attempted  to 
calculate  this  oblateness  by  conceiving  the  rotating 
earth  as  a  fluid  mass,  and  assuming  that  all  fluid  fila- 
ments drawn  from  the  surface  to  the  centre  exert  the 
same  pressure  on  the  centre.  Huvgens's  assumption 
was  that  the  directions  of  the  forces  are  perpendicular 
to  the  superficial  elements.  Bouguer  combined  both 
assumptions.  Clairauf,  finally  {Theorie  de  la  figure 
de  la  terre,  Paris,  1743),  pointed  out  that  the  fulfilment 
of  both  conditions  does  not  assure  the  subsistence  of 
equilibrium. 


396 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 


Clairaut's 
point  of 
view. 


Conditions 
of  equilib- 
riMm  of 
Clairaut's 
canals. 


Clairaut's  starting-point  is  this.  If  the  fluid  earth 
is  in  equilibrium,  we  may,  without  disturbing  its  equi- 
librium, imagine  any  portion  of  it  solidified.  Accord- 
ingly, let  all  of  it  be  solidified  but  a  canal  ABy  of  any 
form.  The  liquid  in  this  canal  must  also  be  in  equilib- 
rium. But  now  the  conditions  which  control  equilib- 
rium are  more  easily  investigated.  If  equilibrium  exists 
in  et^ery  imaginable  canal  of  this  kind,  then  the  entire 
mass  will  be  in  equilibrium.  Incidentally  Clairaut  re- 
marks, that  the  Newtonian  assumption  is  realised  when 
the  canal  passes  through  the  centre  (illustrated  in  Fig. 
206,  cut  2),  and  the  Huygenian  when  the  canal  passes 
along  the  surface  (Fig.  206,  cut  3). 

But  the  kernel  of  the  problem,  according  to  Clai- 
raut, lies  in  a  different  view.     In  all  imaginable  canals, 

Z 


Fig.  207.  Fig.  ao8. 

even  in  one  which  returns  into  itself,  the  fluid  must  be 
in  equilibrium.  Hence,  if  cross-sections  be  made  at 
any  two  points  M  and  N  of  the  canal  of  Fig.  207,  the 
two  fluid  columns  MPN  and  MQN  must  exert  on  the 
surfaces  of  section  at  J/ and  A^  equal  pressures.  The 
terminal  pressure  of  a  fluid  column  of  any  such  canal 
cannot,  therefore,  depend  on  the  length  and  the  form 
of  the  fluid  column,  but  must  depend  solely  on  the  po- 
sition of  its  terminal  points. 

Imagine  in  the  fluid  in  question  a  canal  MN  of  any 
form  (Fig.  208)  referred  to  a  system  of  rectangular  co- 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.  397 

ordinates.     Let  the  fluid  have  the  constant  density  p  Maihemai- 
and  let  the  force-components  X^  V,  Z  acting  on  unit  of  sion  of 
mass  of  the  fluid  in  the  coordinate  directions,  be  f unc-  ditions,  and 
tions  of  the  codrdinates  x,  y,  z  of  this  mass.     Let  the  quent  Ren- 
element  of  length  of  the  canal  be  called  dSf  and  let  its  tion  of 

,  1         1  ,         »        mi       e  liquid  equi- 

projections  on  the  axes  be  ax,  ay,  dz.  The  force-com-  libnum. 
ponents  acting  on  unit  of  mass  in  the  direction  of  the 
canal  are  then  X(dx/ds),  Y{dy/ds),  Z(jiz/ds).     Let 
q  be  the  cross-section  ;  then,  the  total  force  impelling 
the  element  of  mass  pqds  in  the  direction  ds,  is 

This  force  must  be  balanced  by  the  increment  of  pres- 
sure through  the  element  of  length,  and  consequently 
must  be  put  equal  to  q .  dp.  We  obtain,  accordingly, 
dp=i  p  {Xdx  +  Ydy  -|-  Zdzy  The  difference  of  pres- 
sure (/)  between  the  two  extremities  M  and  N  is  found 
by  integrating  this  expression  from  Mto  N,  But  as  this 
difference  is  not  dependent  on  the  form  of  the  canal 
but  solely  on  the  position  of  the  extremities  M  and  iV, 
it  follows  that  p^Xdx-^-  Ydy-^-  Zdz),  or,  the  density 
being  constant,  Xdx  +  Ydy  +  Zdz,  must  be  a  com- 
plete differential.     For  this  it  is  necessary  that 

y^dCr    ^_dU  dU 

^-di'  dy'  ^^dz' 

where  6^  is  a  function  of  coordinates.  Hence,  according 
to  Clairaut,  the  general  condition  of  liquid  equilibrium  is, 
that  the  liquid  be  controlled  by  forces  which  can  be  ex- 
pressed as  the  partial  differential  coefficients  of  one  and 
the  same  function  of  coordinates, 

9.  The  Newtonian  forces  of  gravity,  and  in  fact  all 
central  forces, — forces  that  masses  exert  in  the  direc- 
tions of  their  lines  of  junction  and  which  are  functions 


398  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

Character  of  the  distances  between  these  masses, — possess  this 
forces  property.  Under  the  action  of  forces  of  this  character 
produce      the  equilibrium  of  fluids  is  possible.     If  we  know  Uy 

equilibrium  «  i        /•  •         , 

we  may  replace  the  first  equation  by 

or 

dp  =  pdU  and  /  =  p^+  const. 

The  totality  of  all  the  points  for  which  1/=  const 
is  a  surface,  a  so-called  level  surface.  For  this  surface 
also  /  =  const.  As  all  the  force- relations,  and,  as  we 
how  see,  all  the  pressure-relations,  are  determined  by 
the  nature  of  the  function  6^,  the  pressure-relations, 
accordingly,  supply  a  diagram  of  the  force-relations, 
as  was  before  remarked  in  page  98. 
ciairaut's  In  the  theory  of  Clairaut,  here  presented,  is  con- 

eerni  of  the  tained,  bcyond  all  doubt,  the  idea  that  underlies  the 
potential,  doctrinc  of  force-function  or  potential,  which  was  after- 
wards developed  with  such  splendid  results  by  La- 
place, Poisson,  Green,  Gauss,  and  others.  As  soon 
as  our  attention  has  been  directed  to  this  property  of 
certain  forces,  namely,  that  they  can  be  expressed  as 
derivatives  of  the  same  function  U,  it  is  at  once  recog- 
nised as  a  highly  convenient  and  economical  course  to 
investigate  in  the  place  of  the  forces  themselves  the 
function  U. 

If  the  equation 

dp  =  p  {Xdx  -+-  Ydy  +  Zdz)  =  pdU 

be  examined,  it  will  be  seen  that  A'«&  +  Ydy  -\-  Zdz 
is  the  element  of  the  work  performed  by  the  forces  on 
unit  of  mass  of  the  fluid  in  the  displacement  ds,  whose 
projections  are  dx,  dy,  dz.  Consequently,  if  we  trans- 
port unit  mass  from  a  point  for  which  U^=  C^  to  an- 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.  399 

Other  point,  indifferently  chosen,  for  which  U  =  C,,  charactei^ 

r  rr         y-.  i       istics  of  the 

or,  more  generally,  from  the  surface  u=^C^  to  the  force-func- 
surface  C^=  C^,  we  perform,  no  matter  by  what  path 
the  conveyance  has  been  effected,  the  same  amount  of 
work.  All  the  points  of  the  first  surface  present,  with 
respect  to  those  of  the  second,  the  same  difference  of 
pressure  j  the  relation  always  being  such,  that 

where  the  quantities  designated  by  the  same  indices  • 
belong  to  the  same  surface. 

10.   Let  us  picture  to  ourselves  a  group  of  such  character- 
very  closely  adjacent  surfaces,  of  which  every  two  sue-  level,  or 
cessive  ones  differ  from  each  other  by  the  same,  very  tiai,  sur- 

faces. 

small,  amount  of  work  required  to  transfer  a  mass  from 
one  to  the  other  ;  in  other  words,  imagine  the  surfaces 
C/=  C,  U=  C+  dC,  U=  C+2dC,  and  so  forth. 

A  mass  moving  on  a  level  surface  evidently  per- 
forms no  work.     Hence,  every  component  force  in  a 
direction  tangential  to  the 
surface  is  =  0 ;  and  the  di- 
rection   of     the    resultant 
force  IS  everywhere  normal 
to  the  surface.  If  we  call  dn 
the  element  of  the  normal 
intercepted    between  two 
consecutive  surfaces,  andy 
the  force  requisite  to  con- 
vey unit    mass  from    the 
one  surface  to  the  other 
through  this  element,  the 

work  done  is/,  dn  =zd  C.  As  dC  is  by  hypothesis  every- 
where constant,  the  force  /=  dC/dn  is  inversely  pro- 
portional to  the  distance  between  the  surfaces  consid- 


400  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

ered.  If,  therefore,  the  surfaces  U  are  known,  the 
directions  of  the  forces  are  given  by  the  elements  of  a 
system  of  curves  everywhere  at  right  angles  to  these 
surfaces,  and  the  inverse  distances  between  the  sur- 
faces measure  the  magnitude  of  the  forces.  *  These  sur- 
faces and  curves  also  confront  us  in  the  other  depart- 
ments of  physics.  We  meet  them  as  equi potential 
surfaces  and  lines  of  force  in  electrostatics  and  mag- 
netism, as  isothermal  surfaces  and  lines  of  flow  in  the 
theory  of  the  conduction  of  heat,  and  as  equipotential 
surfaces  and  lines  of  flow  in  the  treatment  of  electrical 
and  liquid  currents, 
ninstration  II.  We  will  uow  illustrate  the  fundamental  idea  of 
ram's  doc-  Clairaut*s  doctrine  by  another,  very  simple  example. 

trine  by  a     _  .  ,,  i-      i  t  i 

simple  Imagme  two  mutually  perpendicular  planes  to  cut  the 
paper  at  right  angles  in  the  straight  lines  OX  and  O  Y 
(Fig.  210).  We  assume  that  a  force-function  exists 
6^=  —  xy^  where  x  and  7  are  the  distances  from  the 
two  planes.  The  force-components  parallel  to  OX  and 
dPKare  then  respectively 


and 


y      dU 


y  =  -—  =  —  X. 

dy 


*  The  same  conclasion  may  be  reached  as  follows.  Imagine  a  water  pipe 
laid  from  New  York  to  Key  West,  with  its  ends  turning  up  vertically,  and  of 
glass.  Let  a  quantity  of  water  be  poured  into  it,  and  when  equilibrium  is 
attained,  let  its  height  be  marked  on  the  glass  at  both  ends.  These  two  marks 
will  be  on  one  level  surface.  Now  pour  in  a  little  more  water  and  again  mark 
the  heights  at  both  ends.  The  additional  water  in  New  York  balances  the 
additional  water  in  Key  West.  The  gravity  of  the  two  are  equal.  But  their 
quantities  are  proportional  to  the  vertical  distances  between  the  marks. 
Hence,  the  f<;^rce  of  gravity  on  a  fixed  quantity  of  water  is  inversely  as  those 
vertical  distances,  that  is,  inversely  as  the  distances  between  consecutive 
level  surfaces.— TVamx 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES. 


401 


The  level  surfaces  are  cylindrical  surfaces,  whose 
generating  lines  are  at  right  angles  to  the  plane  of  the 
paper,  and  whose  directrices,  xy  =  const,  are  equi- 
lateral hyperbolas.  The  lines  of  force  are  obtained  by 
turning  the  first  mentioned  system  of  curves  through 
an  angle  of  45°  in  the  plane  of  the  paper  about  O,  If 
a  unit  of  mass  pass 
from  the  point  rtoO  ^ 

by  the  route  rpO,  or 
r^O,  or  by  any  other 
route,  the  work  done 
is  always  Op  Y.  Oq. 
If  we  imagine  a 
closed  canal  OprqO 
filled  with  a  liquid, 
the  liquid  in  the  ca- 
nal will  be  in  equi- 
librium. If  transverse 
sections  be  made  at 
any  two  pomts,  each 

section  will   sustain   at   both   its   surfaces   the   same 
pressure. 

We  will  now  modify  the  example  slightly.  Let  the  a  modifica 
forces  be  A'=  — 7,  K=  —  «,  where  a  has  a  constant  example, 
value.  There  exists  now  no  function  U  so  constituted 
that  X^  dUjdx  and  K=  dUjdy  ;  for  in  such  a  case  it 
would  be  necessary  that  dX/dy  =  d  Y/dx,  which  is  ob- 
viously not  true.  There  is  therefore  no  force- function, 
and  consequently  no  level  surfaces.  If  unit  of  mass 
be  transported  from  r  to  Ohy  the  way  of  /,  the  work 
done  is  «  X  Oq.  If  the  transportation  be  effected  by 
the  route  rqO,  the  work  done  is  «  X  Oq  ■\-  Op  y,  Oq. 
If  the  canal  OprqO  were  filled  with  a  liquid,  the  liquid 
could  not  be  'in  equilibrium,  but  would  be  forced  to 


402  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

rotate  constantly  in  the  direction  OprqO,  Currents  of 
this  character,  which  revert  into  themselves  but  con- 
tinue their  motion  indefinitely,  strike  us  as  something 
quite  foreign  to  our  experience.  Our  attention,  how- 
ever, is  directed  by  this  to  an  important  property  of 
the  forces  of  nature,  to  the  property,  namely,  that  the 
work  of  such  forces  may  be  expressed  as  a  function  of 
coordinates.  Whenever  exceptions  to  this  principle 
are  observed,  we  are  disposed  to  regard  them  as  appa- 
rent, and  seek  to  clear  up  the  difficulties  involved. 
Torricciii'8  12.  We  shall  now  examine  a  few  problems  of  liquid 
on  the  veio-  motion.  The  founder  of  the  theory  of  hydrodynamics  is 
quid  efflui.  ToRRiCELLi.  Torricelli,*  by  observations  on  liquids  dis- 
charged through  orifices  in  the  bottom  of  vessels,  dis- 
covered the  following  law.  If  the  time  occupied  in  the 
complete  discharge  of  a  vessel  be  divided  into  n  equal 
intervals,  and  the  quantity  discharged  in  the  last,  the 
«'*»,  interval  be  taken  as  the  unit,  there  will  be  dis- 
charged in  the  («  —  1)^,  the  (« —  2y*>,  the(« — 3)^** 

interval,  respectively,  the  quantities  3,  5,  7 ...  .  and 
so  forth.  An  analogy  between  the  motion  of  falling 
bodies  and  the  motion  of  liquids  is  thus  clearly  sug- 
gested. Further,  the  perception  is  an  immediate  one, 
that  the  most  curious  consequences  would  ensue  if  the 
liquid,  by  its  reversed  velocity  of  efflux,  could  rise 
higher  than  its  original  level.  Torricelli  remarked, 
in  fact,  that  it  can  rise  at  the  utmost  to  this  height, 
and  assumed  that  it  would  rise  exactly  as  high  if  all 
resistances  could  be  removed.  Hence,  neglecting  all 
resistances,  the  velocity  of  efflux,  Vy  of  a  liquid  dis- 
charged through  an  orifice  in  the  bottom  of  a  vessel  is 
connected  with  the  height  h  of  the  surface  of  the  liquid 
by  the  equation  r  =  1^2^// ;  that  is  to  say,  the  velocity 

*  Dt  Motn  Cravium  Proftctorum^  1643. 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES,         403 

of  efflux  is  the  final  velocity  of  a  body  freely  falling 
through  the  height  h^  or  liquid-head ;  for  only  with 
this  velocity  can  the  liquid  just  rise  again  to  the  sur- 
face.* 

Torricelli's  theorem  consorts  excellently  with  the»varignon'« 

deduction 

rest  of  our  knowledge  of  natural  processes ;  but  we  of  the  veio- 
feel,  nevertheless,  the  need  of  a  more  exact  insight.  eMux. 
Varignon  attempted  to  deduce  the  principle  from  the 
relation  between  force  and  the  momentum  generated  by 
force.  The  familiar  equation  pi  =:mv  gives,  if  by  a 
we  designate  the  area  of  the  basal  orifice,  by  h  the 
pressure-head  of  the  liquid,  by  s  its  specific  gravity, 
by  g  the  acceleration  of  a  freely  falling  body,  by  v  the 
velocity  of  efflux,  and  by  t  a  small  interval  of  time, 
this  result 

ahs .  T  :^ .  V  or  v^  =^zh, 

g 

Here  ahs  represents  the  pressure  acting  during  the 

time  T  on  the  liquid  mass  avrs/g.   Remembering  that 

z^  is  a  final  velocity,  we  get,  more  exactly, 

V 

,  a    -  .  TS 

ahs  .  r  =      2  .Vy 

g  ~ 
and  thence  the  correct  formula 

v^  =2gh, 

13.  Daniel  Bernoulli  investigated  the  motions  of 
fluids  by  the  principle  of  vis  viva.  We  w?ll  now  treat 
the  preceding  case  from  this  point  of  view,  only  ren- 
dering the  idea  more  modern.  The  equation  which  we 
employ  is/j  =  mv^ Ji,  In  a  vessel  of  transverse  sec- 
tion q  (Fig.  211),  into  which  a  liquid  of  the  specific 

*  The  early  inquirers  deduce  their  propositions  in  the  incomplete  form  of 
proportions,  and  therefore  usually  put  v  proportional  to  ^gk  or  ^X. 


4<M 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHAXICS, 


Daniel  Ber-  gravity  s  is  poured  till  the  head  h  is  reached,  the  surface 

treatment    sinks,  say,  the  small  distance  dh,  and  the  liquid  mass 

problem,     q.  dh,  s/g  IS  discharged  with  the  velocity  v»  The  work 

done  is  the  same  as  though  the  weight  q,  dh,s  had 

descended  the  distance  h.     The  path  of  the  motion  in 

the  vessel  is  not  of  consequence  here.     It  makes  no 

difference  whether  the  stratum  q .  dh 
is  discharged  directly  through  the 
basal  orifice,  or  passes,  say,  to  a 
position  a,  while  the  liquid  at  a  is 
displaced  to  ^,  that  at  b  displaced  to 
c,  and  that  at  c  discharged.  The  work 
done  is  in  each  case  q  ,  dh  .  s  .  h. 
Equating  this  work  to  the  vis  viva  of  the  discharged 
liquid,  we  get 


Fig.  311. 


q  ,  dh  .  s  ,  h=z~ 


dh 
g 


s  v^ 


or 


v  =  V'2,gh, 

The  sole  assumption  of  this  argument  is  that  all 

the  work  done  in  the  vessel  appears  as  vis  viva  in  the 

liquid  discharged,  that  is  to  say,  that  the  velocities 

within  the  vessel  and  the  work  spent  in  overcoming 

friction  therein  may  be  neglected.     This  assumption  is 

not  very  far  from  the  truth  if  vessels  of  sufficient  width 

are  employed,  and  no  violent  rotatory  motion  is  set  up. 

The  law  of         Let  US  ueglect  the  gravity  of  the  liquid  in  the  ves- 

w%en  pro^*  sel,  and  imagine  it  loaded  by  a  movable  piston,  on 

th*e^pres^    whosc  surface-unit  the  pressure  /  falls.     If  the  piston 

fill  re  of 

pistons.  be  displaced  a  distance  dh,  the  liquid  volume  q .  dh 
will  be  discharged.  Denoting  the  density  of  the  liquid 
by  p  and  its  velocity  by  Vy  we  then  shall  have 


q.p.dh=:q.dh,p  ^^  ,  or  7'  =  ^ 


2/ 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.         405 

Wherefore,  under  the  same  pressure,  different  liquids 
are  discharged  with  velocities  inversely  proportional  to 
the  square  root  of  their  density.  It  is  generally  sup> 
posed  that  this  theorem  is  directly  applicable  to  gases. 
Its  form^  indeed,  is  correct ;  but  the  deduction  fre- 
quently employed  involves  an  error,  which  we  shall 
now  expose. 

14.  Two  vessels  (Fig.  212)  of  equal  cross-sections  The  appii- 

^  V      o  /  ^  cation  of 

are  placed  side  by  side  and  connected  with  each  other  this  last  re 

salt  to  the 

by  a  small  aperture  in  the  base  of  their  dividing  walls,  flow  of 
For  the  velocity  of  flow  through  this  aperture  we  ob- 
tain, under  the  same  suppositions  as  before, 

If  we  neglect  the  gravity  of  the  liquid  and  imagine 
the  pressures  p^  and  /^  produced  by  pistons,  we  shall 
similarly  have  v=iV  2(/,  — P'^lP-  For  example,  if  the 
pistons  employed  be  loaded  with  the  weights  P  and 
7^/2,  the  weight  P  will  sink  the  distance  h  and  PJT, 
will  rise  the  distance  //.  The  work  (^P/2)h  is  thus  left, 
to  generate  the  vis  viva  of  the  effluent  fluid. 

A  gas  under  such  circumstances  would  behave  dif-  The  behav- 
ferently.     Supposing  the  gas  to  flow  from  the  vessel  eas  under 
containing  the  load  /'into  that  contain-  snmed  con- 

ing the  load  P/2,  the  first  weight  will      ^"L— J^^    T 
fall  a  distance  //,  the  second,  however,        px?|        I 
since  under  half  the  pressure  a  gas  dou-        Ep^SppM^ 
bles  its  volume,  will  rise  a  distance  2  //,        p— A  ~^ 
so  that  the  work  Ph  —  (/'/2)  2^  =  0       E^:?! ~  J 
would  be  performed.     In  the  case  of         „. 

*         ^  Fig.  212. 

gases,    accordingly,    some    additional 
work,  competent  to  produce  the  flow  between  the  vessels 
must  be  performed.  This  work  the  gas  itself  performs, 
by  expanding,  and  by  overcoming  by  its  force  of  expan- 


406  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

The  result  siofi  a  pressurc.  The  expansive  force  /  and  the  volume 
form  but     w  oi  9l  gas  Stand  to  each  other  in  the  familiar  relation 

differentia  .1.1  t  ^     « 

maKoitude./ttf  =>e,  where  ki  SO  long  as  the  temperature  of  the 
gas  remains  unchanged,  is  a  constant.  Supposing  the 
volume  of  the  gas  to  expand  under  the  pressure  /  by 
an  amount  dw^  the  work  done  is 

For  an  expansion  from  w^  to  w,  or  for  an  increase  of 
pressure  from  /^  to  /,  we  get  for  the  work 

Conceiving  by  this  work  a  volume  of  gas  w^  of 
density  p,  moved  with  the  velocity  i>,  we  obtain 

/2/„  log 

V  p 

The  velocity  of  efflux  is,  accordingly,  in  this  case  also 
inversely  proportional  to  the  square  root  of  the  density ; 
Its  magnitude,  however,  is  not  the  same  as  in  the  case 
of  a  liquid, 
incom-  But  even  this  last  view  is  very  defective.     Rapid 

this  view,  changes  of  the  volumes  of  gases  are  always  accom- 
panied with  changes  of  temperature,  and,  consequently 
also  with  changes  of  expansive  force.  For  this  reason, 
questions  concerning  the  motion  of  gases  cannot  be 
dealt  with  as  questions  of  pure  mechanics,  but  always 
involve  questions  of  heat,  [Nor  can  even  a  thermo- 
dynamical  treatment  always  suffice :  it  is  sometimes 
necessary  to  go  back  to  the  consideration  of  molecular 
motions.] 

15.  The  knowledge  that  a  compressed  gas  contains 
stored- up  work,  naturally  suggests  the  inquiry,  whether 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.         40J 

this  is  not  also  true  of  compressed  liquids.    As  a  mat-  Relative 

volumes  of 

ter  of  fact,  every  liquid  under  pressure  s's  compressed,  compressed 

ffsses  and 

To  effect  compression  work  is  requisite,  which  reap-  fiquids. 
pears  the  moment  the  liquid  expands.  But  this  work, 
in  the  case  of  the  mobile  liquids,  is  very  small.  Imag- 
ine, in  Fig.  213,  a  gas  and  a  mobile  liquid  of  the  same 
volume,  measured  by  OA,  subjected  to  the  same  pres- 
sure, a  pressure  of  one  atmosphere,  designated  b}'  AB. 
If  the  pressure  be  reduced  to  one-half  an  atmosphere, 
the  volume  of  the  gas  will  be  doubled,  while  that  of 
the  liquid  will  be  increased  by  only  about  25  millionths. 
The  expansive  work  of  the  gas  is  represented  by  the 
surface  ABDC,  that  of  the  liquid  by  ABLK^  where 


Fig.  213. 

AJC=0'00002^0A.  If  the  pressure  decrease  till  it 
become  zero,  the  total  work  of  the  liquid  is  represented 
by  the  surface  AB/,  where  A/=  ooooo^OA,  and  the 
total  work  of  the  gas  by  the  surface  contained  between 
AB,  the  infinite  straight  line  ACEG  .  .  .  .,  and  the 
infinite  hyperbola  branch  BDFH .  .  .  .  Ordinarily, 
therefore,  the  work  of  expansion  of  liquids  may  be 
neglected.  There  are  however  phenomena,  for  ex- 
ample, the  soniferous  vibrations  of  liquids,  in  which 
work  of  this  very  order  plays  a  principal  part.  In  such 
cases,  the  changes  of  temperature  the  liquids  undergo 
must  also  be  considered.  We  thus  see  that  it  is  only 
by  a  fortunate  concatenation  of  circumstances  that  we 
are  at  liberty  to  consider  a  phenomenon  with  any  close 


4o8 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 


approximation  to  the  truth  as  a  mere  matter  of  molar 
mechanics. 
The  hydro-        1 6.  We  now  come  to  the  idea  which  Daniel  Ber- 

dynamic 

principle     NOULLi  sought  to  apply  in  his  work  Hydrodynamica^  sive 

of  Daniel 

Bernoulli,  de  Viribus  et  Motibus  Fluidorutn  Commentarii  {iT^B^). 
When  a  liquid  sinks,  the  space  through  which  its  cen- 
tre of  gravity  actually  descends  {descensus  actualis)  is 
equal  to  the  space  through  which  the  centre  of  gravity 
of  the  separated  parts  affected  with  the  velocities  ac- 
quired in  the  fall  can  ascend  {ascensus  potentialis).  This 
idea,  we  see  at  once,  is  identical  with  that  employed 
by  Huygens.     Imagine  a  vessel  filled  with  a  liquid 

(Fig.  214) ;  and  let  its  horizontal  cross- 
section  at  the  distance  x  from  the  plane 
of  the  basal  orifice,  be  called /(.x).  Let 
the  liquid  move  and  its  surface  descend 
a  distance  dx.  The  centre  of  gravity, 
then,  descends  the  distance  x/{x) .  dx/M, 
where  M=  f/(,x)  dx.  If  k  is  the  space  of 
potential  ascent  of  the  liquid  in  a  cross- 
section  equal  to  unity,  the  space  of  po- 
tential ascent  in  the  cross-section /(:r)  will  heJf://(x)^, 
and    the  space  of  potential  ascent  of  the  centre  of 


/fjcj 


\ 

-"/dx 

^-?— ? 

.-rJ 

-~-  -\ 

f-  —  —   - 

_   ..  1  1 

m-     -      — 

-    —  —  —% 

r    —    —    ■ 

-  —  .  f 

%~    ~   ~ 

-   _  _  -M 

m~ 

—   -  .  J 

^fc~   —  , 

_  _  -^ 

%-  - 

_   _  W 

%-~ 

=^ 

Fig.  ai4. 


gravity  will  be 


'X 


dx 


M 


=  k 


N 


where 


N 


=x 


dx 


For  the  displacement  of  the  liquid's  surface  through  a 
distance  dx,  we  get,  by  the  principle  assumed,  both 
iVand  k  changing,  the  equation 

—  xf{x)  dx  =  Ndk  +  kdN. 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES, 


409 


This  equation  was  employed  by  Bernoulli  in  the  solu-  The  parai- 
tion  of  various  problems.  It  will  be  easily  seen,  that  strata. 
Bernoulli's  principle  can  be  employed  with  success 
only  when  the  relative  velocities  of  the  single  parts  of 
the  liquid  are  known.  Bernoulli  assumes, — an  assump- 
tion apparent  in  the  formulae, — that  all  particles  once 
situated  in  a  horizontal  plane,  continue  their  motion 
in  a  horizontal  plane,  and  that  the  velocities  in  the 
different  horizontal  planes  are  to  each  other  in  the  in- 
verse ratio  of  the  sections  of  the  planes.  This  is  the 
assumption  of  the  parallelism  of  strata.  It  does  not,  in 
many  cases,  agree  with  the  facts,  and  in  others  its 
agreement  is  incidental.  When  the  vessel  as  compared 
with  the  orifice  of  efHux  is  very  wide,  no  assumption 
concerning  the  motions  within  the  vessel  is  necessary, 
as  we  saw  in  the  development  of  Torricelli's  theorem. 

17.    A  few  isolated  cases  of  liquid  motion  were  The  water- 

-    ,       __  ,    _  __  ___       ,     ,,  pendnlum 

treated  by  Newton  and  John  Bernoulli.  We  shall  of  Newton, 
consider  here  one  to  which  a 
familiar  law  is  directly  applic- 
able. A  cylindrical  U-tube  with 
vertical  branches  is  filled  with 
a  liquid  (Fig.  215).  The  length 
of  the  entire  liquid  column  is  /. 
If  in  one  of  the  branches  the 
column  be  forced  a  distance  x 
below  the  level,   the  column  in 

the  other  branch  will  rise  the  distance  x,  and  the 
difference  of  level  corresponding  to  the  excursion  x 
will  be  2  jr.  If  or  is  the  transverse  section  of  the  tube 
and  s  the  liquid's  specific  gravity,  the  force  brought 
into  play  when  the  excursion  x  is  made,  will  be  ^asx, 
which,  since  it  must  move  a  mass  otls/gviiW  determine 
the  acceleration  (2  asx)/{als/g)  =  {2g/l)  x,  or,  for  unit 


Fig.  215. 


Bernoulli. 


410  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

excursion,   the  acceleration  2^//.     We  perceive  that 
pendulum  vibrations  of  the  duration 

will  take  place.     The  liquid  column,  accordingly,  vi- 
brates the  same  as  a  simple  pendulum  of  half  the  length 
of  the  column. 
The  liquid         A  similar,  but  somewhat  more  general,  problem  was 

pendulum 

of  John       treated  by  John  Bernoulli.     The  two  branches  of  a 
cylindrical  tube  (Fig.  216),  curved  in  any  manner,  make 

with  the  horizon,  at  the 
points    at    which    the 
surfaces   of   the  liquid 
move,     the     angles    a 
and  p.    Displacing  one 
of  the  surfaces  the  dis- 
tance x^  the  other  sur- 
face  suffers    an   equal 
displacement.     A  difference  of  level  is  thus  produced 
X  (sin  a  -\-  sin/?),  and  we  obtain,  by  a  course  of  reason- 
ing similar  to  that  of  the  preceding  case,  employing 
the  same  symbols,  the  formula 


Fig.  2x6. 


=  "\l. 


/ 

(^  (sin  or  -f  sin/^)  * 

The  laws  of  the  pendulum  hold  true  exactly  for  the 
liquid  pendulum  of  Fig.  215  (viscosity  neglected),  even 
for  vibrations  of  great  amplitude  ;  while  for  the  filar 
pendulum  the  law  holds  only  approximately  true  for 
small  excursions. 

18.  The  centre  of  gravity  of  a  liquid  as  a  whole  can 
rise  only  as  high  as  it  would  have  to  fall  to  produce  its 
velocities.  In  every  case  in  which  this  principle  appears 
to  present  an  exception,  it  can  be  shown  that  the  excep- 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.         411 

tion  is  only  apparent.    One  example  Js  Hero's  fountain.  Hewi 

This  apparatus,  as  we  know,  consists  of  three  vessels, 

which  may  be  designated  in  the  descending  order  as 

A,  B,  C.    The  water  in  the  open  vessel  A 

falls  through  a  tubt 

C ;  the  air  displace' 

on  the  water  in  th 

this  pressure  force 

jet  above  A  wheni 

original  level.     Thi 

true,  considerably 

but  in   actuality  it 

circuitous  route  of 

vessel  A  to  the  mu 

Another    ap-  b*"'"?,'''* 

parent  exception  dnoiic 

,  to  the  principle  . 
in  question  is 
that  of  Montgol- 
fier's  hydraulic 
ram,in  which  the 
liquid  by  its  own 
gravitational 
work  appears  to 
rise  considerably 
above  its  original 
level.  The  liquid 
flows  (Fig.  217) 

from  a  cistern  A  p, 

through  a   long 

pipe  RR  and  a  valve  V,  which  opens  inwards,  into  a 
vessel  B.  When  the  current  becomes  rapid  enough,  the 
valve  V  is  forced  shut,  and  a  liquid  mass  m  affected  with 
the  velocity  ?'  is  suddenly  arrested  in  RR,  which  must 


412 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 


be  deprived  of  its  momentum.  If  this  be  done  in  the 
time  /,  the  liquid  can  exert  during  this  time  a  pressure 
qz=imv/tj  to  which  must  be  added  its  hydrostatical 
pressure  p.  The  liquid,  therefore,  will  be  able,  during 
this  interval  of  time,  to  penetrate  with  a  pressure  p  -{-  q 
through  a  second  valve  into  a  pila  HeroniSy  H^  and  in 
consequence  of  the  circumstances  there  existing  will 
rise  to  a  higher  level  in  the  ascension-tube  55  than 
that  corresponding  to  its  simple  pressure  /.  It  is 
to  be  observed  here,  that  a  considerable  portion  of  the 
liquid  must  first  flow  off  into  By  before  a  velocity  requi- 
site to  close  V\s  produced  by  the  liquid's  work  in  RR, 
A  small  portion  only  rises  above  the  original  level  \ 
the  greater  portion  flows  from  A  into  B,  If  the  liquid 
discharged  from  55  were  collected,  it  could  be  easily 
proved  that  the  centre  of  gravity  of  the  quantity  thus 
discharged  and  of  that  received  in  B  lay,  as  the  result 
of  various  losses,  actually  below  the  level  of  A, 

The  principle  of  the  hydraulic  ram,  that  of  the 


An  illastra- 

elucidates  transference  of  work  done  by  a  large  liquid  mass  to  a 

the  action 
of  the  hy- 
draulic ram 

10 


smaller  one,  which 
thus  acquires  a  great 
vis  viva^  may  be  illus- 
trated in  the  following 
very  simple  manner. 
Close  the  narrow 
opening  (7  of  a  funnel 
and  plunge  it,  with  its 
wide  opening  down- 
wards, deep  into  a 
large  vessel  of  water.  If  the  finger  closing  the  upper 
opening  be  quickly  removed,  the  space  inside  the 
funnel  will  rapidly  fill  with  water,  and  the  surface  of  the 
water  outside  the  funnel  will  sink.  The  work  performed 


Fig.  ai8. 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.         413 

is  equivalent  to  the  descent  of  the  contents  of  the  funnel 
from  the  centre  of  gravity  S  of  the  superficial  stratum 
to  the  centre  of  gravity  *S"  of  the  contents  of  the  fun- 
nel. If  the  vessel  is  sufficiently  wide  the  velocities  in 
it  are  all  very  small,  and  almost  the  entire  vis  viva  is 
concentrated  in  the  contents  of  the  funnel.  If  all  the 
parts  of  the  contents  had  the  same  velocities,  they 
could  all  rise  to  the  original  level,  or  the  mass  as  a 
whole  could  rise  to  the  height  at  which  its  centre  of 
gravity  was  coincident  with  S,  But  in  the  narrower 
sections  of  the  funnel  the  velocity  of  the  parts  is 
greater  than  in  the  wider  sections,  and  the  former 
therefore  contain  by  far  the  greater  part  of  the  vis 
viva.  Consequently,  the  liquid  parts  above  are  vio- 
lently separated  from  the  parts  below  and  thrown 
out  through  the  neck  of  the  funnel  high  above  the 
original  surface.  The  remainder,  however,  are  left 
considerably  below  that  point,  and  the  centre  of  grav- 
ity of  the  whole  never  as  much  as  reaches  the  original 
level  of  5. 

19.   One  of  the  most  important  achievements  of  Hydrostatic 
Daniel  Bernoulli  is  his  distinction  of  hydrostatic  and  dynamic 

pressure. 

hydrodynamic    pressure.      The    pressure 

which  liquids  exert  is  altered  by  motion  ; 

and  the  pressure  of  a  liquid  in  motion 

may,  according  to  the  circumstances,  be 

greater  or  less  than  that  of  the  liquid  at  rest 

with  the  same  arrangement  of  parts.  We 

will  illustrate  this  by  a  simple  example. 

The  vessel -4,  which  has  the  form  of  a  body 

of  revolution  with  vertical  axis,  is  kept 

constantly  filled  with  a  frictionless  liquid,  so  that  its 

surface  2X  mn  does  not  change  during  the  discharge 

at  kl.  We  will  reckon  the  vertical  distance  of  a  particle 


414  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

Detcnnina-  from  the  surf ace  m  n  downwards  as  positive  and  call 

tion  of  the    .  rtii  t  •••!  <• 

pressures  it  s.  Let  US  follow  the  course  of  a  prismatic  element  of 
acting  in  li- volume,  whose  horizontal  base- area  is  a  and  height  /?, 
motion.  in  its  downward  motion,  neglecting,  on  the  assump- 
tion of  the  parallelism  of  strata,  all  velocities  at  right 
angles  to  z.  Let  the  density  of  the  liquid  be  /},  the 
velocity  of  the  element  v,  and  the  pressure,  which  is 
dependent  on  0,  p.  If  the  particle  descend  the  dis- 
tance dzy  we  have  by  the  principle  of  vis  viva 

aftpd\-^\  =  afipgdz  —  aj~fidz (1) 

that  is,  the  increase  of  the  vis  viva  of  the  element  is 
equal  to  the  work  of  gravity  for  the  displacement  in 
question,  less  the  work  of  the  forces  of  pressure  of  the 
liquid.  The  pressure  on  the  upper  surface  of  the  element 
is  apj  that  on  the  lower  surface  is  a[/  -["  C^//^^)/^]* 
The  element  sustains,  therefore,  if  the  pressure  in- 
crease downwards,  an  upward  pressure  a  {dp/dz)ft ; 
and  for  any  displacement  dz  of  the  element,  the  work 
a{dp/dz^ftdz  must  be  deducted.  Reduced,  equation 
(i)  assumes  the  form 


and,  integrated,  gives 

„  ^  pgz  — /  -[-  const (2) 


v^ 


If  we  express  the  velocities  in  two  different  hori- 
zontal cross-sections  a^  and  a^  at  the  depths  s,  and  z^ 
below  the  surface,  by  v^,  v^,  and  the  corresponding 
pressures  by  p^,  p^^  we  may  write  equation  (2)  in  the 
form 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.         415 
Taking  for  our  cross-section  a^   the  surface,  z.  =  0,  The  hydro- 

dynamic 

^  J  =  0  ;  and  as  the  same  quantity  of  liquid  flows  through  pressure 
all  cross-sections  in  the  same  interval  of  time,  a.  v.  =thecircum- 

stances  of 

^2  ^2'     Whence,  finally,  the  motion. 


/2  =  9S^ 


The  pressure  p^  of  the  liquid  in  motion  (the  hydro- 
dynamic  pressure)  consists  of  the  pressure  pgz^  of  the 
liquid  at  rest  (the  hydrostatic  pressure)  and  of  a  pres- 
sure (/>/2)z'5  [(fl|  — ^X)I^X\  dependent  on  the  density, 
the  velocity  of  flow,  and  the  cross-sectional  areas.  In 
cross-sections  larger  than  the  surface  of  the  liquid,  the 
hydrodynamic  pressure  is  greater  than  the  hydrostatic, 
and  vice  versa, 

A  clearer  idea  of  the  significance  of   Bernoulli's  illustration 

.  .of  these  re- 

principle  may  be  obtained  by  imagining  the  liquid  in  suits  by  the 

,  ,  now  of  li- 

the vessel  A  unacted  on  by  gravity,  and  its  outflow  quids  under 

pressures 
>duced 
pistons. 


produced  by  a  constant  pressure  /^  on  the  surface,  produced 
Equation  (3)  then  takes  the  form 

If  we  follow  the  course  of  a  particle  thus  moving,  it 
will  be  found  that  to  every  increase  of  the  velocity  of 
flow  (in  the  narrower  cross-sections)  a  decrease  of 
pressure  corresponds,  and  to  every  decrease  of  the.  ve- 
locity of  flow  (in  the  wider  cross-sections)  an  increase 
of  pressure.  This,  indeed,  is  evident,  wholly  aside 
from  mathematical  considerations.  In  the  present  case 
every  change  oi  the  velocity  of  a  liquid  element  must  be 
exclusively  produced  by  the  work  of  the  liquid's  forces 
of  pressure.  When,  therefore,  an  element  enters  into 
a  narrower  cross-section,  in  which  a  greater  velocity 
of  flow  prevails,  it  can  acquire  this  higher  velocity  only 


4i6  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

on  the  condition  that  a  greater  pressure  acts  on  its  rear 
surface  than  on  its  front  surface,  that  is  to  say,  only 
when  it  moves  from  points  of  higher  to  points  of  lower 
pressure,  or  when  the  pressure  decreases  in  the  direc- 
tion of  the  motion.  If  we  imagine  the  pressures  in 
a  wide  section  and  in  a  succeeding  narrower  section 
to  be  for  a  moment  equal,  the  acceleration  of  the  ele- 
ments in  the  narrower  section  will  not  take  place  ;  the 
elements  will  not  escape  fast  enough  ;  they  will  accumu- 
late before  the  narrower  section  ;  and  at  the  entrance 
to  it  the  requisite  augmentation  of  pressure  will  be  im- 
mediately produced.  The  converse  case  is  obvious. 
<  20.  In  dealing  with  more  complicated  cases,  the 
°  problems  of  liquid  motion,  even  though  viscosity  be 


neglected,  present  great  difficulties;  and  when  the 
enormous  effects  of  viscosity  are  taken  into  account, 
anything  like  a  dynamical  solution  of  almost  every 
problem  is  out  of  the  question.  So  much  so,  that  al- 
though these  investigations  were  begun  by  Newton, 
we  have,  up  to  the  present  time,  only  been  able  to 
master  a  very  few  of  the  simplest  problems  of  this  class, 
and  that  but  imperfectly.  We  shall  content  ourselves 
with  a  simple  example.  If  we  cause  a  liquid  contained 
in  a  vessel  of  the  pressure-head  h  to  flow,  not  through 
an  orifice  in  its  base,  but  through  a  long  cylindrical 
tube  fixed  in  its  side  (Fig.  220),  the  velocity  of  efflux 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES.  417 

V  yrill  be  less  than  that  deducible  from  Torricelli's  law, 
as  a  portion  of  the  work  is  consumed  by  resistances 
due  to  viscosity  and  perhaps  to  friction.  We  find,  in 
fact,  that  z;  =  1/2  ^  //  J ,  where  ^  j  <  ^.  Expressing  by  h  ^ 
the  r^^r/Vy-head,  and  by  ^3  the  resistance-hi&dA,  we  may 
put  A  =  ^,  +  '^2*  ^^^^  the  main  cylindrical  tube  we 
affix  vertical  lateral  tubes,  the  liquid  will  rise  in  the 
latter  tubes  to  the  heights  at  which  it  equilibrates  the 
pressures  in  the  main  tube,  and  will  thus  indicate  at  all 
points  the  pressures  of  the  main  tube.  The  noticeable 
fact  here  is,  that  the  liquid-height  at  the  point  of  influx 
of  the  tube  is  =  Z/^,  and  that  it  diminishes  in  the  direc- 
tion of  the  point  of  outflow,  by  the  law  of  a  straight 
line,  to  zero.  The  elucidation  of  this  phenomenon  is 
the  question  now  presented. 

Gravity  here  does  not  act  directly  on  the  liquid  in  The  condi- 
the  horizontal  tube,  but  all  effects  are  transmitted  to  it  perform-  ^ 
by  the  pressure  of  the  surrounding  parts.     If  we  imag-work  in 

sucli  CAses. 

ine  a  prismatic  liquid  element  of  basal  area  a  and 
length  ft  to  be  displaced  in  the  direction  of  its  length 
a  distance  dz,  the  work  done,  as  in  the  previous  case,  is 

dz^  ^  dz 

For  a  finite  displacement  we  have 

Work  is  done  when  the  element  of  volume  is  displaced 
from  a  place  of  higher  to  a  place  of  lower  pressure. 
The  amount  of  the  work  done  depends  on  the  size  of 
the  element  of  volume  and  on  the  difference  of  pressure 
at  the  initial  and  terminal  points  of  the  motion,  and 
not  on  the  length  and  the  form  of  the  path  traversed. 


4i8 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 


The  conse- 
quences of 
tnese  con- 
ditions. 


If  the  diminution  of  pressure  were  twice  as  rapid  in 
one  case  as  in  another,  the  difference  of  the  pressures 
on  the  front  and  rear  surfaces,  or  xSx'^  force  of  the  work, 
would  be  doubled,  but  the  space  through  which  the 
work  was  done  would  be  halved.  The  work  done  would 
remain  the  same,  whether  done  through  the  space  ab 
or  ac  of  Fig.  221. 

Through  every  cross-section  q  of  the  horizontal  tube 
the  liquid  flows  with  the  same  velocity  v.  If,  neglect- 
ing the  differences  of  velocity  in  the  same  cross- section, 
we  consider  a  liquid  element  which  exactly  fills  the 
section  q  and  has  the  length  y5,  the  vis  viva  qP p{v^  j'l) 
of  such  an  element  will  persist  unchanged  throughout 

its  entire  course  in  the  tube. 
This  is  possible  only  provided 
the  vis  viva  consumed  by  friction 
is  replaced  by  the  work  of  the 
liquid'*  s  forces  of  pressure,  H  ence, 
in  the  direction  of  the  motion 
of  the  element  the  pressure 
must  diminish,  and  for  equal  distances,  to  which  the 
same  work  of  friction  corresponds,  by  equal  amounts. 
The  total  work  of  gravity  on  a  liquid  element  q ^p 
issuing  from  the  vessel,  is  qfi pgh.  Of  this  the  portion 
^/5p(z^2/2)  is  the  vis  viva  of  the  element  discharged 
with  the  velocity  v  into  the  mouth  of  the  tube,  or,  as 
V  =  V2gh^y  the  portion  q^pgh^.  The  remainder  of 
the  work,  therefore,  q  fipgh^,  is  consumed  in  the  tube, 
if  owing  to  the  slowness  of  the  motion  we  neglect  the 
losses  within  the  vessel. 

If  the  pressure-heads  respectively  obtaining  in  the 
vessel,  at  the  mouth,  and  at  the  extremity  of  the  tube, 
are^,  h^,  0,  or  the  pressures  are/  =  hgp,  p^  =  A^gp,0, 
then  by  equation  (i)  of  page  417  the  work  requisite  to 


Fig.  221. 


THE  EXTENSION  OF  THE  PRINCIPLES,         419 

generate  the  vis  viva  of  the  element  discharged  into 
the  mouth  of  the  tube  is 

and  the  work  transmitted  by  the  pressure  of  the  liquid 
to  the  element  traversing  the  length  of  the  tube,  is 

qPp2  =  ^PsP^2y 

or  the  exact  amount  consumed  in  the  tube. 

Let  us  assume,  for  the  sake  of  argument,  that  the  indirect 

-  ,  demonstra* 

pressure  does  not  decrease  from/-  at  the  mouth  touonof 
zero  at  the  extremity  of  the  tube  by  the  law  of  a  straight  Bequenccs. 
line,  but  that  the  distribution  of  the  pressure  is  differ- 
ent, say,  constant  throughout  the  entire  tube.  The 
parts  in  advance  then  will  at  once  suffer  a  loss  of  ve- 
locity from  the  friction,  the  parts  which  follow  will 
crowd  upon  them,  and  there  will  thus  be  produced  at 
the  mouth  of  the  tube  an  augmentation  of  pressure 
conditioning  a  constant  velocity  throughout  its  entire 
length.  The  pressure  at  the  end  of  the  tube  can  only 
be  ==  0  because  the  liquid  at  that  point  is  not  prevented 
from  yielding  to  any  pressure  impressed  upon  it. 

If  we  imagine  the  liquid  to  be  a  mass  of  smooth  a  simile 
elastic  balls,  the  balls  will  be  most  compressed  at  the  which  these 
bottom  of  the  vessel,  they  will  enter  the  tube  in  a  state  may*b™*°* 
of  compression,  and  will  gradually  lose  that  state  in  ceived. 
the  course  of  their  motion.     We  leave  the  further  de- 
velopment of  this  simile  to  the  reader. 

It  is  evident,  from  a  previous  remark,  that  the  work 
stored  up  in  the  compression  of  the  liquid  itself,  is  very 
small.  The  motion  of  the  liquid  is  due  to  the  work  of 
gravity  in  the  vessel,  which  by  means  of  the  pressure 
of  the  compressed  liquid  is  transmitted  to  the  parts  in 
the  tube. 


420  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

An  interesting  modiBcatioD  of  the  case  just  dis- 
cussed is  obtained  by  causing  the  liquid  to  flow  through 
.  a  tube  composed  of  a  number  of  shorter  cylindrical 
tubes  of  varying  widths.  The  pressure  in  the  direction 
of  outflow  then  diminishes  (Fig.  222)  more  rapidly  in 
the  narrower  tubes,  in  which  a  greater  consumption  of 
work  by  friction  takes  place,  than  in  the  wider  ones. 
We  further  note,  in  every  passage  of  the  liquid  into  a 


wider  tube,  that  is  to  a  smaller  velocity  of  flow,  an  in- 
crease of  pressure  (a  positive  congestion)  ;  in  every 
passage  into  a  narrower  tube,  that  is  to  a  greater  velo- 
city of  flow,  an  abrupt  diminulion  of  pressure  (a  nega- 
tive congestion).  The  velocity  of  a  liquid  element  on 
which  no  direct  forces  act  can  be  diminished  or  in- 
creased only  by  its  passing  to  points  of  higher  or  lower 
pressure. 


science. 


CHAPTER  IV. 

THE  FORMAL  DEVELOPMENT  OF  MECHANICS. 

I. 
THE  ISOPERIMETRICAL  PROBLEMS. 

I.  When  the  chief  facts  of  a  physical  science  have  The  formal, 
once  been  fixed  by  observation,  a  new  period  of  its  suished 

11  ••  i.».  i»t  1  xromthede- 

development  begins — the  deducttt^e,  which  we  treated  ductive,  de- 
in  the  previous  chapter.  In  this  period,  the  facts  are  of  physical 
reproducible  in  the  mind  without  constant  recourse  to 
observation.  Facts  of  a  more  general  and  complex 
character  are  mimicked  in  thought  on  the  theory  that 
they  are  made  up  of  simpler  and  more  familiar  obser- 
vational elements.  But  even  after  we  have  deduced 
from  our  expressions  for  the  most  elementary  facts 
(the  principles)  expressions  for  more  common  and  more 
complex  facts  (the  theorems)  and  have  discovered  in 
all  phenomena  the  same  elements,  the  developmental 
process  of  the  science  is  not  yet  completed.  The  de- 
ductive development  of  the  science  is  followed  by  its 
formal  development.  Here  it  is  sought  to  put  in  a  clear 
compendious  form,  or  system,  the  facts  to  be  repro- 
duced, so  that  each  can  be  reached  and  mentally  pic- 
tured with  the  least  intellectual  effort.  Into  our  rules 
for  the  mental  reconstruction  of  facts  we  strive  to  in- 
corporate the  greatest  possible  uniformity,  so  that  these 
rules  shall  be  easy  of  acquisition.  It  is  to  be  remarked, 
that  the  three  periods  distinguished  are  not  sharply 


422  THE  SCIEP/CE  OF  MECHANICS. 

separated  from  one  another,  but  that  the  processes  of 
development  referred  to  frequently  go  hand  in  hand, 
although  on  the  whole  the  order  designated  is  unmis- 
takable. 
Theisopari-  2.  A  powerful  influence  was  exerted  on  the  formal 
problems,    development   of  mechanics  by  a  particular  class  of 

and  ques-  , 

tions  of      mathematical  problems,  which,   at  the  close  of  the 

maxima 

and  minima  seventeenth  and  the  beginning  of  the  eighteenth  cen- 
turies, engaged  the  deepest  attention  of  inquirers. 
These  problems,  the  so-called  isoperimetrical  problems^ 
will  now  form  the  subject  of  our  remarks.  Certain 
questions  of  the  greatest  and  least  values  of  quanti- 
ties, questions  of  maxima  and  minima,  were  treated  by 

the    Greek    mathemati- 
cians.      Pythagoras     is 
said  to  have  taught  that 
the   circle,  of  all  plane 
figures  of  a  given  peri- 
meter, has  the  greatest 
area.  The  idea,  too,  of  a 
certain  economy  in  the  processes  of  nature  was  not 
foreign  to  the  ancients.     Hero  deduced  the  law  of  the 
reflection  of  light  from  the  theory  that  light  emitted 
from  a  point  A  (Fig.  223)  and  reflected  at  J/ will  travel 
to  B  by  the  shortest  route.     Making  the  plane  of  the 
paper  the  plane  of  reflection,  SS  the  intersection  of 
the  reflecting  surface,  A  the  point  of  departure,  B  the 
point  of  arrival,  and  M  the  point  of  reflection  of  the 
ray  of  light,  it  will  be  seen  at  once  that  the  line  AMB' ^ 
where  B  is  the  reflection  of  B,  is  a  straight  line.    The 
line  AMB*  is  shorter  than  the  line  ANB*,  and  there- 
fore also  AMB  is  shorter  than  ANB,     Pappus  held 
similar   notions   concerning   organic   nature ;    he   ex- 


FORMAL  DEVELOPMENT, 


423 


plained,  for  example,  the  form  of  the  cells  of  the  honey- 
comb by  the  bees'  efforts  to  economise  in  materials. 

These  ideas  fell,  at  the  time  of  the  revival  of  the  The  re- 
searches of 
sciences,  on  not  unfruitful  soil.     They  were  first  taken  Kepler, Fer- 

up  by  Fermat  and  Roberval,  who  developed  a  method  Robervai. 
applicable  to  such  problems.  These  inquirers  ob- 
served,— as  Kepler  had  already  done, — that  a  magni- 
tude y  which  depends  on  another  magnitude  at,  gen- 
erally possesses  in  the  vicinity  of  its  greatest  and  least 
values  a  peculiar  property.  Let  x  (Fig.  224)  denote 
abscissas  and^  ordinates.  If,  while  x  increases,  y  pass 
through  a  maximum  value,  its  increase,  or  rise,  will 
be  changed  into  a  decrease,  or 
fall;  and  if  it  pass  through  a 
minimum  value  its  fall  will  be 
changed  into  a  rise.  The  neigh- 
boring values  of  the  maximum 
or  minimum  value,  consequently, 
will  lie  very  near  each  other,  and 

the  tangents  to  the  curve  at  the  points  in  question  will 
generally  be  parallel  to  the  axis  of  abscissas.  Hence, 
to  find  the  maximum  or  minimum  values  of  a  quan- 
tity, we  seek  the  parallel  tangents  of  its  curve. 

The  method  of  tangents  may  be  put  in  analytical  The 
form.  For  example,  it  is  required  to  cut  off  from  a  tangents, 
given  line  a  a  portion  x  such  that  the  product  of  the 
two  segments  x  and  a  —  x  shall  be  as  great  as  possible. 
Here,  the  product  x{a  —  ^)  must  be  regarded  as  the 
quantity  y  dependent  on  x.  At  the  maximum  value  of 
y  any  infinitely  small  variation  of  x^  say  a  variation  ^, 
will  produce  no  change  in  y.  Accordingly,  the  required 
value  of  X  will  be  found,  by  putting 

x{a  —  jr)  =  (jf  -|-  S){a  —  X  —  ^ 
or 


424 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 


or 


ax  —  x^  =.ax  ^  a^  —  x^  —  x^  —  x^  —  5' 

0  =  tf  —  2:c  — 5. 


mal  effect. 


As  ^  may  be  made  as  small  as  we  please,  we  also  get 

^  =  a  —  1x\ 

whence  x  =  «/2. 

In  this  way,  the  concrete  idea  of  the  method  of 
tangents  may  be  translated  into  the  language  of  alge- 
bra ;  the  procedure  also  contains,  as  we  see,  the  germ 
of  the  differential  calculus. 
The  refrac-       Fermat  sought  to  find  for  the  law  of  the  refraction 
Manunf-    of  light  an  expression  analogous  to  that  of  Hero  for 

law  of  reflection.    He  remarked 

that  light,  proceeding   from  a 

point  A^    and    refracted   at   a 

point  My  travels  to  B^  not  by 

the  shortest  route,  but  in  the 

shortest  time.  If  the  path  AMB 

is   performed   in    the    shortest 

time,  then  a  neighboring  path 

ANBy  infinitely  near  the  real 

path,  will  be  described  in  the 

same  time.    If  we  draw  from  N  on  AM  and  from  M  on 

NB  the  perpendiculars  NP  and  MQ,  then  the  second 

route,  before  refraction,  is  less  than  the  first  route  by  a 

•distance  J//'=-A^J/ sin  a,  but  is  larger  than  it  after 

refraction  by  the  distance  NQ  =  NM^vn  §,     On  the 

supposition,  therefore,  that  the  velocities  in  the  first 

and  second  media  are  respectively  v^  and  v^y  the  time 

required  for  the  path  AMB  will  be  a  minimum  when 


Fig.  325. 


NM^\n  a      NMsm  p 


=  0 


V. 


V, 


or 


FORMAL  DEVELOPMENT,  425 

v^       sinflr 

-  =    •    z^  =  ^> 
7>3       sin  p 

where  n  stands  for  the  index  of  refraction.  Hero's  law 
of  reflection,  remarks  Leibnitz,  is  thus  a  special  case 
of  the  law  of  refraction.  For  equal  velocities  {v^  =  v^, 
the  condition  of  a  minimum  of  time  is  identical  with 
the  condition  of  a  minimum  of  space. 

Huygens,  in  his  optical  investigations,  applied  and  Hnygens's 
further  perfected  the  ideas  of  Fermat,  considering,  not  of  Fermafs 

r  Aftfi  AJTC  ufifi. 

only  rectilinear,  but  also  curvilinear  motions  of  light, 
in  media  in  which  the  velocity  of  the  light  varied  con- 
tinuously from  place  to  place.  For  these,  also,  he 
found  that  Fermat's  law  obtained.  Accordingly,  in  all 
motions  of  light,  an  endeavor,  so  to  speak,  to  produce 
results  in  a  minimum  of  time  appeared  to  be  the  funda- 
mental tendency. 

3.  Similar  maximal  or  minimal  properties  were  The  prob- 
brought  out  in  the  study  of  mechanical  phenomena,  brachisto- 
As  we  have  already  noticed,  John  Bernoulli  knew  that 
a  freely  suspended  chain  assumes  the  form  for  which 
its  centre  of  gravity  lies  lowest.  This  idea  was,  of 
course,  a  simple  one  for  the  investigator  who  first  rec- 
ognised the  general  import  of  the  principle  of  virtual 
velocities.  Stimulated  by  these  observations,  inquir- 
ers now  began  generally  to  investigate  maximal  and 
minimal  characters.  The  movement  received  its  most ' 
powerful  impulse  from  a  problem  propounded  by  John 
Bernoulli,  in  June,  1696* — the  problem  of  the  brachis- 
tochrone.  In  a  vertical  plane  two  points  are  situated, 
A  and  B,  It  is  required  to  assign  in  this  plane  the 
curve  by  which  a  falling  body  will  travel  from  A  to  B 
in  the  shortest  time.  The  problem  was  very  ingeniously 

*  Ada  Ernditarum,  Leipsic. 


426  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

solved  by  John  Bernoulli  himself ;  and  solutions  were 
also  supplied  by  Leibnitz,   L*H6pital,   Newton,    and 
James  Bernoulli. 
johnBcr-  The   most   remarkable   solution   was  John    Ber- 

noulli'sin-  „,,...  ,         ,  ,  , 

eeniousso-  NOULLis  owu.     This  inquirer  remarks  that  problems 

lutionofthe     .        , 

problem  of  of  this  class  have  already  been  solved,  not  for  the  mo- 

the  brachis-    ,  , 

tochrone.    tion  of  falling  bodies,  but  for  the  motion  of  light.    He 
accordingly  imagines  the  motion  of  a  falling  body  re- 
placed by  the  motion  of 
a  ray  of  light.    (Comp. 
P-  379)   The  two  points 
A  and  B  are  supposed 
to  be  fixed  in  a  medium 
in  which  the  velocity  of 
light    increases    in    the 
vertical  downward  direction  by  the  same  law  as  the 
velocity  of  a  falling  body.     The  medium  is  supposed 
to  be  constructed  of  horizontal  layers  of  downwardly 


decreasing  density,  such  that  v '=-\  2gh  denotes  the 
velocity  of  the  light  in  any  layer  at  the  distance  h  be- 
low A,  A  ray  of  light  which  travels  from  A  to  B  un- 
der such  conditions  will  describe  this  distance  in  the 
shortest  time,  and  simultaneously  trace  out  the  curve 
of  quickest  descent. 

Calling  the  angles  made  by  the  element  of  the 
curve  with  the  perpendicular,  or  the  normal  of  the 
layers,  oty  a\  or".  .  .  .,  and  the  respective  velocities 
V,  p',  v".  .  .  .,  we  have 

sin  a sin  a' sin  a'* . 

or,  designating  the  perpendicular  distances  below  A 
by  X,  the  horizontal  distances  from  A  by  y^  and  the  arc 
of  the  curve  by  j. 


FORMAL  DEVELOPMENT,  427 


(: 


./  (.  /  chrone  a 

"^/  __  jf,  cycloid. 

7} 


whence  follows 

//>'2  _,  ^2  y;2  ^j2  —  ^2  7,2  (,/>v2   _p  ^^2) 

and  because  z^  =  1/2  ^jc  also 

//v  =  //jca  I  —    -  ,  where  a  =  ^ — r;r- 

This  is  the  differential  equation  of  a  cycloid,  or  curve 
described  by  a  point  in  the  circumference  of  a  circle  of 
radius  r=^a/2  =  ij^gk^^  rolling  on  a  straight  line. 

To  find  the  cycloid  that  passes  through  A  and  By  The  con- 
it  is  to  be  noted  that  all  cycloids,  inasmuch  as  they  are  Jhe  cycloid 

'  ■  ^  between 

produced  by  similar  con-  t^?  K>ven 

structions,    are    similar^       ^\ 

and  that  if  generated  by 

the  rolling  of  circles  on 

AD  from  the  point  A  as 

origin,  are  also  similarly 

,       .  1  Pig*  3?7* 

Situate  a  with  respect  to 

the  point  A,  Accordingly,  we  draw  through  AB  a 
straight  line,  and  construct  any  cycloid,  cutting  the 
straight  line  in  B.  The  radius  of  the  generating 
circle  is,  say,  r'.  Then  the  radius  of  the  generating 
circle  of  the  cycloid  sought  is  r=  r\AB/AB'). 

This  solution  of  John  Bernoulli's,  achieved  entirely 
without  a  method,  the  outcome  of  pure  geometrical 
fancy  and  a  skilful  use  of  such  knowledge  as  happened 
to  be  at  his  command,  is  one  of  the  most  remarkable 
and  beautiful  performances  in  the  history  of  physical 
science.  John  Bernoulli  was  an  aesthetic  genius  in  this 
field.  His  brother  James's  character  was  entirely  differ- 
ent. James  was  the  superior  of  John  in  critical  power, 


428  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

Compiri-    but  in  originality  and  imagination  was  surpassed  by  the 
sdMiiifio     latter.     James  Bernoulli  likewise  solved  this  problem, 
etlobn  and  though  in  less  felicitous  form.   But,  on  the  Other  hand, 
nouiii.        he  did  not  fail  to  develop,  with  great  thoroughness,  a 
general  ra^xSxoA  applicable  to  such  problems.     Thus, 
in  these  two  brothers  we  find  the  two  fundamental 
traits  of   high  scientific   talent  separated  from  one 
another, — traits,  which  in  the  very  greatest  natural 
inquirers,   in  Newton,  for  example,  are  combined  to- 
gether. We  shall  soon  see  those  two  tendencies,  which 
within  one  bosom  might  have  fought  their  battles  un- 
noticed, clashing  in  open  conflict,  in  the  persons  of 
these  two  brothers. 


■(  ?M«.. 


I»ineiB«-  4,  James  Bernoulli  finds  that  the  chief  object  of 
■narks  on  research  hitherto  had  been  to  find  the  values  of  a  vari- 
niiurBof  able  quantity,  for  which  a  second  variable  quantity, 
probiim.  which  is  a  function  of  the  first,  assumes  its  greatest  or 
its  least  value.   The  present  problem,  however,  is  to  find 


FORMAL  DEVELOPMENT,  429 

from  among  an  infinite  number  of  curves  one  which  pos- 
sesses a  certain  maximal  or  minimal  property.  This,  as 
he  correctly  remarks,  is  a  problem  of  an  entirely  dif- 
ferent character  from  the  other  and  demands  a  new 
method.  • 

The  principles  that  James  Bernoulli  employed  inThepHnci- 
the  solution  of  this  problem  {Acta  Eruditorum^  May,  ployed  in 

r    11  James  Ber- 

1697)*  are  as  follows :  nouiu'sso- 

(i)  If  a  curve  has  a  certain  property  of  maximum 
or  minimum,  every  portion  or  element  of  the  curve  has 
the  same  property. 

(2)  Just  as  the  infinitely  adjacent  values  of  the 
maxima  or  minima  of  a  quantity  in  the  ordinary  prob- 
lems, for  infinitely  small  changes  of  the  independent 
variables,  are  constant,  so  also  is  the  quantity  here  to 
be  made  a  maximum  or  minimum  for  the  curve  sought, 
for  infinitely  contiguous  curves^  constant. 

(3)  It  is  finally  assumed,  for  the  case  of  the  brachis- 
tochrone,  that,  the  velocity  is  7/ =  1/2^//,  where  h  de- 
notes the  height  fallen  through. 

If  we  picture  to  ourselves  a  very  small  portion  ABCthe  essen- 

tial  fea- 

of  the  curve  (Fig.  228),  and,  imagining  a  horizontal  tures  of 

ft  1  1       «  James  Ber- 

ime drawn   through  B,   cause  uoniii'sso- 

,  .  -  .  j4\.  lution. 

the  portion  taken  to  pass  mto 
the  infinitely  contiguous  por- 
tion ADC,  we  shall  obtain,  by 
considerations  exactly  similar 
to  those  employed  in  the  treat- 
ment of  Fermat's  law,  the  well- 
known    relation    between    the 

sines  of  the  angles  made  by  the  curve-elements  with 
the  perpendicular  and  the  velocities  of  descent.  In 
this  deduction  the  following  assumptions  are  made, 

*  See  also  his  works,  Vol.  II.  p.  768.  « 


430 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 


The  Pro- 
gramma  of 


(i),  that  the  part^  or  element,  ABC  is  brachistochro- 
nous,  and  (2),  that  ADC  is  described  in  the  same  time 
as  ABC,  Bernoulli's  calculation  is  very  prolix  ;  but 
its  essential  features  are  obvious,  and  the  problem  is 
solved  *  by  the  above-stated  principles. 

With  the  solution  of  the  problem  of  the  brachisto- 
jamesBer-  chrone,  Tames  Bernoulli,  in  accordance  with  the  prac- 

noulli,  or        .  •*  .  .  .    .  ^ 

theproposi-tice  then  prevailing  among  mathematicians,  proposed 

tion  of  tlio 

general  iso-  the  foUowiug  more  general  "  isoperimetrical  problem  '*: 

perimetri" 

cai  prob-  <«  Of  all  isoperimetrical  curves  (that  is,  curves  of  equal 
"perimeters  or  equal  lengths)  between  the  same  two 
"fixed  points,  to  find  the  curve  such  that  the  space 
"included  (i)  by  a  second  curve,  each  of  whose  ordi- 
"  nates  is  a  given  function  of  the  corresponding  ordi- 
"nate  or  the  corresponding  arc  of  the  one  sought,  (2) 
"  by  the  ordinates  of  its  extreme  points,  and  (3)  by  the 
"  part  of  the  axis  of  abscissae  lying  between  those  ordi- 
" nates,  shall  be  a  maximum  or  minimum." 

For  example.   It  is  required  to  find  the  curve  BFN^ 
described  on  the  base  BN  such,  that  of  all  curves  of 

the    same    length    on   BN^ 
this  particular  one  shall  make 
the  area  BZN  a  minimum, 
where  PZ=(^PFy,  LM  = 
{LKy^  and  so  on.     Let  the 
relation    between    the   ordi- 
nates of  BZN  and  the  cor- 
responding ordinates  of  BFN 
be  given  by  the  curve  BH,     To  obtain  PZ  from  PF, 
draw  FGH  at  right  angles  to  BG,  where  ^6^  is  at  right 
angles  to  BN.     By  hypothesis,  then,  PZ=i  GHy  and 


*  For  the  details  of  this  solution  and  for  information  generally  on  the  his- 
tory of  this  subject,  see  Woodhouse's  Treatise  on  Isoperimetrical  ProbUntt 
and  the  Calculus  i^  Variations^  Cambridge,  z8io. — Trans, 


FORMAL  DEVELOPMENT,  431 

SO  for  the  other  ordinates.     Further,  we  put  BPz=y, 
PF=  X,  PZ  =  a:". 

John  Bernoulli  gave,  forthwith,  a  solution  of  this  John  Ber- 

.  noulli'a  so- 

problem,  in  the  form  lutionof 

this  prob- 

where  a  is  an  arbitrary  constant.     For  «  =  1, 

xdx 


/xax 
==  a 


—  Va^—x'^, 


that  is,  BFN  is  a  semicircle  on  ^iV  as  diameter,  and 
the  area  BZN  is  equal  to  the  area  BFN,  For  this  par- 
ticular case,  the  solution,  in  fact,  is  correct.  But  the 
general  formula  is  not  universally  valid. 

On  the  publication  of  John  Bernoulli's  solution, 
James  Bernoulli  openly  engaged  to  do  three  things  : 
first,  to  discover  his  brother's  method ;  second,  to  point 
out  its  contradictions  and  errors ;  and,  third,  to  give  the 
true  solution.  The  jealousy  and  animosity  of  the  two 
brothers  culminated,  on  this  occasion,  in  a  violent  and 
acrimonious  controversy,  which  lasted  till  James's 
death.  After  James's  death,  John  virtually  confessed 
his  error  and  adopted  the  correct  method  of  his  brother. 

James  Bernoulli  surmised,  and  in  all  probability  James  Ber- 

.  noulli's 

correctly,  that  John,  misled  by  the  results  of  his  re-  criticism  of 

searches  on  the  catenary  and  the  curve  of  a  sail  filled  nouiH's  so- 
lution, 
with  wind,  had  again  attempted  an  indirect  solution, 

imagining  ^/^A^  filled  with  a  liquid  of  variable  density 

and  taking  the  lowest  position  of  the  centre  of  gravity 

as  determinative  of  the  curve  required.     Making  the 

ordinate  /'Z=/,  the  specific  gravity  of  the  liquid  in 

the  ordinate  PF-=zx  must  be  pjx^  and  similarly  in 

every  other  ordinate.     The  weight  of  a  vertical  fila- 


432 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 


ment  is  then  / .  dyjx^  and  its  moment  with  respect  to 

^iV^is 

\     pdy       1      ^ 
x<^=-^pdy. 


2 


X 


p. 


ution. 


Hence,  for  the  lowest  position  of  the  centre  of  gravity, 
i  fpdy,  or  Cfi  dy  =zBZJV,  is  a  maximum.  But  the 
fact  is  here  overlooked,  remarks  James  Bernoulli,  that 
with  the  variation  of  the  curve  BFN  the  weight  of  the 
liquid  also  is  varied.  Consequently,  in  this  simple 
form  the  deduction  is  not  admissible. 
Thefunda-  In  the  solution  which  he  himself  gives.  Tames  Ber- 
principle  of  noulli  once  more  assumes  that  the  small  portion  F F,,, 

James  Ber-  '^  '" 

nouiii'8  of  the  curve  possesses  the  prop- 

eneral  so-  «.  j  7^ 

erty  which  the  whole  curve  pos- 
sesses. And  then  taking  the  four 
successive  points  F  F^  F,,  F,,,, 
of  which  the  two  extreme  ones 
are  fixed,   he   so  varies  F,   and 
Fff  that  the  length  of  the  arc  F 
Ff   Fff  F,,f  remains  unchanged^ 
which  is  possible,  of  course,  only  by  a  displacement 
of  two  points.     We  shall  not  follow  his  involved  and 
unwieldy  calculations.    The  principle  of  the  process  is 
clearly  indicated  in  our  remarks.     Retaining  the  des- 
ignations above  employed,  James  Bernoulli,  in  sub- 
stance, states  that  when 

fpdy  is  a  maximum,  and  when 

dy=-^^---ML 
\^2ap—p^ 

fpdy  is  a  miuimum. 


Fig.  aao. 


FORMAL  DEVELOPMENT.  433 

The  dissensions  between  the  two  brothers  were,  we 
may  admit,  greatly  to  be  deplored.  Yet  the  genius  of 
the  one  and  the  profundity  of  the  other  have  borne,  in 
the  stimulus  which  Euler  and  Lagrange  received  from 
their  several  investigations,  splendid  fruits. 

5.  Euler  iProblematis  Isoperimetrici Solutio  Generalise  Euier^a 

general 

Com,  Acad,  Petr,  T.  VI,  for  1733,  published  in  i738)*ciassifica- 
was  the  first  to  give  a  more  general  method  of  treating  isopcrimet- 

.  ...  .    rical  prob- 

these  questions  of  maxima  and  minima,  or  isoperimetri-  lems. 
cal  problems.  But  even  his  results  were  based  on 
prolix  geometrical  considerations,  and  not  possessed  of 
analytical  generality.  Euler  divides  problems  of  this 
category,  with  a  clear  perception  and  grasp  of  their 
differences,  into  the  following  classes  : 

(i)  Required,  of  a// curves,  that  for  which  a  prop- 
erty ^  is  a  maximum  or  minimum. 

(2)  Required,  of  all  curves,  equally  possessing  a 
property  Ay  that  for  which  -^  is  a  maximum  or  mini- 
mum. 

(3)  Required,  of  all  curves,  equally  possessing  two 
properties,  A  and  B,  that  for  which  C  is  a  maximum 
or  minimum.     And  so  on. 

A  problem  of  the  first  class  is  (Fig.  231)  the  finding  Examples. 
of  the  shortest  curve  through  M  and  N,  A  problem  of 
the  second  class  is  the  finding  of  a  curve  through  M 
and  Ny  which,  having  the  given  length  A^  makes  the 
area  MPN  a  maximum.  A  problem  of  the  third  class 
would  be  :  of  all  curves  of  the  given  length  A,  which 
pass  through  M^  N  and  contain  the  same  area 
MPN=^B,  to  find  one  which  describes  when  rotated 
about  MN  the  least  surface  of  revolution.    And  so  on. 

*  Euler's  principal  contribations  to  this  subject  are  contained  in  three 
memoirs,  published  in  the  Commentaries  ^ Peiertburg^  lot  \\xe  years  1733,  1736, 
and  X7<S6,  and  in  the  tract  Methodtu  inveniendi  Lineas  Curva*  Pro^ietate 
Meucimi  Minimive  gaudentet^  Lausanne  and  Geneva,  1744. — Trans. 


434  ^^^^'  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

We  may  observe  here,  that  the  finding  of  an  abso- 
lute maximum  or  minimum,  without  collateral  condi- 
tions, is  meaningless.    Thus,  all  the  curves  of  which  in 

the  first  example  the  shortest  is  sought 
possess  the  common  property  of  pas- 
sing through  the  points  M  and  N. 

The  solution  of  problems  of  the 
first  class  requires  the  variation  of  two 
elements  of  the  curve  or  of  one  point. 
This  is  also  sufficient.  In  problems 
of  the  second  class  three  elements  or 
Fig.  a3i.  ^^^  points  must  be  varied ;  the  reason 

being,  that  the  varied  portion  must 
possess  in  common  with  the  unvaried  portion  the  prop- 
erty Ay  and,  as  B  is  to  be  made  a  maximum  or  mini- 
mum, also  the  property  B,  that  is,  must  satisfy  two  con- 
ditions. Similarly,  the  solution  of  problems  of  the  third 
class  requires  the  variation  of  four  elements.  And 
so  on. 
The  com-  The  solutiou  of  a  problem  of  a  higher  class  involves, 

of  the  iao-    by  implication,  the  solution  of  its  converse,  in  all  its 
cai  proper-  forms.  Thus,  in  the  third  class,  we  vary  four  elements 

ties  with  * 

Eui'ers in-  of  the  curve,  SO,  that  the  varied  portion  of  the  curve 
shall  share  equally  with  the  original  portion  the  values 
A  and  B  and,  as  C  is  to  be  made  a  maximum  or  a 
minimum,  also  the  value  C  But  the  same  conditions 
must  be  satisfied,  if  of  all  curves  possessing  equally  B 
and  C  that  for  which  ^  is  a  maximum  or  minimum  is 
sought,  or  of  all  curves  possessing  A  and  C  that  for 
which  ^  is  a  maximum  or  minimum  is  sought.  Thus 
a  circle,  to  take  an  example  from  the  second  class,  con- 
tains, of  all  lines  of  the  same  length  Aj  the  greatest 
area  By  and  the  circle,  also,  of  all  curves  containing 
the  same  area  B^  has  the  shortest  length  A,     As  the 


FORMAL  DEVELOPMENT.  435 

condition  that  the  property  A  shall  be  possessed  in 
common  or  shall  be  a  maximum,  is  expressed  in  the 
same  manner,  Euler  saw  the  possibility  of  reducing  the 
problems  of  the  higher  classes  to  problems  of  the  first 
class.  Ify  for  example^  it  is  required  to  find,  of  all 
curves  having  the  common  property  A^  that  which 
makes  B  a  maximum,  the  curve  is  sought  for  which 
A  +  ^f^B  is  a  maximum,  where  m  is  an  arbitrary  con- 
stant. If  on  any  change  of  the  curve,  A  +  ttiB,  for  any 
value  of  niy  does  not  change,  this  is  generally  possible 
only  provided  the  change  of  A^  considered  by  itself, 
and  that  of  B^  considered  by  itself,  are  =  0. 

6.  Euler  was  the  originator  of  still  another  impor-  The  funda- 
tant  advance.     In  treatmg  the  problem  of  finding  the  principle  o( 

.       James  Ber- 

brachistochrone  in  a  resisting  medium,  which  was  in-  noniU's 
vestigated  by  Herrmann  and  him,  the  existing  meth-  shown  not 

,  1  .  -r-*  1        1  1  •  1  .     to  be  uni- 

ods  proved  mcompetent.  For  the  brachistochrone  m  versaiiy 
a  vacuum,  the  velocity  depends  solely  on  the  vertical 
height  fallen  through.  The  velocity  in  one  portion  of 
the  curve  is  in  no  wise  dependent  on  the  other  por- 
tions. In  this  case,  then,  we  can  indeed  say,  that  if 
the  whole  curve  is  brachistochronous,  every  element 
of  it  is  also  brachistochronous.  But  in  a  resisting 
medium  the  case  is  different.  The  entire  length  and 
form  of  the  preceding  path  enters  into  the  determina- 
tion of  the  velocity  in  the  element.  The  whole  curve 
can  be  brachistochronous  without  the  separate  ele- 
ments necessarily  exhibiting  this  property.  By  con- 
siderations of  this  character,  Euler  perceived,  that  the 
principle  introduced  by  James  Bernoulli  did  not  hold 
universally  good,  but  that  in  cases  of  the  kind  referred 
to,  a  more  detailed  treatment  was  required. 

7.  The  methodical  arrangement  and  the  great  num- 
ber of  the  problems  solved,  gradually  led  Euler  to  sub- 


436  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

LagranKe's  stantially  the  same  methods  that  Lagrange  afterwards 
Ei8to%of  developed  in  a  somewhat  different  form,  and  which 
lus  of  Vari-  now  go  by  the  name  of  the  Calculus  of  Variations,  First, 
John  Bernoulli  lighted  on  an  accidental  solution  of  a 
problem,  by  analogy.  James  Bernoulli  developed,  for 
the  solution  of  such  problems,  a  geometrical  method. 
Euler  generalised  the  problems  and  the  geometrical 
method.  And  finally,  Lagrange,  entirely  emancipating 
himself  from  the  consideration  of  geometrical  figures, 
gave  an  analytical  method.  Lagrange  remarked,  that 
the  increments  which  functions  receive  in  consequence 
of  a  change  in  their /^rw  are  quite  analogous  to  the  in- 
crements they  receive  in  consequence  of  a  change  of 
their  independent  variables.  To  distinguish  the  two 
species  of  increments,  Lagrange  denoted  the  former 
by  6y  the  latter  by  d.  By  the  observation  of  this  anal- 
ogy Lagrange  was  enabled  to  write  down  at  once  the 
equations  which  solve  problems  of  maxima  and  minima. 
Of  this  idea,  which  has  proved  itself  a  very  fertile  one, 
Lagrange  never  gave  a  verification ;  in  fact,  did  not 
even  attempt  it.  His  achievement  is  in  every  respect 
a  pectiliar  one.  He  saw,  with  great  economical  in- 
sight, the  foundations  which  in  his  judgment  were  suf- 
ficiently secure  and  serviceable  to  build  upon.  But 
the  acceptance  of  these  fundamental  principles  them- 
selves was  vindicated  only  by  its  results.  Instead  of 
employing  himself  on  the  demonstration  of  these  prin- 
ciples, he  showed  with  what  success  they  could  be  em- 
ployed. {Essai  d^une  nouvelle  methode  pour  determiner 
les  maxima  et  minima  des  formules  integrates  indefinies, 
Misc,  Taur,     1762.) 

The  difficulty  which  Lagrange's  contemporaries  and 
successors  experienced  in  clearly  grasping  his  idea,  is 
quite  intelligible.  Euler  sought  in  vain  to  clear  up  the 


FORMAL  DEVELOPMENT.  437 

difierence  between  a  variation  and  a  differential  by  The  mis- 
imagining  constants  contained  in  the  function,  with  Uons  of  La- 
the change  of  which  the  form  of  the  function  changed,  idea. 
The  increments  of  the  value  of  the  function  arising 
from  the  increments  of  these  constants  were  regarded 
by  him  as  the  variations,  while  the  increments  of  the 
function  springing  from  the  increments  of  the  indepen- 
dent variables  were  the  differentials.  The  conception 
of  the  Calculus  of  Variations  that  springs  from  such  a 
view  is  singularly  timid,  narrow,  and  illogical,  and  does 
not  compare  with  that  of  Lagrange.  Even  LindelSfs 
modern  work,  so  excellent  in  other  respects,  is  marred 
by  this  defect.  The  first  really  competent  presenta- 
tion of  Lagrange's  idea  is,  in  our  opinion,  that  of  Jel- 
LETT.*  Jellett  appears  to  have  said  what  Lagrange  per- 
haps was  unable  fully  to  say,  perhaps  did  not  deem  it 
necessary  to  say. 

8.  Jellett's  view  is,  in  substance,  this.     Quantities  J«"«^'««^- 
generally  are  divisible  into  constant  and  variable  quan-  the  pnnci- 

.  .  ,  .  pies  of  the 

titles;  the  latter  being  subdivided  into  independent Caicuins of 
and  dependent  variables,  or  such  as  may  be  arbitrarily 
changed,  and  such  whose  change  depends  on  the 
change  of  other,  independent,  variables,  in  some  way 
connected  with  them.  The  latter  are  called  functions 
of  the  former,  and  the  nature  of  the  relation  that  con- 
nects them  is  termed  the  form  of  the  function.  Now, 
quite  analogous  to  this  division  of  quantities  into  con- 
stant and  variable,  is  the  division  of  the  forms  of  func- 
tions into  determinate  (constant)  and  indeterminate  (vari- 
able). If  the  form  of  a  function,  y  =  <p{x)j  is  inde- 
terminate, or  variable,  the  value  of  the  function  y  can 
change  in  two  ways  :    (i)  by  an  increment  dx  of  the 

•  An  RUmentary  TretUist  on  tkt  CaUnhu  ef  Variaiiinu,    By  the  Rev. 
John  Hewitt  Jellett.  Dublin,  183a 


438  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

independent  variable  jr,  or  (2)  by  a  change  oiform,  by 
a  passage  from  (pio  <p^.  The  first  change  is  the  dif- 
ferential dy,  the  second,  the  variation  dy.  Accord- 
ingly, 

dy=  q}(x  -\-  dx)  —  q)  (^),  and 

^y  =  <P\  W  —  9  (^)- 

The  object         The  change  of  value  of  an  indeterminate  function 

of  the  cal- 

cuius  of  va-  due  to  a  mere  change  of  form  involves  no  problem, 

riations  il- 

lustrated.  just  as  the  change  of  value  of  an  independent  variable 
involves  none.  We  may  assume  any  change  of  form 
we  please,  and  so  produce  any  change  of  value  we 
please.  A  problem  is  not  presented  till  the  change  in 
value  of  a  determinate  function  {F^  of  an  indetermi- 
nate function  9?,  due  to  a  change  of  form  of  the  included 
indeterminate  function,  is  required.  For  example,  if 
we  have  a  plane  curve  of  the  indeterminate  ioxxa  y=- 
q>  (x)^  the  length  of  its  arc  between  the  abscissae  x^ 
and\^j  is 

a  determinate  function  of  an  indeterminate  function. 
The  moment  a  definite  form  of  curve  is  fixed  upon,  the 
value  of  5  can  be  given.  For  any  change  of  form  of 
the  curve,  the  change  in  value  of  the  length  of  the  arc, 
6S^  is  determinable.  In  the  example  given,  the  func- 
tion S  does  not  contain  the  function  y  directly,  but 
through  its  first  differential  coefficient  dy/dx,  which  is 
itself  dependent  on  y.  Let  u  =  F{y^  be  a  determinate 
function  of  an  indeterminate  function  j'  =  <p{x^  ;  then 

Su=.F{y+Sy)-  F{y)  ='^-^-}p  Sy. 

Again,  let  u  =F{y,  dyjdx)  be  a  determinate  function 


FORMAL  DEVELOPMENT.  439 

of  an  indeterminate  function,  y  =  <p{x).  For  a  change 
of  form  of  (p,  the  value  of  y  changes  by  dy  and  the 
value  of  dy/dx  by  6{dy/dx).  The  corresponding  change 
in  the  value  of  u  is 

dy  "^  dy  dx 

dx 

dy 
The  expression  6  -/-  is  obtained  by  our  definition  from  Expres- 

ax  siona  for 

the  varia- 

dy^  d(^y^6y^  _dy  ^  djy  {l^Stili'*'" 

dx  dx  dx  dx'  coeffidenta 

Similarly,  the  following  results  are  found : 

^d^y^d^dy       d^  y^d^dy 
dx^  —  ~dx^'      d~x^  ^  ~d~x^' 

and  so  forth. 

We  now  proceed  to  a  problem,  namely,  the  de-Aprobieia 
termination  of  the  form  of  the  function  ^  =  ^^(x)  that 
will  render 

U=J^Vdx 
where 


a  maximum  or  minimum  ;  q>  denoting  an  indetermi- 
nate, and  F  a  determinate  function.  The  value  of  U 
may  be  varied  (i)  by  a  change  of  the  limits,  x^^  x^. 
Outside  of  the  limits,  the  change  of  the  independent 
variables  x,  as  such,  does  not  affect  U\  accordingly, 
if  we  regard  the  limits  as  fixed,  this  is  the  only  respect 
in  which  we  need  attend  to  x.  The  only  other  way 
(2)  in  which  the  value  of  U  is  susceptible  of  variation 


440  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

is  by  a  change  of  iki^form  oiy=.  <p(x).  This  produces 
a  change  of  va/ue  in 


amounting  to 


*  » 


and  so  forth.  The  total  change  in  [/,  which  we  shall 
call  DC/,  and  to  express  the  maximum-minimum  con- 
dition put  =  0,  consists  of  the  differential  dC/  and  the 
variation  617.     Accordingly, 

I>17=  dU'+  6C/=  0. 

Expresaion  Denoting  by  V^dx^  and  —  ^o^-^o  ^^®  increments  of 
variation  of  U  due  to  the  change  of  the  limits,  we  then  have 

the  func- 
tion in  •**! 

question.  DU=  V^  dx^  —  V^  dx^  +  6 J  Vdx  = 

V^  dx^  —V^dx^  -f  J^d  r.  dx  =  0. 
But  by  the  principles  stated  on  page  439  we  further  get 

^^=dy^y\dy^dx'^-d--y^dx-^     .  .  .  = 

dx  dx^ 

dV  dVddy        dV  d^dy^ 

^      /y  '^'^  /""y  d'x^'^  — 

dx  dx^ 

For  the  sake  of  brevity  we  put 

dy  ""  ^yy  ""  ^y^'y  ""     '' 

dx  dx^ 


Then 


(J  rV//jc=r 


FORMAL  DEVELOPMENT.  441 

^o      \  /  Qie  third 

term  of  the 

One  difl&culty  here  is,  that  not  only  dy,  but  also  the  foPfhfjJi"  | 
terms  ddy/dx^  d^  dy/dx^  ....  occur  in  this  equation,  ▼aria'^on- 
— terms  which  are  dependent  on  one  another,  but  not 
in  a  directly  obvious  manner.     This  drawback  can  be 
removed  by  successive  integration  by  parts,  by  means 
of  the  formula 

Cudv  =  uv —  Cvdu. 

By  this  method 

^»  -d-x  -  di  ^y  +  J  -d^  *-^''*'  "'^^  ^°  °°- 

Performing  all  these  integrations  between  the  limits, 
we  obtain  for  the  condition  DU^=^  the  expression 

0  =  V^dx^  -  V^  dx^ 


dP^   ,       \  {d6y\       /_       </^3   ,       \  idSy\ 


+i'.-'5+-),(f),-(-'-t^-+-jA*; 

+ 

which  now  contains  only  6y  under  the  integral  sign. 

The  terms  in  the  first  line  of  this  expression  are 
independent  of  any  change  in  the  form  of  the  function 
and  depend  solely  upon  the  variation  of  the  limits. 


442  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

The  inter-  The  terms  of  the  two  following  lines  depend  on  the 
the  results,  change  in  the  form  of  the  function,  for  the  limiting 
values  of  x  only ;  and  the  indices  i  and  2  state  that 
the  actual  limiting  values  are  to  be  put  in  the  place  of 
the  general  expressions.  The  terms  of  the  last  line, 
finally,  depend  on  the  general  change  in  the  form  of 
the  function.  Collecting  all  the  terms,  except  those  in 
the  last  line,  under  one  designation  a^ — a^y  and  calling 
the  expression  in  parentheses  in  the  last  line  /9,  we 
have 

0  =  Of,  —  «o  +  r^  •  ^y '  ^^' 

But  this  equation  can  be  satisfied  only  if 

a,^a^  =  0 (1) 

and 

f/3dydx  =  0 (2) 

For  if  each  of  the  members  were  not  equal  to  zero, 
each  would  be  determined  by  the  other.  But  the  in- 
tegral of  an  indeterminate  function  cannot  be  expressed 
in  terms  of  its  limiting  values  only.  Assuming,  there- 
fore, that  the  equation 

j)36y^x  =  0, 

Theequa-  holds  generally  good,  its  conditions  can  be  satisfied, 
solves  the  since  6y  is  throughout  arbitrary  and  its  generality  of 
makes  the   form  cannot  be  restricted,  only  by  making  y5  =  0.    By 

function  in 

question  a   the  equation 

therefore,  the  form  of  the  function  y  =  q>(x)  that  makes 
the  expression  C/'a  maximum  or  minimum  is  defined. 


maximum 
or  mini- 
mum. 


FORMAL  DEVELOPMENT,  443 

Equation  (3)  was  found  by  Euler.  But  Lagrange  first 
showed  the  application  of  equation  (i),  for  the  deter- 
mination of  a  function  by  the  conditions  at  its  limits. 
By  equation  (3),  which  it  must  satisfy,  the^r^i  of  the 
function  y  =  <p{x)  is  generally  determined ;  but  this 
equation  contains  a  number  of  arbitrary  constants, 
whose  values  are  determined  solely  by  the  conditions 
at  the  limits.  With  respect  to  notation,  J ellett  rightly 
remarks,  that  the  employment  of  the  symbol  ^  in  the 
first  two  terms  V^Sx^  z=zV^dx^  of  equation  (i),  (the 
form  used  by  Lagrange,)  is  illogical,  and  he  correctly 
puts  for  the  increments  of  the  independent  variables 
the  usual  S5mibols  dx^y  dx^, 

9.  To  illustrate  the  use  to  which  these  equations  a  practical 

illustration 

may  be  put,  let  us  seek  the  form  of  the  function  that  of  the  use 

;  '^      '  of  these 

makes  equations. 


/v 


1  + 

a  minimum — the  shortest  line.     Here 


All  expressions  except 


vanish  in  equation  (3),  and  that  equation  becomes 
dP^jdx  =  0  ;  which  means  that  -P,,  and  consequently 
its  only  variable,  dy/dx,  is  independent  of  x.  Hence, 
dy/dx  =  a,  and  y  =  ax  -{•  b,  where  a  and  b  are  con- 
stants. 

The  constants  a,  b  are  determined  by  the  values  of 


444  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

Develop-     the  limits.     If  the  straight  line  passes  through  the 

ment  of  the 

illustration,  points  Xq,  y^  and  x^y  y^y  then 

^o=""«in (-) 

and  as  ^Xq  =  dx^  =  0,  Sy^  =  6y^  =  0,  equation  (i) 
vanishes.  The  coefficients  6  (dy/dx),  ^  {d^yjdx^), .... 
independently  vanish.  Hence,  the  values  of  a  and  b 
are  determined  by  the  equations  {m)  alone. 

If  the  limits  x^y  x^  only  are  given,  but^^,  ^^  are 
indeterminate,  we  have  dx^  =  //x^  =  0,  and  equation 
(i)  takes  the  form 

— T^=z3  (^yi  —  ^yo)  =  0, 

Vl  +  a^ 

which,  since  Sy^  and  6y^  are  arbitrary,  can  only  be 
satisfied  if  ^  =  0.  The  straight  line  is  in  this  case 
y=zd,  parallel  to  the  axis  of  abscissae,  and  as  ^  is  inde- 
terminate, at  any  distance  from  it. 

It  will  be  noticed,  that  equation  (i)  and  the  sub- 
sidiary conditions  expressed  in  equation  (»i),  with  re- 
spect to  the  determination  of  the  constants,  generally 
complement  each  other. 

If 

Xa 


=/-'\ 


• + I'i)'  ^' 


is  to  be  made  a  minimum,  the  integration  of  the  appro- 
priate form  of  (3)  will  give 


r  .  ^ 

jr  —  r  X  —  c 


C 

y=-o 


e     -\-    e 


c 


If  Z is  a  minimum,  then  7.71  Z  also  is  a  minimum,  and 
the  curve  found  will  give,  by  rotation  about  the  axis 
of  abscissae,  the  least  surface  of  revolution.     Further, 


FORMAL  DEVELOPMENT.  445 

to  a  minimum  of  Z  the  lowest  position  of  the  centre  of 
gravity  of  a  homogeneously  heavy  curve  of  this  kind 
corresponds  ;  the  curve  is  therefore  a  catenary.  The 
determination  of  the  constants  Cy  c^  is  effected  by  means 
of  the  limiting  conditions,  as  above. 

In  the  treatment  of  mechanical  problems,  a  dis- variations 

*  and  virtual 

tinction  is  made  between  the  increments  of  coordmates  displace- 
ments dis- 

that  actually  take  place  in  time,  namely,  dx,  dy,  dz,  tinguished. 
and  the  possible  displacements  ^x^  dy^  dz,  considered, 
for  instance,  in  the  application  of  the  principle  of  vir- 
tual velocities.  The  latter,  as  a  rule,  are  not  varia- 
tions; that  is,  are  not  changes  of  value  that  spring 
from  changes  in  the  form  of  a  function.  Only  when 
we  consider  a  mechanical  system  that  is  a  continuum, 
as  for  example  a  string,  a  flexible  surface,  an  elastic 
body,  or  a  liquid,  are  we  at  liberty  to  regard  6x,  6y, 
dz  as  indeterminate  functions  of  the  coordinates  x,  y, 
z,  and  are  we  concerned  with  variations. 

It  is  not  our  purpose  in  this  work,  to  develop  math-  importance 
ematical  theories,  but  simply  to  treat  the  purely  phys-  caius  of  va- 

'  '^  -^  jT  ,       .  .    nations  for 

ical  part  of  mechanics.  But  the  history  of  the  isopen-  mechanics, 
metrical  problems  and  of  the  calculus  of  variations  had 
to  be  touched  upon,  because  these  researches  have  ex- 
ercised a  very  considerable  influence  on  the  develop- 
ment of  mechanics.  Our  sense  of  the  general  prop- 
erties of  systems,  and  of  properties  of  maxima  and 
minima  in  particular,  was  much  sharpened  by  these 
investigations,  and  properties  of  the  kind  referred  to 
were  subsequently  discovered  in  mechanical  systems 
with  great  facility.  As  a  fact,  physicists,  since  La- 
grange's time,  usually  express  mechanical  principles 
in  a  maximal  or  minimal  form.  This  predilection 
would  be  unintelligible  without  a  knowledge  of  the 
historical  development. 


446  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 


II. 

THEOLOGICAL.  ANIMISTIC,   AND     MYSTICAL    POINTS  OF  VIEW 

IN  MECHANICS. 

I.  If,  in  entering  a  parlor  in  Germany,  we  happen 
to  hear  something  said  about  some  man  being  very 
pious,  without  having  caught  the  name,  we  may  fancy 
that  Privy  Counsellor  X  was  spoken  of, — or  Herr  von 
Y ;  we  should  hardly  think  of  a  scientific  man  of  our 
acquaintance.  It  would,  however,  be  a  mistake  to  sup- 
pose that  the  want  of  cordiality,  occasionally  rising  to 
embittered  controversy,  which  has  existed  in  our  day 
between  the  scientific  and  the  theological  faculties, 
always  separated  them.  A  glance  at  the  history  of 
science  suffices  to  prove  the  contrary. 
The  con-  People  talk  of  the  **  conflict"  of  science  and  the- 

ence  and  ology,  or  better  of  science  and  the  church.  It  is  in 
truth  a  prolific  theme.  On  the  one  hand,  we  have  the 
long  catalogue  of  the  sins  of  the  church  against  pro- 
gress, on  the  other  side  a  **  noble  army  of  martyrs,*' 
among  them  no  less  distinguished  figures  than  Galileo 
and  Giordano  Bruno.  It  was  only  by  good  luck  that 
Descartes,  pious  as  he  was,  escaped  the  same  fate. 
These  things  are  the  commonplaces  of  history ;  but  it 
would  be  a  great  mistake  to  suppose  that  the  phrase 
** warfare  of  science"  is  a  correct  ■  description  of  its 
general  historic  attitude  toward  religion,  that  the  only 
repression  of  intellectual  development  has  come  from 
priests,  and  that  if  their  hands  had  been  held  off,  grow- 
ing science  would  have  shot  up  with  stupendous  velo- 
city. No  doubt,  external  opposition  did  have  to  be 
fought ;  and  the  battle  with  it  was  no  child's  play. 


FORMAL  DEVELOPMENT,  447 

Nor  was  any  engine  too  base  for  the  church  to  handle  The  struR- 

.  ,  sleofscien- 

in  this  struggle.     She  considered  nothing  but  how  to  tists  with 

,  their  own 

conquer  ;  and  no  temporal  policy  ever  was  conducted  precon- 

ceiveci 

SO  selfishly,  so  unscrupulously,  or  so  cruelly.  But  in-  ideas, 
vestigators  have  had  another  struggle  on  their  hands, 
and  by  no  means  an  easy  one,  the  struggle  with  their 
own  preconceived  ideas,  and  especially  with  the  notion 
that  philosophy  and  science  must  be  founded  on  the- 
ology. It  was  but  slowly  that  this  prejudice  little  by 
little  was  erased. 

2.   But  let  the  facts  speak  for  themselves,  while  we  Historical 

,  ,  examples. 

introduce  the  reader  to  a  few  historical  personages. 

Napier,  the  inventor  of  logarithms,  an  austere  Puri- 
tan, who  lived  in  the  sixteenth  century,  was,  in  addi- 
tion to  his  scientific  avocations,  a  zealous  theologian. 
Napier  applied  himself  to  some  extremely  curious 
speculations.  He  wrote  an  exegetical  commentary  on 
the  Book  of  Revelation,  with  propositions  and  mathe- 
matical demonstrations.  Proposition  XXVI,  for  ex- 
ample, maintains  that  the  pope  is  the  Antichrist ;  propo- 
sition XXXVI  declares  that  the  locusts  are  the  Turks 
and  Mohammedans  ;  and  so  forth. 

Blaise  Pascal  (i 623-1 662),  one  of  the  most  rounded 
geniuses  to  be  found  among  mathematicians  and  phys- 
icists, was  extremely  orthodox  and  ascetical.  So  deep 
were  the  convictions  of  his  heart,  that  despite  the  gen- 
tleness of  his  character,  he  once  openly  denounced  at 
Rouen  an  instructor  in  philosophy  as  a  heretic.  The 
healing  of  his  sister  by  contact  with  a  relic  most  seri- 
ously impressed  him,  and  he  regarded  her  cure  as  a 
miracle.  On  these  facts  taken  by  themselves  it  might 
be  wrong  to  lay  great  stress ;  for  his  whole  family  were 
much  inclined  to  religious  fanaticism.  But  there  are 
plenty  of  other  instances  of  his  religiosity.     Such  was 


448  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

Pascal.  his  resolve, — ^which  was  carried  out,  too, — to  abandon 
altogether  the  pursuits  of  science  and  to  devote  his  life 
solely  to  the  cause  of  Christianity.  Consolation,  he 
used  to  say,  he  could  find  nowhere  but  in  the  teachings 
of  Christianity  ;  and  all  the  wisdom  of  the  w6rld  availed 
him  not  a  whit.  The  sincerity  of  his  desire  for  the 
conversion  of  heretics  is  shown  in  his  Lettres  provin- 
dales,  where  he  vigorously  declaims  against  the  dread- 
ful subtleties  that  the  doctors  of  the  Sorbonne  had 
devised,  expressly  to  persecute  the  Jansenists.  Very 
remarkable  is  Pascal's  correspondence  with  the  theo- 
logians of  his  time  ;  and  a  modern  reader  is  not  a  little 
surprised  at  finding  this  great  "scientist"  seriously 
discussing  in  one  of  his  letters  whether  or  not  the  Devil 
was  able  to  work  miracles. 

otto  yon  Otto  von  Gucricke,  the  inventor  of  the  air-pump, 

occupies  himself,  at  the  beginning  of  his  book,  now 
little  over  two  hundred  years  old,  with  the  miracle  of 
Joshua,  which  he  seeks  to  harmonise  with  the  ideas 
of  Copernicus.  In  like  manner,  we  find  his  researches 
on  the  vacuum  and  the  nature  of  the  atmosphere  in- 
troduced by  disquisitions  concerning  the  location  of 
heaven,  the  location  of  hell,  and  so  forth.  Although 
Guericke  really  strives  to  answer  these  questions  as  ra- 
tionally as  he  can,  still  we  notice  that  they  give  him 
considerable  trouble,— rquestions,  be  it  remembered, 
that  to-day  the  theologians  themselves  would  consider 
absurd.  Yet  Guericke  was  a  man  who  lived  after  the 
Reformation  ! 

The  giant  mind  of  Newton  did  not  disdain  to  employ 
itself  on  the  interpretation  of  the  Apocalypse.  On  such 
subjects  it  was  difficult  for  a  sceptic  to  converse  with 
him.  When  Halley  once  indulged  in  a  jest  concerning 
theological  questions,  he  is  said  to  have  curtly  repulsed 


FORMAL  DEVELOPMENT.  449 

him  with  the  remark  :   **  I  have  studied  these  things  ;  Newton  and 

Leibnitz. 

you  have  not  I " 

We  need  not  tarry  by  Leibnitz,  the  inventor  of  the 
best  of  all  possible  worlds  and  of  pre-established  har- 
mony— inventions  which  Voltaire  disposed  of  in  Can- 
didff  a  humorous  novel  with  a  deeply  philosophical  pur- 
pose. But  everybody  knows  that  Leibnitz  was  almost 
if  not  quite  as  much  a  theologian,  as  a  man  of  science. 

Let  us  turn,  however,  to  the  last  century.  Euler,  in  Euier. 
his  Letters  to  a  German  Princess^  deals  with  theologico- 
philosophical  problems  in  the  midst  of  scientific  ques- 
tions. He  speaks  of  the  difficulty  involved  in  explaining 
the  interaction  of  body  and  mind,  due  to  the  total 
diversity  of  these  two  phenomena, — a  diversity  to  his 
mind  undoubted.  The  system  of  occasionalism,  devel- 
oped by  Descartes  and  his  followers,  agreeably  to  which 
God  executes  for  every  purpose  of  the  soul,  (the  soul  it- 
self not  being  able  to  do  so,)  a  corresponding  movement 
of  the  body,  does  not  quite  satisfy  him.  He  derides, 
also,  and  not  without  humor,  the  doctrine  of  pre- 
established  harmony,  according  to  which  perfect  agree- 
ment was  established  from  the  beginning  between  the 
movements  of  the  body  and  the  volitions  of  the  soul, — 
although  neither  is  in  any  way  connected  with  the 
other, — just  as  there  is  harmony  between  two  different 
but  like-constructed  clocks.  He  remarks,  that  in  this 
view  his  own  body  is  as  foreign  to  him  as  that  of  a 
rhinoceros  in  the  midst  of  Africa,  which  might  just  as 
well  be  in  pre-established  harmony  with  his  soul  as 
its  own.  Let  us  hear  his  own  words.  In  his  day,  Latin 
was  almost  universally  written.  When  a  German 
scholar  wished  to  be  especially  condescending,  he 
wrote  in  French  :  * '  Si  dans  le  cas  d*un  d^r^glement 
**de  mon  corps  Dieu  ajustait  celui  d*un  rhinoceros, 


450  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

'*en  sorte  que  ses  mouvements  fussent  tellement  d'ac- 
**  cord  avec  les  ordres  de  mon  ame,  qu'il  levat  la  patte 
'*au  moment  que  je  voudrais  lever  la  main,  et  ainsi 

*  *  des  autres  operations,  ce  serait  alors  mon  corps.    Je 

*  *  me  trouverais  subitement  dans  la  forme  d*un  rhino- 
'<  ceros  au  milieu  de  TAfrique,  mais  non  obstant  cela 
"mon  ime  continuerait  les  m^me  operations.  J*aurais 
"^galement  Thonneur  d'dcrire  k  V.  A.,  mais  je  ne  sais 
**  pas  comment  elle  recevrait  mes  lettres." 

Euier's  Ouc  would  almost  imagine  that  Euler,  here,  had  been 

thcoloEic&l 

proclivities  tempted  to  play  Voltairolt  And  yet,  apposite  as  was 
his  criticism  in  this  vital  point,  the  mutual  action  of 
body  and  soul  remained  a  miracle  to  him,  still.  But  he 
extricates  himself,  however,  from  the  question  of  the 
freedom  of  the  will,  very  sophistically.  To  give  some 
idea  of  the  kind  of  questions  which  a  scientist  was  per- 
mitted to  treat  in  those  days,  it  may  be  remarked  that 
Euler  institutes  in  his  physical  ** Letters"  investiga- 
tions concerning  the  nature  of  spirits,  the  connection 
between  body  and  soul,  the  freedom  of  the  will,  the 
influence  of  that  freedom  on  physical  occurrences, 
prayer,  physical  and  moral  evils,  the  conversion  of  sin- 
ners, and  such  like  topics  ; — and  this  in  a  treatise  full 
of  clear  physical  ideas  and  not  devoid  of  philosophical 
ones,  where  the  well-known  circle-diagrams  of  logic 
have  their  birth-place. 

Character         3.   Let  these  examples  of  religious  physici^s  suffice. 

ofihetheo-    __      ,  ,  ,      ,  .  •  n      r  , 

logical  We  have  selected  them  intentionally  from  among  the 
the  great  in-  foremost  of  Scientific  discoverers.  The  theological  pro- 
clivities which  these  men  followed,  belong  wholly  to 
their  innermost  private  life.  They  tell  us  openly  things 
which  they  are  not  compelled  to  tell  us,  things  about 
which  they  might  have  remained  silent.  What  they 
utter  are  not  opinions  forced  upon  them  from  without ; 


FORMAL  DEVELOPMENT.  451 

they  are  their  own  sincere  views.  They  were  not  con- 
scious of  any  theological  constraint.  In  a  court  which 
harbored  a  Lamettrie  and  a  Voltaire,  Euler  had  no  rea- 
son to  conceal  his  real  convictions. 

According  to  the  modern  notion,  these  men  should  character 

of  their  age. 

at  least  have  seen  that  the  questions  they  discussed 
did  not  belong  under  the  heads  where  they  put  them, 
that  they  were  not  questions  of  science.  Still,  odd  as 
this  contradiction  between  inherited  theological  beliefs 
and  independently  created  scientific  convictions  seems 
to  us,  it  is  no  reason  for  a  diminished  admiration  of 
those  leaders  of  scientific  thought.  Nay,  this  very  fact 
is  a  proof  of  their  stupendous  mental  power  :  they  were 
able,  in  spite  of  the  contracted  horizon  of  their  age,  to 
which  even  their  own  apergus  were  chiefly  limited,  to 
point  out  the  path  to  an  elevation,  where  our  genera- 
tion has  attained  a  freer  point  of  view. 

Every  unbiassed  mind  must  admit  that  the  age  in 
which  the  chief  development  of  the  science  of  mechan- 
ics took  place,  was  an  £ige  of  predominantly  theological 
cast.  Theological  questions  were  excited  by  everything, 
and  modified  everything.  No  wonder,  then,  that  me- 
chanics took  the  contagion.  But  the  thoroughness  with 
which  theological  thought  thus  permeated  scientific 
inquiry,  will  best  be  seen  by  an  examination  of  details. 

4.   The  impulse  imparted  in  antiquity  to  this  direc-  Galileo's 

researches 

tion  of  thought  by  Hero  and  Pappus  has  been  alluded  on  the 
to  in  the  preceding  chapter.  At  the  beginning  of  the  materials, 
seventeenth  century  we  find  Galileo  occupied  with  prob- 
lems concerning  the  strength  of  materials.  He  shows 
that  hollow  tubes  offer  a  greater  resistance  to  flexure 
than  solid  rods  of  the  same  length  and  the  same  quantity 
of  material,  and  at  once  applies  this  discovery  to  the 
explanation  of  the  forms  of  the  bones  of  animals,  which 


452  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

are  usually  hollow  and  cylindrical  in  shape.  The  phe- 
nonnenon  is  easily  illustrated  by  the  comparison  of  a 
flatly  folded  and  a  rolled  sheet  of  paper.  A  horizontal 
beam  fastened  at  one  extremity  and  loaded  at  the  other 
may  be  remodelled  so  as  to  be  thinner  at  the  loaded 
end  without  any  loss  of  stiffness  and  with  a  consider- 
able saving  of  material.  Galileo  determined  the  form  of 
a  beam  of  equal  resistance  at  each  cross-section.  He 
also  remarked  that  animals  of  similar  geometrical  con- 
struction but  of  considerable  difference  of  size  would 
comply  in  very  unequal  proportions  with  the  laws  of 
resistance. 
Evidences         The  forms  of  boues,  feathers,  stalks,  and  other  or- 

of  design  .  1,1  .... 

in  nature,  ganic  Structures,  adapted,  as  they  are,  m  their  minut- 
est details  to  the  purposes  they  serve,  are  highly  cal- 
culated to  make  a  profound  impression  on  the  thinking 
beholder,  and  this  fact  has  again  and  again  been  ad- 
duced in  proof  of  a  supreme  wisdom  ruling  in  nature. 
Let  us  examine,  for  instance,  the  pinion-feather  of  a 
bird.  The  quill  is  a  hollow  tube  diminishing  in  thick- 
ness as  we  go  towards  the  end,  that  is,  is  a  body  of 
equal  resistance.  Each  little  blade  of  the  vane  re- 
peats in  miniature  the  same  construction.  It  would 
require  considerable  technical  knowledge  even  to  imi- 
tate a  feather  of  this  kind,  let  alone  invent  it.  We 
should  not  forget,  however,  that  scrutiny,  or  quest  of 
explanation,  not  wonder,  is  the  office  of  science.  We 
know  how  Darwin  sought  to  solve  these  problems,  by 
the  theory  of  natural  selection.  That  Darwin's  solution 
is  a  complete  one,  may  fairly  be  doubted  ;  Darwin  him- 
self questioned  it.  All  external  conditions  would  be 
powerless  if  something  were  not  present  that  admitted 
of  variation.  But  there  can  be  no  question  that  his 
theory  is  the  first  serious  attempt  to  replace  mere  won- 


FORMAL  DEVELOPMENT,  453 

der  at  the  adaptations  of  organic  nature  by  serious  in- 
quiry into  the  mode  of  their  origin. 

Pappus's  ideas  concerning  the  cells  of  honeycombs  The  cells  r.f 

,  ,  .  r         .  ,    ,.  .  ,  ,      the  honey- 

were  the  subject  of  animated  discussion  as  late  as  the  comb. 

eighteenth  century.  In  a  treatise,  published  in  1865, 
entitled  Homes  Without  Hands  (p.  428),  Wood  substan- 
tially relates  the  following  :  "  Maraldi  had  been  struck 
with  the  great  regularity  of  the  cells  of  the  honey- 
comb. He  measured  the  angles  of  the  lozenge-shaped 
plates,  or  rhombs,  that  form  the  terminal  walls  of  the 
cells,  and  found  them  to  be  respectively  109^28'  and 
70°  32'.  Reaumur,  convinced  that  these  angles  were  in 
some  way  connected  with  the  economy  of  the  cells, 
requested  the  mathematician  Konig  to  calculate  the 
form  of  a  hexagonal  prism  terminated  by  a  pyramid 
composed  of  three  equal  and  similar  rhombs,  which 
would  give  the  greatest  amount  of  si>ace  with  a  given 
amount  of  material.  The  answer  was,  that  the  angles 
should  be  109^26'  and  70°  34'.  The  difference,  accord- 
ingly, was  two  minutes.  Maclaurin,*  dissatisfied  with 
this  agreement, repeated  Maraldi's  measurements, found 
them  correct,  and  discovered,  in  going  over  the  calcu- 
lation, an  error  in  the  logarithmic  table  employed  by 
Konig.  Not  the  bees,  but  the  mathematicians  were 
wrong,  and  the  bees  had  helped  to  detect  the  error  ! " 
Any  one  who  is  acquainted  with  the  methods  of  meas- 
uring crystals  and  has  seen  the  cell  of  a  honeycomb, 
with  its  rough  and  non -reflective  surfaces,  will  question 
whether  the  measurement  of  such  cells  can  be  executed 
with  a  probable  error  of  only  two  minutes,  f  So,  we 
must  take  this  story  as  a  sort  of  pious  mathematical 

*  Fkilo*ophic»l  TranMoction*  for  1743. — Trans. 

t  But  see  G.  F.  Maraldi  in  the  Mimaires  d«  VacatUmie  for  1712.  It  is,  how- 
ever, now  well  known  the  cells  vary  considerably.  See  Chauncey  Wright, 
PhiUsophieal  DiMcuwtions,  1877,  p.  3x1.  — TVaw^. 


454  'J^^F-  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

fairy-tale,  quite  apart  from  the  consideration  that  noth- 
ing would  follow  from  it  even  were  it  true.  Besides, 
from  a  mathematical  point  of  view,  the  problem  is  too 
imperfectly  formulated  to  enable  us  to  decide  the  ex- 
tent to  which  the  bees  have  solved  it. 
Other  The  ideas  of  Hero  and  Fermat,  referred  to  in  the 

instances. 

previous  chapter,  concerning  the  motion  of  light,  at 
once  received  from  the  hands  of  Leibnitz  a  theolog- 
ical coloring,  and  played,  as  has  been  before  mentioned, 
a  predominant  role  in  the  development  of  the  calculus 
of  variations.  In  Leibnitz's  correspondence  with  John 
Bernoulli,  theological  questions  are  repeatedly  dis- 
cussed in  the  very  midst  of  mathematical  disquisitions. 
Their  language  is  not  unfrequently  couched  in  biblical 
pictures.  Leibnitz,  for  example,  says  that  the  problem 
of  the  brachistochrone  lured  him  as  the  apple  had  lured 
Eve. 
Thetheo-  Maupertuis,   the  famous  president  of  the  Berlin 

nei  of  the^  Academy,  and  a  friend  of  Frederick  the  Great,  gave 
least  ac-  a  ncw  impulse  lo  the  theologising  bent  of  physics  by 
the  enunciation  of  his  principle  of  least  action.  In  the 
treatise  which  formulated  this  obscure  principle,  and 
which  betrayed  in  Maupertuis  a  woeful  lack  of  mathe- 
matical accuracy,  the  author  declared  his  principle  to  be 
the  one  which  best  accorded  with  the  wisdom  of  the 
Creator.  Maupertuis  was  an  ingenious  man,  but  not  a 
man  of  strong,  practical  sense.  This  is  evidenced  by 
the  schemes  he  was  incessantly  devising :  his  bold  prop- 
ositions to  found  a  city  in  which  only  Latin  should  be 
spoken,  to  dig  a  deep  hole  in  the  earth  to  find  new 
substances,  to  institute  psychological  investigations  by 
means  of  opium  and  by  the  dissection  of  monkeys,  to 
explain  the  formation  of  the  embryo  by  gravitation,  and 
so  forth.     He"  was  sharply  satirised  by  Voltaire  in  the 


FORMAL  DEVELOPMENT.  455 

Histoire  du  docteur  Akakia,   a  work  which  led,  as  we 
know,  to  the  rupture  between  Frederick  and  Voltaire. 

Maupertuis's  principle  would  in  all  probability  soon  Enier'sre- 

-  ,r  t,-r^f  1  1  tention  of 

have  been  forgotten,  had  Euler  not  taken  up  the  sug-  the  thcoioK- 

icsil  b&sis  of 

gestion.  Euler  magnanimously  left  the  principle  its  this  prin- 
name,  Maupertuis  the  glory  of  the  invention,  and  con- 
verted it  into  something  new  and  really  serviceable. 
What  Maupertuis  meant  to  convey  is  very  difficult  to 
ascertain.  What  Euler  meant  may  be  easily  shown  by 
simple  examples.  If  a  body  is  constrained  to  move  on  a 
rigid  surface,  for  instance,  on  the  surface  of  the  earth,  it 
will  describe  when  an  impulse  is  imparted  to  it,  the 
shortest  path  between  its  initial  and'  terminal  positions. 
Any  other  path  that  might  be  prescribed  it,  would  be 
longer  or  would  rfequire  a  greater  time.  This  principle 
finds  an  application  in  the  theory  of  atmospheric  and 
oceanic  currents.  The  theological  point  of  view,  Euler 
retained.  He  claims  it  is  possible  to  explain  phenomena, 
not  only  from  their  physical  causes^  but  also  from  their 
purposes,  *'As  the  construction  of  the  universe  is  the 
''most  perfect  possible,  being  the  handiwork  of  an 
"  all-wise  Maker,  nothing  can  be  met  with  in  the  world 
''in  which  some  maximal  or  minimal  property  is  not 
"displayed.  There  is,  consequently,  no  doubt  but 
"that  all  the  effects  of  the  world  can  be  derived  by 
"the  method  of  maxima  and  minima  from  their  final 
"causes  as  well  as  from  their  efficient  ones."* 

5.   Similarly,  the  notions  of  the  constancy  of  the 
quantity  of  matter,  of  the  constancy  of  the  quantity  of 

*  **  Qunm  enim  mundi  universi  fabrica  sit  perfectissima,  atque  a  creatore 
sapientissimo  absoluta,  nihil  omnino  in  mundo  contingit,  in  quo  non  maximi 
minimive  ratio  quaepiam  eluceat ;  quam  ob  rem  dubium  prorsus  est  nullum, 
quin  omnes  mundi  effectus  ex  causis  finalibus,  ope  method!  maximorum  et 
minimorum,  aequo  feliciter  determinari  quaeant,  atque  ex  ipsis  causis  efficien-  * 

tibus."     {Methodtu  invtniendi  tineas  curuas  maximi  minimive  propitiate 
gamdentet,    Lausanne,  1744.) 


456  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECIIAXICS. 

The  central  motion,  of  the  indestructibility  of  work  or  energy,  con- 
modern  ceptions  which  completely  dominate  modern  physics, 
mainly  of    all  arose  under  the  influence  of  theological  ideas.   The 

theological  .  ^-         v     j    ^i      •  •     •       •  ^^  t 

origin.  uotious  m  questiou  had  their  origin  in  an  utterance  of 
Descartes,  before  mentioned,  in  the  Principles  of  Philos- 
ophy, agreeably  to  which  the  quantity  of  matter  and  mo- 
tion originally  created  in  the  world, — such  being  the 
only  course  compatible  with  the  constancy  of  the  Crea- 
tor,— is  always  preserved  unchanged.  The  conception 
of  the  manner  in  which  this  quantity  of  motion  should 
be  calculated  was  very  considerably  modified  in  the 
progress  of  the  idea  from  Descartes  to  Leibnitz,  and  to 
their  successors,  and  as  the  outcome  of  these  modifi- 
cations the  doctrine  gradually  and  slowly  arose  which 
is  now  called  the  "  law  of  the  conservation  of  energy." 
But  the  theological  background  of  these  ideas  only 
slowly  vanished.  In  fact,  at  the  present  day,  we  still 
meet  with  scientists  .who  indulge  in  self-created  mys- 
ticisms concerning  this  law. 

Gradual  During  the  entire  sixteenth  and  seventeenth  centu- 

iransition        •  j  i  e  •    i 

from  the     rics,  dowu  to  the  close  of  the  eighteenth,  the  prevail- 

theological   ..... 

point  of  ing  inclination  of  inquirers  was,  to  find  in  all  physical 
laws  some  particular  disposition  of  the  Creator.  But 
a  gradual  transformation  of  these  views  must  strike 
the  attentive  observer.  Whereas  with  Descartes  and 
Leibnitz  physics  and  theology  were  still  greatly  inter- 
mingled, in  the  subsequent  period  a  distinct  endeavor 
is  noticeable,  not  indeed  wholly  to  discard  theology, 
yet  to  separate  it  from  purely  physical  questions.  Theo- 
logical disquisitions  were  put  at  the  beginning  or  rele- 
gated to  the  end  of  physical  treatises.  Theological 
speculations  were  restricted,  as  much  as  possible,  to 
the  question  of  creation,  that,  from  this  point  onward, 
the  way  might  be  cleared  for  physics. 


view. 


FORMAL  DEVELOPMENT.  457 

Towards  the  close  of  the  eighteenth  century  a  re-  ultimate 

.  complete 

markable  change  took  place, — a  change  which  wasemancipa- 
apparentiy  an  abrupt  departure  from  the  current  trend  physics 

from  tlieol* 

of  thought,  but  in  reality  was  the  logical  outcome  of  ogy. 
the  development  indicated.  After  an  attemi>t  in  a 
youthful  work  to  found  mechanics  on  Euler'  s  principle 
of  least  action,  Lagrange,  in  a  subsequent  treatment 
of  the  subject,  declared  his  intention  of  utterly  disre- 
garding theological  and  metaphysical  speculations,  as 
in  their  nature  precarious  and  foreign  to  science.  He 
erected  a  new  mechanical  system  on  entirely  different 
foundations,  and  no  one  conversant  with  the  subject 
will  dispute  its  excellencies.  All  subsequent  scientists 
of  eminence  accepted  Lagrange's  View,  and  the  pres- 
ent attitude  of  physics  to  theology  was  thus  substan- 
tially determined. 

6.  The  idea  that  theology  and  physics  are  two  dis-  The  mod- 
tinct  branches  of  knowledge,  thus  took,  from  its  first  aiwayj  «*»« 
germination  in  Copernicus  till  its. final  proniulgation !*»««.'«**«« 
by  Lagrange,  almost  two  centuries  to  attain  clearness 
in  the  minds  of  investigators.  At  the  same  time  it 
cannot  be  denied  that  this  truth  was  always  clear  to 
the  greatest  minds,  like  Newton.  Newton  never,  de- 
spite his  profound  religiosity,  mingled  theology  with 
the  questions  of  science.  True,  even  he  concludes  his 
Optics,  whilst  on  its  last  pages  his  clear  and  luminous 
intellect  still  shines,  with  an  exclamation  of  humble 
contrition  at  the  vanity  of  all  earthly  things.  But  his 
optical  researches  proper,  in  contrast  to  those  of  Leib- 
nitz, contain  not  a  trace  of  theology.  The  same  may 
be  said  of  Galileo  and  Huygens.  Their  writings  con- 
form almost  absolutely  to  the  point  of  view  of  La- 
grange, and  may  be  accepted  in  this  respect  as  class- 
ical.    But  the  general  views  and  tendencies  of  an  age 


458  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

must  not  be  judged  by  its  greatest,  but  by  its  average, 
minds. 
The  theo-  To  Comprehend  the  process  here  portrayed,  the  gen- 

lOf^lCSl  COQ- 

ceptionof  eral  condition  of  affairs  in  these  times  must  be  consid* 

the  world 

natural  and  ered.    It  stauds  to  reasou  that  in  a  stage  of  civilisation 
able.  in  which  religion  is  almost  the  sole  education,  and  the 

only  theory  of  the  world,  people  would  naturally  look 
at  things  in  a  theological  point  of  view,  and  that  they 
would  believe  that  this  view  was  possessed  of  compe- 
tency in  all  fields  of  research.  If  we  transport  ourselves 
back  to  the  time  when  people  played  the  organ  with 
their  fists,  when  they  had  to  have  the  multiplication  table 
visibly  before  them  to  calculate,  when  they  did  so  much 
with  their  hands  that  people  now-a-days  do  with  their 
heads,  we  shall  not  demand  of  such  a  time  that  it 
should  critically  put  to  the  test  its  own  views  and  the- 
ories. With  the  widening  of  the  intellectual  horizon 
through  the  great  geographical,  technical,  and  scien- 
tific discoveries  and  inventions  of  the  fifteenth  and  six- 
teenth centuries,  with  the  opening  up  of  provinces  in 
which  it  was  impossible  to  make  any  progress  with  the 
old  conception  of  things,  simply  because  it  had  been 
formed  prior  to  the  knowledge  of  these  provinces,  this 
bias  of  the  mind  gradually  and  slowly  vanished.  The 
great  freedom  of  thought  which  appears  in  isolated 
cases  in  the  early  middle  ages,  first  in  poets  and  then 
in  scientists,  will  always  be  hard  to  understand.  The  en- 
lightenment of  those  days  must  have  been  the  work  of  a 
few  very  extraordinary  minds,  and  can  have  been  bound 
to  the  views  of  the  people  at  large  by  but  very  slender 
threads,  more  fitted  to  disturb  those  views  than  to  re- 
form them.  Rationalism  does  not  seem  to  have  gained 
a  broad  theatre  of  action  till  the  literature  of  the  eigh- 
teenth century.    Humanistic,  philosophical,  historical, 


FORMAL  DEVELOPMENT.  459 

and  physical  science  here  met  and  gave  each  other 
mutual  encouragement.  All  who  have  experienced,  in 
part,  in  its  literature,  this  wonderful  emancipation  of 
the  human  intellect,  will  feel  during  their  whole  lives  a 
deep,  elegiacal  regret  for  the  eighteenth  century. 

7.  The  old  point  of  view,  then,  is  abandoned.  Its  The  en- 
history  is  now  detectible  only  in  the  form  of  the  me-  mem  of  the 
chanical  principles.  And  this  form  will  remain  strange 
to  us  as  long  as  we  neglect  its  origin.  The  theological 
conception  of  things  gradually  gave  way  to  a  more 
rigid  conception  ;  and  this  was  accompanied  with  a 
considerable  gain  in  enlightenment,  as  we  shall  now 
briefly  indicate. 

When  we  say  light  travels  by  the  paths  of  shortest 
time,  we  grasp  by  such  an  expression  many  things. 
But  we  do  not  know  as  yet  why  light  prefers  paths  of 
shortest  time.  We  forego  all  further  knowledge  of  the 
phenomenon,  if  we  find  the  reason  in  the  Creator's  wis- 
dom. We  of  to-day  know,  that  light  travels  by  all 
paths,  but  that  only  on  the  paths  of  shortest  time  do 
the  waves  of  light  so  intensify  each  other  that  a  per- 
ceptible result  is  produced.  Light,  accordingly,  only 
appears  to  travel  by  the  paths  of  shortest  time.  After  Extrava- 
the  prejudice  which  prevailed  on  these  questions  had  weii  as 

•  J-    ^    1       J-  J    •     economy  in 

been  removed,  cases  were  immediately  discovered  in  nature, 
which  by  the  side  of  the  supposed  economy  of  nature 
the  most  striking  extravagance  was  displayed.  Cases 
of  this  kind  have,  for  example,  been  pointed  out  by 
Jacobi  in  connection  with  Euler's  principle  of  least  ac- 
tion. A  great  many  natural  phenomena  accordingly 
produce  the  impression  of  economy,  simply  because 
they  visibly  appear  only  when  by  accident  an  econom- 
ical accumulation  of  effects  take  place.  This  is  the 
same  idea  in  the  province  of  inorganic  nature  that  Dar- 


46o  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

win  worked  out  in  the  domain  of  organic  nature.      We 
facilitate  instinctively  our  comprehension  of  nature  by 
applying  to  it  the  economical  ideas  with  which  we  are 
familiar. 
Expiana-  Often  the  phenomena  of  nature  exhibit  maximal 

tionofmax-  ...  .         ,  ,  , 

imai  and  or  mmimal  properties  because  when  these  greatest  or 
effects.  least  properties  have  been  established  the  causes  of  all 
further  alteration  are  removed.  The  catenary  gives 
the  lowest  point  of  the  centre  of  gravity  for  the  simple 
reason  that  when  that  point  has  been  reached  all  fur- 
ther descent  of  the  system's  parts  is  impossible.  Li- 
quids exclusively  subjected  to  the  action  of  molecular 
forces  exhibit  a  minimum  of  superficial  area,  because 
stable  equilibrium  can  only  subsist  when  the  molecular 
forces  are  able  to  effect  no  further  diminution  of  super- 
ficial area.  The  important  thing,  therefctre,  is  not  the 
maximum  or  minimum,  but  the  removal  of  work  ;  work 
being  the  factor  determinative  of  the  alteration.  It 
sounds  much  less  imposing  but  is  much  more  elucida- 
tory, much  more  correct  and  comprehensive,  instead 
of  speaking  of  the  economical  tendencies  of  nature,  to 
say  :  "So  much  and  so  much  only  occurs  as  in  virtue 
of  the  forces  and  circumstances  involved  can  occur." 
Points  of  The  question  may  now  justly  be  asked,  If  the  point 

the  theoiog- of  view  of  thcology  which  led  to  the  enunciation  of  the 
scientific  principles  of  mechanics  was  utterly  wrong,  how  comes 
tions.  it  that  the  principles  themselves  are  in  all  substantial 
points  correct  ?  The  answer  is  easy.  In  the  first  place, 
the  theological  view  did  not  supply  the  contents  of  the 
principles,  but  simply  determined  their  guise\  their  mat- 
ter was  derived  from  experience.  A  similar  influence 
would  have  been  exercised  by  any  other  dominant  type 
of  thought,  by  a  commercial  attitude,  for  instance,  such 
as  presumably  had  its  effect  on  Stevinus's  thinking.   In 


FORMAL  DEVELOPMENT.  461 

the  second  place,  the  theological  conception  of  nature 
itself  owes  its  origin  to  an  endeavor  to  obtain  a  more 
comprehensive  view  of  the  world  ; — the  very  same  en- 
deavor that  is  at  the  bottom  of  physical  science.  Hence, 
even  admitting  that  the  physical  philosophy  of  theology 
is  a  fruitless  achievement,  a  reversion  to  a  lower  state  of 
scientific  culture,  we  still  need  not  repudiate  the  sound 
root  from  which  it  has  sprung  and  which  is  not  differ- 
ent from  that  of  true  physical  inquiry. 

In  fact,  science  can  accomplish  nothing  by  the  con-  Necessity 

of  a  con- 
sideration of  individual  facts ;  from  time  to  time  it  must  stant  con- 

cast  Its  glance  at  the   world  as  a   whole,     Galileo  s  of  the  ah, 

.  .  in  research 

laws  of  falling  bodies,  Huygens's  principle  of  vis  viva, 
the  principle  of  virtual  velocities,  nay,  even  the  con- 
cept of  mass,  could  not,  as  we  saw,  be  obtained,  ex- 
cept by  the  alternate  consideration  of  individual  facts 
and  of  nature  as  a  totality.  We  may,  in  our  men- 
tal reconstruction  of  mechanical  processes,  start  from 
the  properties  of  isolated  masses  (from  the  elementary 
or  differential  laws),  and  so  compose  our  pictures  of 
the  processes  ;  or,  we  may  hold  fast  to  the  properties 
of  the  system  as  a  whole  (abide  by  the  integral  laws). 
Since,  however,  the  properties  of  one  mass  always  in- 
clude relations  to  other  masses,  (for  instance,  in  ve- 
locity and  acceleration  a  relation  of  time  is  involved, 
that  is,  a  connection  with  the  whole  world,)  it  is  mani- 
fest that  purely  differential,  or  elementary,  laws  do  not 
exist.  It  would  be  illogical,  accordingly,  to  exclude 
as  less  certain  this  necessary  view  of  the  All,  or  of  the 
more  general  properties  of  nature,  from  our  studies. 
The  more  general  a  new  principle  is  and  the  wider  its 
scope,  the  more  perfect  tests  will,  in  view  of  the  possi- 
bility of  error,  be  demanded  of  it. 

The  conception  of  a  will  and  intelligence  active  in 


462  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

Pasan  ideas  nature  IS  by  no  means  the  exclusive  property  of  Chris- 
tices  rife  in  tian  monotheism.   On  the  contrary,  this  idea  is  a  quite 

the  modem  ,         ...  .  i    r      •    i  •  -n* 

world.  lamihar  one  to  paganism  and  fetishism.  Paganism, 
however,  finds  this  will  and  intelligence  entirely  in  in- 
dividual phenomena,  while  monotheism  seeks  it  in  the 
All.  Moreover,  a  pure  monotheism  does  not  exist. 
The  Jewish  monotheism  of  the  Bible  is  by  no  means 
free  from  belief  in  demons,  sorcerers,  and  witches  ; 
and  the  Christian  monotheism  of  mediaeval  times  is 
even  richer  in  these  pagan  conceptions.  We  shall  not 
speak  of  the  brutal  amusement  in  which  church  and 
state  indulged  in  the  torture  and  burning  of  witches, 
and  which  was  undoubtedly  provoked,  in  the  majority 
of  cases,  not  by  avarice  but  by  the  prevalence  of  the 
ideas  mentioned.  In  his  instructive  work  on  Primitive 
Culture  Tylor  has  studied  the  sorcery,  superstitions, 
and  miracle- belief  of  savage  peoples,  and  compared 
them  with  the  opinions  current  in  mediaeval  times  con- 
cerning witchcraft.  The  similarity  is  indeed  striking. 
The  burning  of  witches,  which  was  so  frequent  in 
Europe  in  the  sixteenth  and  seventeenth  centuries,  is 
to-day  vigorously  conducted  in  Central  Africa.  Even 
now  and  in  civilised  countries  and  among  cultivated 
people  traces  of  these  conditions,  as  Tylor  shows,  still 
exist  in  a  multitude  of  usages,  the  sense  of  which,  with 
our  altered  point  of  view,  has  been  forever  lost. 

8.  Physical  science  rid  itself  only  very  slowly  of 
these  conceptions.  The  celebrated  work  of  Giambatista 
della  Porta,  Magia  naturalis^  which  appeared  in  1558, 
though  it  announces  important  physical  discoveries,  is 
yet  filled  with  stuff  about  magic  practices  and  demono- 
logical  arts  of  all  kinds  little  better  than  those  of  a  red- 
skin medicine-man.  Not  till  the  appearance  of  Gil- 
bert's work.  De  magnete  (in  r6oo),  was  any  kind  of  re- 


FORMAL  DEVELOPMENT,  463 

striction.  placed  on  this  tendency  of  thought.    When  we  Animistic 

_  .  .  notions  in 

reflect  that  even  Luther  is  said  to  have  had  personal  science, 
encounters  with  the  Devil,  that  Kepler,  whose  aunt  had 
been  burned  as  a  witch  and  whose  mother  came  near 
meeting  the  same  fate,  said  that  witchcraft  could  not 
be  denied,  and  dreaded  to  express  his  real  opinion  of 
astrology,  we  can  vividly  picture  tp  ourselves  the 
thought  of  less  enlightened  minds  of  those  ages. 

Modern  physical  science  also  shows  traces  of  fetish- 
ism, as  Tylor  >vell  remarks,  in  its  "forces."  And  the 
hobgoblin  practices  of  modern  spiritualism  are  ample 
evidence  that  the  conceptions  of  paganism  have  not 
been  overcome  even  by  the  cultured  society  of  to-day. 

It  is  natural  that  these  ideas  so  obstinately  assert 
themselves.  Of  the  many  impulses  that  rule  man 
with  demoniacal  power,  that  nourish,  preserve,  and 
propagate  him,  without  his  knowledge  or  supervision, 
of  these  impulses  of  which  the  middle  ages  present 
such  great  pathological  excesses,  only  the  smallest 
part  is  accessible  to  scientific  analysis  and  conceptual 
knowledge.  The  fundamental  character  of  all  these 
instincts  is  the  feeling  of  our  oneness  and  sameness 
with  nature ;  a  feeling  that  at  times  can  be  silenced 
but  never  eradicated  by  absorbing  intellectual  occupa- 
tions, and  which  certainly  has  a  sound  basis,  no  matter 
to  what  religious  absurdities  it  may  have  given  rise. 

9.  The  French  encyclopaedists  of  the  eighteenth 
century  imagined  they  were  not  far  from  a  final  ex- 
planation of  the  world  by  physical  and  mechanical  prin- 
ciples ;  Laplace  even  conceived  a  mind  competent  to 
foretell  the  progress  of  nature  for  all  eternity,  if  but  the 
masses,  their  positions,  and  initial  velocities  were  given. 
In  the  eighteenth  century,  this  joyful  overestimation  of 
the  scope  of  the  new  physico-mechanical  ideas  is  par- 


464 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 


Overcsti- 
mation  of 
the  me- 
chanical 
view. 


Pretensions 
and  atti- 
tude of 
physical 
science. 


donabie.  Indeed,  it  is  a  refreshing,  noble,  and  ele- 
vating spectacle  ;  and  we  can  deeply  sympathise  with 
this  expression  of  intellectual  joy,  so  unique  in  history. 
But  now,  after  a  century  has  elapsed,  after  our  judg- 
ment has  grown  more  sober,  the  world-conception  of  the 
encyclopaedists  appears  to  us  as  a  viechanical  mythology 
in  contrast  to  the  animistic  of  the  old  religions.  Both 
views  contain  undue  and  fantastical  exaggerations  of 
an  incomplete  perception.  Careful  physical  research 
will  lead,  however,  to  an  analysis  of  our  sensations. 
We  shall  then  discover  that  our  hunger  is  not  so  essen- 
tially different  from  the  tendency  of  sulphuric  acid  for 
zinc,  and  our  will  not  so  greatly  different  from  the 
pressure  of  a  stone,  as  now  appears.  We  shall  again 
feel  ourselves  nearer  nature,  without  its  being  neces- 
sary that  we  should  resolve  ourselves  into  a  nebulous 
and  mystical  mass  of  molecules,  or  make  nature  a 
haunt  of  hobgoblins.  The  direction  in  which  this  en- 
lightenment is  to  be  looked  for,  as  the  result  of  long 
and  painstaking  research,  can  of  course  only  be  sur- 
mised. To  anticipate  the  result,  or  even  to  attempt  to 
introduce  it  into  any  scientific  investigation  of  to-day, 
would  be  mythology,  not  science. 

Physical  science  does  not  pretend  to  be  a  complete 
view  of  the  world ;  it  simply  claims  that  it  is  working 
toward  such  a  complete  view  in  the  future.  The  high- 
est ^ilosophy  of  the  scientific  investigator  is  precisely 
this  toleration  of  an  incomplete  conception  of  the  world 
and  the  preference  for  it  rather  than  an  apparently  per- 
fect, but  inadequate  conception.  Our  religious  opin- 
ions are  always  our  own  private  affair,  as  long  as  we  do 
not  obtrude  them  upon  others  and  do  not  apply  them 
to  things  which  come  under  the  jurisdiction  of  a  differ- 
ent tribunal.     Physical  inquirers  themselves  entertain 


FORMAL  DEVELOPMENT.  465 

the  most  diverse  opinions  on  this  subject,  according  to 
the  range  of  their  intellects  and  their  estimation  of  the 
consequences. 

Physical  science  makes  no  investigation  at  all  into 
things  that  are  absolutely  inaccessible  to  exact  investi- 
gation, or  as  yet  inaccessible  to  it.  But  should  prov- 
inces ever  be  thrown  open  to  exact  research  which  are 
now  closed  to  it,  no  well-organised  man,  no  one  who 
cherishes  honest  intentions  towards  himself  and  others, 
will  any  longer  then  hesitate  to  countenance  inquiry 
with  a  view  to  exchanging  his  opinion  regarding  such 
provinces  for  positive  knowledge  of  them. 

When,  to-day,  we  see  society  waver,  see  it  change  Results  of 

.  .  .  ^.  ,.  .  .  theinconi- 

its  Views  on  the  same  question  according  to  its  mood  and  pietenessof 

OQr  view  of 

the  events  of  the  week,  like  the  register  of  an  organ,  when  the  world. 
we  behold  the  profound  mental  anguish  which  is  thus 
produced,  we  should  know  that  this  is  the  natural  and 
necessary  outcome  of  the  incompleteness  and  transi- 
tional character  of  our  philosophy.  A  competent  view 
of  the  world  can  never  be  got  as  a  gift ;  we  must  ac- 
quire it  by  hard  work.  And  only  by  granting  free  sway 
to  reason  and  experience  in  the  provinces  in  which  they 
alone  are  determinative,  shall  we,  to  the  weal  of  man- 
kind, approach,  slowly,  gradually,  but  surely,  to  that 
ideal  of  a  monistic  view  of  the  world  which  is  alone 
compatible  with  the  economy  of  a  sound  mind. 

III. 

ANALYTICAL    MECHANICS. 

I.    The  mechanics  of  Newton  are  purely  geometrical.  The  peo- 

mctncsil 

He  deduces  his  theorems  from  his  initial  assumptions  mechanics 

,      .  -  .       -  .  __.    of  Newton. 

entirely  by  means  of  geometrical  constructions.  His 
procedure  is  frequently  so  artificial  that,  as  Laplace 


466 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 


Analytic 
mechanics. 


Euler  and 
Maclau- 
rin's  con- 
tributions. 


Lagrange's 
perfection 
of  the 
science. 


remarked,  it  is  unlikely  that  the  propositions  were  dis- 
covered in  that  way.  We  notice,  moreover,  that  the 
expositions  of  Newton  are  not  as  candid  as  those  of 
Galileo  and  Huygens.  Newton's  is  the  so-called  syn- 
thetic method  of  the  ancient  geometers. 

When  we  deduce  results  from  given  suppositions, 
the  procedure  is  called  synthetic.  When  we  seek  the 
conditions  of  a  proposition  or  of  the  properties  of  a  fig- 
ure, the  procedure  is  analytic.  The  practice  of  the  latter 
method  became  usual  largely  in  consequence  of  the 
application  of  algebra  to  geometry.  It  has  become 
customary,  therefore,  to  call  the  algebraical  method 
generally,  the  analytical.  The  term  ''analytical  me- 
chanics," which  is  contrasted  with  the  synthetical,  or 
geometrical,  mechanics  of  Newton,  is  the  exact  equiva- 
lent of  the  phrase  "algebraical  mechanics." 

2.  The  foundations  of  analytical  mechanics  were 
laid  by  Euler  {Mechanica,  sive  Motus  Scientia  Analytice 
Exposita,  St.  Petersburg,  1736).  But  while  Euler's 
method,  in  its  resolution  of  curvilinear  forces  into  tan- 
gential and  normal  components,  still  bears  a  trace  of 
the  old  geometrical  modes,  the  procedure  of  Maclaurin 
{A  Complete  System  of  Fluxions  ^  Edinburgh,  1742)  marks 
a  very  important  advance.  This  author  resolves  all 
forces  in  three  fixed  directions,  and  thus  invests  the 
computations  of  this  subject  with  a  high  degree  of 
symmetry  and  perspicuity. 

3.  Analytical  mechanics,  however,  was  brought  to 
its  highest  degree  of  perfection  by  Lagrange.  La- 
grange's aim  is  {Mecanique  analytique^  Paris,  1788)  to 
dispose  once  for  all  oi  the  reasoning  necessary  to  resolve 
mechanical  problems,  by  embodying  as  much  as  pos- 
sible of  it  in  a  single  formula.  This  he  did.  Every  case 
that  presents  itself  can  now  be  dealt  with  by  a  very 


FORMAL  DEVELOPMENT,  467 

simple,  highly  symmetrical  and  perspicuous  schema ; 
and  whatever  reasoning  is  left  is  performed  by  purely 
mechanical  methods.  The  mechanics  of  Lagrange 
is  a  stupendous  contribution  to  the  economy  of 
thought. 

In  statics,  Lagrange  starts  from  the  principle  ofstaUcs 

....  ,^  ,  ,  ...         founded  on 

Virtual  velocities.     On  a  number  of  material  points  the  princi- 
ples of  vir- 

Wj,  Wg,  ///g.  .  .  .,  definitely  connected  with  one  another,  tuai  veioci- 
are  impressed  the  forces  P^,  P^y  P^,  .  ,  ,  If  these 
points  receive  any  infinitely  small  displacements /j, 
/2>  /s  •  •  •  •  compatible  with  the  connections  of  the  sys- 
tem, then  for  equilibrium  JSPp  =  0  ;  where  the  well- 
known  exception  in  which  the  equality  passes  into  an 
inequality  is  left  out  of  account. 

Now  refer  the  whole  system  to  a  set  of  rectangular 
codrdinates.  Let  the  coordinates  of  the  material  points 
be  jCj,  ^j,  2j,  jTg,  ^2>  ^2  •  •  •  •  Resolve  the  forces  into 
the  components  X^,  V^,  Z^,  X^,  V^,  Z^,  .  .  .  parallel 
to  the  axes  of  coordinates,  and  the  displacements  into 
the  displacements  dx^^,  dy^y  dz^,  6x2,  dy^s  ^^2'  •  •  •> 
also  parallel  to  the  axes.  In  the  determination  of  the 
work  done  only  the  displacements  of  the  point  of  appli- 
cation in  the  direction  of  each  force-component  need 
be  considered  for  that  component,  and  the  expression 
of  the  principle  accordingly  is 

2(XSx+  V6y  +  Zdz)  =  0 (1) 

where  the  appropriate  indices  are  to  be  inserted  for 
the  points,  and  the  final  expressions  summed. 

The  fundamental  formula  of  dynamics  is  derived  Dynamics 

on  the  prin- 

from  D'Alembert's  principle.     On  the  material  points  cipie  of 

D'Aleni' 

m^,  m^,  W3  .  .  .  .,  having  the  codrdinates  x^^  y^,  z^,  x^,  bert. 
^2,  2^2  ...  .  the  force-components  AT^,  K^,  Z^,  A'g,  1^2, 
Zj .  .  .  .  act.     But,  owing  to  the  connections  of  the 


468  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

system's  parts,  the  masses  undergo  accelerations,  which 
are  those  of  the  forces. 

d^x^  d^y^  d^z^ 

These  are  called  the  effective  forces.  But  the  impressed 
forces,  that  is,  the  forces  which  exist  by  virtue  of  the 
laws  of  physics,  X,  Y,  Z.  ,  ,  .  and  the  negative  of  these 
effective  forces  are,  owing  to  the  connections  of  the 
system,  in  equilibrium.  Applying,  accordingly,  the 
principle  of  virtual  velocities,  we  get 

Discussion        4.  Thus,  Lagrange  conforms  to  tradition  in  making 

of  La- 

grange's  statics  precede  dynamics.  He  was  by  no  means  com- 
pelled to  do  so.  On  the  contrary,  he  might,  with  equal 
propriety,  have  started  from  the  proposition  that  the 
connections,  neglecting  their  straining,  perform  no 
work,  or  that  all  the  possible  work  of  the  system  is  due 
to  the  impressed  forces.  In  the  latter  case  he  would 
have  begun  with  equation  (2),  which  expresses  this 
fact,  and  which,  for  equilibrium  (or  non-accelerated 
motion)  reduces  itself  to  (i)  as  a  particular  case.  This 
would  have  made  analytical  mechanics,  as  a  system, 
even  more  logical. 

Equation  (i),  which  for  the  case  of  equilibrium 
makes  the  element  of  the  work  corresponding  to  the 
assumed  displacement  =  0,  gives  readily  the  results 
discussed  in  page  69.     If 

dV  dV  dV 

^~  dx'  dy'  dz' 


FORMAL  DEVELOPMENT,  469 

that  is  to  say,  if  X,  F,  Z  are  the  partial  differential  co- 
efficients of  one  and  the  same  function  of  the  coordi- 
nates of  position,  the  whole  expression  under  the  sign 
of  summation  is  the  total  variation,  d  V,  of  F,  If  the 
latter  is  =  0,  Kis  in  general  a  maximum  or  a  minimum. 

5.  We  will  now  illustrate  the  use  of  equation  (i)  by  indication 

.  .  .         .  ofthegen- 

a  simple  example.   If  all  the  points  of  application  of  the  erai  steps 

.1  r  1  1  •    'orthesolu- 

forces  are  mdependent  of  each  other,  no  problem  is  tion  of  stat- 

.  .  .  ...  *cal  prob- 

presented.  Each  point  is  then  in  equilibrium  onlyiems. 
when  the  forces  impressed  on  it,  and  consequently 
their  components,  are  ==  0.  All  the  displacements  dx, 
6}'y  Sz,  .  ,  ,  are  then  wholly  arbitrary,  and  equation 
(i)  can  subsist  only  provided  the  coefficients  of  all  the 
displacements  dx,  6y,  6z,  ,  .  .  are  equal  to  zero. 

But  if  equations  obtain  between  the  coordinates  of 
the  several  points,  that  is  to  say,  if  the  points  are  sub- 
ject to  mutual  constraints,  the  equations  so  obtaining 
will  be  of  the  form  F(x^y  y^y  z^,  x^,  y^,  z^.  .  .  .)  =  0, 
or,  more  briefly,  of  the  form  jF=0,  Then  equations 
also  obtain  between  the  displacements,  of  the  form 

^^;  ^^^  +  <^  ^-^'^  +  ^  ^^^  +  ^:c/^« +  ••••  =  ^' 

which  we  shall  briefly  designate  asZ>/^=0.  If  the 
system  consist  of  n  points,  we  shall  have  3  n  coordi- 
nates, and  equation  (i)  will  contain  ^n  magnitudes 
dxy  Sy,  dz,  ,  .  ,  If,  further,  between  the  coordinates 
fn  equations  of  the  form  jF=0  subsist,  then  m  equa- 
tions of  the  form  DF=  0  will  be  simultaneously  given 
between  the  variations  Sx,  6y,  6z .  ,  ,  .  By  these 
equations  m  variations  can  be  expressed  in  terms  of  the 
remainder,  and  so  inserted  in  equation  (i).  In  (i), 
therefore,  there  are  left  3«  —  m  arbitrary  displace- 
ments, whose  coefficients  are  put  =  0.    There  are  thus 


470 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 


A  statical 
example. 


obtained  between  the  forces  and  the  co6rdinates  3  » — m 
equations,  to  which  the  m  equations  (-^=  0)  must  be 
added.  We  have,  accordingly,  in  all,  3«  equations, 
which  are  sufficient  to  determine  the.  3;!  coordinates  of 
the  position  of  equilibrium,  provided  the  forces  are 
given  and  only  they^rw  of  the  system's  equilibrium  is 
sought. 

But  if  the  form  of  the  system  is  given  and  the  forces 
are  sought  that  maintain  equilibrium,  the  question  is 
indeterminate.  We  have  then,  to  determine  3  n  force- 
components,  only  3»  —  m  equa- 
tions ;  the  m  equations  (J^  =  0) 
not  containing  the  force-compo- 
nents. 

As  an  example  of  this  man- 
ner of  treatment  we  shall  select 
a  lever  OM^za^  free  to  rotate 
about  the  origin  of  co6rdinates 
in  the  plane  XYy  and  having  at  its  end  a  second,  simi- 
lar lever  MN^=^b,  At  M  and  Ny  the  coordinates  of 
which  we  shall  call  x^  y  and  x^^  y\y  the  forces  X^  Kand 
X^y  Fj  are  applied.     Equation  (i),  then,  has  the  form 

X6x^X^6x^  +  Ydy^  Y^dy^=^   •  •   •   (3) 

Of  the  form  I*'=0  two  equations  here  exist ;  namely, 

^x,-xy  +  (y^-yy- fi2^o  f    ^  ^ 

The  equations  I>F=  0,  accordingly,  are 

xSx  -\-  ySy  =  0  J 

(^1  —  X)  6x^  —  {x^  —  x)dx-\r  d  —y^  ^y^—Y  •  (5) 

{y^  —y)  ^y  =  ^  ) 

Here,  two  of  the  variations  in  (5)  can  be  expressed 
in  terms  of  the  others  and  introduced  in  (3).    Also  for 


Pig.  232. 


FORMAL  DEVELOPMENT.  471 

purposes  of  elimination  Lagrange  employed  a  per- Lagrangc/a 
fectly  uniform  and  systematic  procedure,  which  maynatecocffi- 
be  pursued  quite  mechanically,  without  reflection.  We 
shall  use  it  here.   It  consists  in  multiplying  each  of  .the 
equations  (5)  by  an  indeterminate  coefficient  A,  /i,  and 
adding  each  in  this  form  to  (3).     So  doing,  we  obtain 

\Y^\y-lx^^-y)-\dy  ^ly,-^  pi^y  -y)-\dy,  f-"* 

The  coefficients  of  the  four  displacements  may  now 
be  put  (Jirectly  =  0.  For  two  displacements  are  ar- 
bitrary, and  the  two  remaining  coefficients  may  be 
made  equal  to  zero  by  the  appropriate  choice  of  A  and 
}x — which  is  tantamount  to  an  elimination  of  the  two 
remaining  displacements. 

We  have,  therefore,  the  four  equations 

X -\-  \x  —  A'G'^'i  —  jf)  =  0 

-^1  +)"(^i  —  •^)  =  ^ 
Y\\y-pL^y^-y')  =  ^ 

We  shall  first  assume  that  the  coordinates  are  given, 
and  seek  the  forces  that  maintain  equilibrium.  The 
values  of  \  and  pi  are  each  determined  by  equating  to 
zero  two  coefficients.  We  get  from  the  second  and 
fourth  equations, 

p,  = i-,  and  /i  = ^  , 

x,—x  y^—y 

whence 

y,~y,-y ^  ^ 

that  is  to  say,  the  total  component  force  impressed  at 
N  has  the  direction  MN.  From  the  first  and  third 
equations  we  get 


(6) 


47a  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

Their  en..         A  =  --^-i-^^tZlfl,     A  =  --^+-^-^-*''--::^, 
ployment  in  x  Y 

the  deter- 

{Jj.°J{j°j°  °' and  from  these  by  simple  reduction 

equation.  X+X,  X 

Y+y;=y ^^^ 

that  is  to  say,  the  resultant  of  the  forces  applied  at  Af 
and  N  acts  in  the  direction  OM,  * 

The  four  force-components  are  accordingly  subject 
to  only  two  conditions,  (7)  and  (8).  The  problem,  con- 
sequently, is  an  indeterminate  one  ;  as  it  must  be  from 
the  nature  of  the  case ;  for  equilibrium  does  not  depend 
upon  the  absolute  magnitudes  of  the  forces,  but  upon 
their  directions  and  relations. 

If  we  assume  that  the  forces  are  given  and  seek  the 
four  coordinates,  we  treat  equations  (6)  in  exactly  the 
same  manner.  Only,  we  can  now  make  use,  in  addi- 
tion, of  equations  (4).  Accordingly,  we  have,  upon  the 
elimination  of  X  and  fji,  equations  (7)  and  (8)  and  two 
equations  (4).  From  these  the  following,  which  fully 
solve  the  problem,  are  readily  deduced  • 


y  = 


V{X+X^)^-\-{Y^YJ 


*  The  mechanical  interpretation  of  the  indeterminate  coefficients  At  j^  may 
be  shown  as  follows.  Equations  (6)  express  the  equilibrium  of  Xvio/ree  points 
on  which  in  addition  to  X,  V,  X^,  V'^  other  forces  act  which  answer  to  the  re- 
maining expressions  and  just  destroy  A",  l',  Jfj,  K^.  The  point  N^  for  example, 
is  in  equilibrium  if  Xi  is  destroyed  by  a  force  fi  [x^ — x),  undetermined  as  yet 
in  magnitude,  and  V\  by  a  force  H  [y\  — y).  This  supplementary  force  is  due 
to  the  constraints.  Its  direction  is  determined  ;  though  its  magnitude  is  not. 
If  we  call  the  angle  which  it  makes  with  the  axis  of  abscissas  a,  we  shall  have 

tana  =  '';^''"^l^^>->'- 

that  is  to  say.  the  force  due  to  the  connections  acts  in  the  direction  of  i. 


FORMAL  DEVELOPMENT,  473 

X^  = ^ —    ^^ 1 ^ Character 

lein. 

Simple  as  this  example  is,  it  is  yet  sufficient  to  give 
us  a  distinct  idea  of  the  character  and  significance  of 
Lagrange's  method.  The  mechanism  of  this  method  is 
excogitated  once  for  all,  and  in  its  application  to  par- 
ticular cases  scarcely  any  additional  thinking  is  re- 
quired. The  simplicity  of  the  example  here  selected 
being  such  that  it  can  be  solved  by  a  mere  glance  at 
the  figure,  we  have,  in  our  study  of  the  method,  the 
advantage  of  a  ready  verification  at  every  step. 

6.  We  will  now  illustrate  the  application  of  equa-  General 
tion  (2),  which  is  Lagrange's  form  of  statement  of  theTsoiution 
D*Alembert*s  principle.     There  is  no  problem  whenfcai^ro™ 

IfilXlS 

the  masses  move  quite  independently  of  one  another. 
Each  mass  yields  to  the  forces  applied  to  it ;  the  va- 
riations dXf  dy,  dz .  ,  ,  ,  are  wholly  arbitrary,  and  each 
coefficient  may  be  singly  put  ==  0.  For  the  motion  of 
n  masses  we  thus  obtain  3  n  simul- 
taneous differential  equations. 

But  if  equations  of  condition 
(/^=  0)  obtain  between  the  coordi- 
nates, these  equations  will  lead  to 
others  {DF--^^)  between  the  dis- 
placements or  variations.  With  the 

.  F»R.  233- 

latter  we  proceed  exactly  as  in  the 
application  of  equation  (i).  Only  it  must  be  noted 
here  that  the  equations  1^=0  must  eventually  be  em- 
ployed in  their  undifferentiated  as  well  as  in  their  dif- 
ferentiated form,  as  will  best  be  seen  from  the  follow- 
ing example. 


474  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

A  dynam-  A  hcavy  material  point  «r,  lying  in  a  vertical  plane 

pie.  XY,  is  free  to  move  on  a  straight  line,  y  =i  axj  inclined 

at  an  angle  to  the  horizon.  (Fig.  233.)  Here  equa- 
tion (2)  becomes 

and,  since  A!'=  0,  and  Y=  —  mg^  also 

'J/l'^*  +  (^+S>^'=« (^) 

The  place  of  -^  =  0  is  taken  by 

y  =  ax (10) 

and  for  DF  ==  0  we  have 

dy  =  a6x. 

Equation  (9),  accordingly,  since  6y  drops  out  and 
djc  is  arbitrary,  passes  into  the  form 

^x        f  d^}\ 

By  the  differentiation  of  (10),  or  {F=  0),  we  have 

d^y  d^x  I 

and,  consequently, 

d'^x    .      (     .      d^x\ 

Then,  by  the  inte.gration  of  (11),  we  obtain 

—  a       /2 

and 

where  b  and  c  are  constants  Qf  integration,  determined 
by  the  initial  position  and  velbcity  of  m.  This  result 
can  also  be  easily  found  by  the  direct  method. 


FORMAL  DEVELOPMENT,  475 

Some  care  is  necessary  in  the  application  of  equa-  a  modifica- 

y     >.     •  r     »-i  f\  •  1  •  rrs'x  i  •       t*©"  of  this 

tion  (i)  \i  F'=i\S  contains  the  time.    The  procedure  m  example, 
such  cases  may  be  illustrated  by  the  following  example. 
Imagine  in  the  preceding  case  the  straight  line  on 
which  m  descends  to  move  vertically  upwards  with  the 
acceleration  y*     We  start  again  from  equation  (9) 

d'^x  ^      ,    /      .    d^y\  ^ 

/'=  0  is  here  replaced  by 

y  =  ax^Y%    •■■■'■ (12) 

To  form  DF=  0,  we  vary  (12)  only  with  respect  to  x 
and  y,  for  we  are  concerned  here  only  with  the  possible 
displacement  of  the  system  in  its  position  at  any  given 
instant^  and  not  with  the  displacement  that  actually 
takes  place  in  time.  We  put,  therefore,  as  in  the  pre- 
vious case, 

dy  =^  a  dx, 

and  obtain,  as  before, 

d^x       I     .   d^y\         ^  ,,„, 

But  to  get  an  equation  in  x  alone,  we  have,  since  x 
and  >>  are  connected  in  (13)  by  the  actual  motion,  to 
differentiate  (12)  with  respect  to  /  and  employ  the  re- 
sulting equation 

///2  ■"  ^  dt^~  "*"  ^ 
for  substitution  in  (13).     In  this  way  the  equation 

is  obtained,  which,  integrated,  gives 


476 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 


/2 


X 


y  = 


y— 


/a 


a- 


u  +  x) 


2 


-|-  <z^/  -j-  ac. 


If  a  weightless  body  w  lie  on  the  moving  straight 
line,  we  obtain  these  equations 

■^  =  rT^/2  +  ^^'  +  ^^' 

— results  which  are  readily  understood,  when  we  re- 
flect that,  on  a  straight  line  moving  upwards  with  the 
acceleration  ^,  m  behaves  as  if  it  were  affected  with  a 
downward  acceleration  y  on  the  straight  line  at  rest. 
Discussion         7-  The  procedure  with  equation  ( 1 2)  in  the  preced- 
ffied  exam-  ing  example  may  be  rendered  somewhat  clearer  by  the 
^®"  following  consideration.     Equation  (2),  D*Alembert's 

principle,    asserts,   that  all  the  work 
that  can  be  done  in  the  displacement 
of  a  system  is  done  by  the  impressed 
forces  and  not  by  the  connections.  This 
is  evident,  since  the  rigidity  of  the  con- 
nections allows  no  changes  in  the  rela- 
tive positions  which  would  be  neces- 
sary for  any  alteration  in  the  potentials  of  the  elastic 
forces.     But  this  ceases  to  be  true  when  the  connec- 
tions undergo  changes  in  time.   In  this  case,  the  changes 
of  the  connections  perform  work,  and  we  can  then  ap- 
ply equation  (2)  to  the  displacements  that  actually  take 
place  only  provided  we  add  to  the  impressed  forces  the 
forces  that  produce  the  changes  of  the  connections. 

A  heavy  mass  in  is  free  to  move  on  a  straight  line 
parallel  to  C?F(Fig.  234.)     Let  this  line  be  subject  to 


a 


1 


Fig.  *34- 


FORMAL  DEVELOPMENT.  477 

a  forced  acceleration  in  the  direction  of  x,  such  that  illustration 

of  the  mod- 

the  equation  jF=0  becomes  ifiedexam- 

^  pie. 

^  =  y-l> 0-^) 

D'Alembert*s  principle  again  gives  equation  (9). 
But,  since  from  Z>/^=  0  it  follows  here  that  dx  =  0, 
this  equation  reduces  itself  to 

^+S')*^=' ^''^ 

in  which  6y  is  wholly  arbitrary.     Wherefore, 

and 

to  which  must  be  supplied  (14)  or 

It  is  patent  that  (15)  does  not  assign  the  total  work 
of  the  displacement  that  actually  takes  place,  but  only 
that  of  some  possible  displacement  on  the  straight  line 
conceived,  for  the  moment,  as  fixed. 

If  we  imagine  the  straight  line  massless,  and  cause 
it  to  travel  parallel  to  itself  in  some  guiding  mechan- 
ism moved  by  a  force  niyy  equation  (2)  will  be  re- 
placed by 

my  —  m  ~^^^^  6x  +  [—  mg  —  m  -^^j^y  =  0, 

and  since  dx^  dy  are  wholly  arbitrary  here,  we  obtain 

the  two  equations 

inx       . 
V ^0 


478  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

which  give  the  same  results  as  before.  The  apparently 
different  mode  of  treatment  of  these  cases  is  simply  the 
result  of  a  slight  inconsistency,  springing  from  the  fact 
that  all  the  forces  involved  are,  for  reasons  facilitating 
calculation,  not  included  in  the  consideration  at  the 
outset,  but  a  portion  is  left  to  be  dealt  with  subse- 
quently. 
Deduction         8.  As  the  different  mechanical  principles  only  ex- 
cipie^o?"/*  press  different  aspects  of  the  same  fact,  any  one  of 
Lagrange's  them  is  easily  deducible  from  any  other  ;  as  we  shall 
tardynam-  HOW  illustrate  by  developing  the  principle  of  %ns  inva 
ica^equa-    £j.qj^  equation  (2)  of  page  468.     Equation  (2)  refers  to 
instantaneously  possible  displacements,  that  is,  to  "vir- 
tual "  displacements.     But  when  the  connections  of  a 
system  are  independent  of  the  time,  the  motions  that 
actually  take  place  2X^  "virtual"  displacements.  Conse- 
quently the  principle  may  be  applied  to  actual  motions. 
For  dxy  6y,  dz,  we  may,   accordingly,   write  dx,  dy, 
dzy  the  displacements  which  take  place  in  time,  and 
put 

^  iXdx  +  Ydy  +  Zdz^  = 

^     (d^x  .      ,d^y.     ,   d^z  . 
:2fn\^--.dx^rj,,dy^^^^dz 

'  The  expression  to  the  right  may,  by  introducing  for 
dx^  {dxjdf)  dt  and  so  forth,  and  by  denoting  the  velo- 
city by  ?;,  also  be  written 

^     Id'^  x  dx  .^   ,   d^y  dy  .     ,   d'^  z  dz    ,  \ 
\dt^   dt       ^  dt^   dt       ~  dt^   dt 


^d2m 


a      AM  2 


FORMAL  DEVELOPMENT.  479 

Also  in  the  expression  to  the  left,  {dxjdf)  dt  may  be  Force- 
written  for  dx.     But  this  gives 

J^  {Xdx  +  Ydy  +  Zdz)  =  2im  (r^  _  ^.2)^ 

where  Vq  denotes  the  velocity  at  the  beginning  and  7^ 
the  velocity  at  the  end  of  the  motion.  The  integral  to  the 
left  can  always  be  found  if  we  can  reduce  it  to  a  single 
variable,  that  is  to  say,  if  we  know  the  course  of  the 
motion  in  time  or  the  paths  which  the  movable  points 
describe.  If,  however,  X,  Y,  Z  are  the  partial  differ- 
ential coefficients  of  the  same  function  6^of  coordinates, 
if,  that  is  to  say, 

dU  dU  dU 

^^  dx'  77'  7F' 

as  is  always  the  case  when  only  central  forces  are  in- 
volved, this  reduction  is  unnecessary.  The  entire  ex- 
pression to  the  left  is  then  a  complete  differential.  And 
we  have 

which  is  to  say,  the  difference  of  the  force-functions 
(or  work)  at  the  beginning  and  the  end  of  the  motion 
is  equal  to  the  difference  of  the  vires  vivce  at  the  be- 
ginning and  the  end  of  the  motion.  The  vires  vivce  are 
in  such  case  also  functions  of  the  coordinates. 

In  the  case  of  a  body  movable  in  the  plane  of  X 
and  Ksuppose,  for  example,  X=^ — j,  K=  —  x\  we 
then  have 

r 

J^'—ydx  —  xdy)  =  —Jd^xy)  = 

^oyo  —  ^y=  \fn{y^  —  vX), 

But  if  A"  =  —  fl,  K=  —  jc,  the  integral  to  the  left  is 
—  Ha  dx  -{■  ^  ^y)'  This  integral  can  be  assigned  the 
moment  we  know  the  path  the  body  has  traversed,  that 


480 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 


Essential 
character 
of  analyt- 
ical me- 
chanics. 


is,  if  y  is  determined  a  function  of  x.     If,  for  example, 
y=px^y  the  integral  would  become 

-J {a  +  2px^)  dx  ^.  a  (.r,  —  x)  ^  ^/^  (^o^-_^)_^ 

The  difference  of  these  two  cases  is,  that  in  the  first 
the  work  is  simply  a  function  of  coordinates,  that  a 
force-function  exists,  that  the  element  of  the  work  is  a 
complete  differential,  and  the  work  consequently  is  dor 
termined  by  the  initial  and  final  values  of  the  coordi- 
nates, while  in  the  second  case  it  is  dependent  on  the 
entire  path  described. 

9.  These  simple  examples,  in  themselves  present- 
ing no  difficulties,  will  doubtless  suffice  to  illustrate  the 
general  nature  of  the  operations  of  analytical  mechan- 
ics. No  fundamental  light  can  be  expected  from  this 
branch  of  mechanics.  On  the  contrary,  the  discovery 
of  matters  of  principle  must  be  substantially  completed 
before  we  can  think  of  framing  analytical  mechanics  ; 
the  sole  aim  of  which  is  a  perfect  practical  mastery  of 
problems.  Whosoever  mistakes  this  situation,  will 
never  comprehend  Lagrange's  great  performance,  which 
here  too  is  essentially  of  an  economical  ch^x^iCter.  Poin- 
sot  did  not  altogether  escape  this  error. 

It  remains  to  be  mentioned  that  as  the  result  of  the 
labors  of  Mobius,  Hamilton,  Grassmann,  and  others,  a 
new  transformation  of  mechanics  is  preparing.  These 
inquirers  have  developed  mathematical  conceptions 
that  conform  more  exactly  and  directly  to  our  geomet- 
rical ideas  than  do  the  conceptions  of  common  analyt- 
ical geometry  ;  and  the  advantages  of  analytical  gene- 
rality and  direct  geometrical  insight  are  thus  united. 
But  this  transformation,  of  course,  lies,  as  yet,  beyond 
the  limits  of  an  historical  exposition. 


FORMAL  DEVELOPMENT,  481 


IV. 
THE  ECONOMY  OF  SCIENCE. 

I.   It  is  the  object  of  science  to  replace,  or  save^  ex-  The  basis 

,,  J.  ,  ..'.  ,  f  of  science, 

perienceSy  by  the  reproduction  and  anticipation  of  facts  economy  of 
in  thought.  Memory  is  handier  than  experience,  and 
often  answers  the  same  purpose.  This  economical 
office  of  science,  which  fills  its  whole  life,  is  apparent 
at  first  glance ;  and  with  its  full  recognition  all  mys- 
ticism in  science  disappears. 

Science  is  communicated  by  instruction,  in  order 
that  one  man  may  profit  by  the  experience  of  another 
and  be  spared  the  trouble  of  accumulating  it  for  him- 
self ;  and  thus,  to  spare  posterity,  the  experiences  of 
whole  generations  are  stored  up  in  libraries. 

Language,  the  instrument  of  this  communication,  The  eco- 

...tr  *i  ^*  T>  *  nomical 

IS  itself  an  economical  contrivance.  Experiences  are  character 
analysed,  or  broken  up,  into  simpler  and  more  familiar  ^agei 
experiences,  and  then  symbolised  at  some  sacrifice  of 
precision.  The  symbols  of  speech  are  as  yet  restricted 
in  their  use  within  national  boundaries,  and  doubtless 
will  long  remain  so.  But  written  language  is  gradually 
being  metamorphosed  into  an  ideal  universal  character. 
It  is  certainly  no  longer  a  mere  transcript  of  speech. 
Numerals,  algebraic  signs,  chemical  symbols,  musical 
notes,  phonetic  alphabets,  may  be  regarded  as  parts 
already  formed  of  this  universal  character  of  the  fu- 
ture ;  they  are,  to  some  extent,  decidedly  conceptual, 
and  of  almost  general  international  use.  The  analysis 
of  colors,  physical  and  physiological,  is  already  far 
enough  advanced  to  render  an  international  system  of 
color-signs  perfectly  practical.     In  Chinese  writing, 


482  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

Possibility  we  have  an  actual  example  of  a  true  ideographic  Ian- 

of  a  univer-  j    i  •  i      •        i  •  rr 

sal  Ian-  guage,  prouounced  diversely  m  different  provinces,  yet 
everywhere  carrying  the  same  meaning.  Were  the 
system  and  its  signs  only  of  a  simpler  character,  the 
use  of  Chinese  writing  might  become  universal.  The 
dropping  of  unmeaning  and  needless  accidents  of  gram- 
mar, as  English  mostly  drops  them,  would  be  quite 
requisite  to  the  adoption  of  such  a  system.  But  uni- 
versality would  not  be  the  sole  merit  of  such  a  char- 
acter ;  since  to  read  it  would  be  to  understand  it.  Our 
children  often  read  what  they  do  not  understand  ;  but 
that  which  a  Chinaman  cannot  understand,  he  is  pre- 
cluded from  reading. 
Econom-  2.    In  the  reproduction  of   facts  in   thought,    we 

tero*fa\"*^  never  reproduce  the  facts  in  full,  but  only  that  side  of 
senialfons   them  which  is  important  to  us,  moved  to  this  directly 
world.        or  indirectly  by  a  practical  interest.   Our  reproductions 
are  invariably  abstractions.    Here  again  is  an  econom- 
ical tendency. 

Nature  is  composed  of  sensations  as  its  elements. 
Primitive  man,  however,  first  picks  out  certain  com- 
pounds of  these  elements — those  namely  that  are  re- 
latively permanent  and  of  greater  importance  to  him. 
The  first  and  oldest  words  are  names  of  **  things." 
Even  here,  there  is  an  abstractive  process,  an  abstrac- 
tion from  the  surroundings  of  the  things,  and  from  the 
continual  small  changes  which  these  compound  sensa- 
tions undergo,  which  being  practically  unimportant  are 
not  noticed.  No  inalterable  thing  exists.  The  thing 
is  an  abstraction,  the  name  a  symbol,  for  a  compound 
of  elements  from  whose  changes  we  abstract.  The 
reasoR  we  assign  a  single  word  to  a  whole  compound  is 
that  we  need  to  suggest  all  the  constituent  sensations 
at  once.  When,  later,  we  come  to  remark  the  change- 


FORMAL  DEVELOPMENT.  483 

ableness,  we  cannot  at  the  same  time  hold  fast  to  the 
idea  of  the  thing's  permanence,  unless  we  have  recourse 
to  the  conception  of  a  thing-in-itself,  or  other  such  like 
absurdity.  Sensations  are  not  signs  of  things ;  but,  on 
the  contrary,  a  thing  is  a  thought-symbol  for  a  com- 
pound sensation  of  relative  fixedness.  Properly  speak- 
ing the  world  is  not  composed  of  ** things"  as  its  ele- 
ments, but  of  colors,  tones,  pressures,  spaces,  times, 
in  short  what  we  ordinarily  call  individual  sensations. 

The  whole  operation  is  a  mere  affair  of  economy. 
In  the  reproduction  of  facts,  we  begin  with  the  more 
durable  and  familiar  compounds,  and  supplement  these 
later  with  the  unusual  by  way  of  corrections.  Thus, 
we  speak  of  a  perforated  cylinder,  of  a  cube  with  bev- 
eled edges,  expressions  involving  contradictions,  un- 
less we  accept  the  view  here  taken.  All  judgments  are 
such  amplifications  and  corrections  of  ideas  already 
admitted. 

3.  In  speaking  of  cause  and  effect  we  arbitrarily  The  ideas 
give  relief  to  those  elements  to  whose  connection  we  effect, 
have  to  attend  in  the  reproduction  of  a  fact  in  the  re- 
spect in  which  it  is  important  to  us.  There  is  no  cause 
nor  effect  in  nature  ;  nature  has  but  an  individual  exis- 
tence ;  nature  simply  is.  Recurrences  of  like  cases  in 
which  A  is  always  connected  with  B^  that  is,  like  results 
under  like  circumstances,  that  is  again,  the  essence  of  the 
connection  of  cause  and  effect,  exist  but  in  the  abstrac- 
tion which  we  perform  for  the  purpose  of  mentally  re- 
producing the  facts.  Let  a  fact  become  familiar,  and 
we  no  longer  require  this  putting  into  relief  of  its  con- 
necting marks,  our  attention  is  no  longer  attracted  to 
the  new  and  surprising,  and  we  cease  to  speak  of  cause 
and  effect.  Heat  is  said  to  be  the  cause  of  the  tension 
of  steam ;  but  when  the  phenomenon  becomes  familiar 


484  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

we  think  of  the  steam  at  once  with  the  tension  proper 
to  its  temperature.     Acid  is  said  to  be  the  cause  of  the 
reddening  of  tincture  of  litmus  \  but  later  we  think  of 
the  reddening  as  a  property  of  the  acid. 
Hume,  Hume  first  propounded  the  question,  How  can  a 

Kanti  snd 

schopen-    thing  A  act  on  another  thing -^  ?    Hume,  in  fact,  re- 

haucr's  eX" 

pianations  jects  causalitv  and  recognises  only  a  wonted  succes- 

of  cause 

and  effect,  sion  in  time.  Kant  correctly  remarked  that  a  necessary 
connection  between  A  and  B  could  not  be  disclosed  by 
simple  observation.  He  assumes  an  innate  idea  or 
category  of  the  mind,  a  Verstandesbegriff^  under  which 
the  cases  of  experience  are  subsumed.  Schopenhauer, 
who  adopts  substantially  the  same  position,  distin- 
guishes four  forms  of  the  '*  principle  of  sufHcient  rea- 
son"— the  logical,  physical,  and  mathematical  form, 
and  the  law  of  motivation.  But  these  forms  differ  only 
as  regards  the  matter  to  which  they  are  applied,  which 
may  belong  either  to  outward  or  inward  experience. 
Cause  and  The  natural  and  common-sense  explanation  is  ap- 
economical  parcutly  this.  The  ideas  of  cause  and  effect  originally 
oTSio?ght.^  sprang  from  an  endeavor  to  reproduce  facts  in  thought. 
At  first,  the  connection  of  A  and  By  of  C  and  Z>,  of  E 
and  Fy  and  so  forth,  is  regarded  as  familiar.  But  after 
a  greater  range  of  experience  is  acquired  and  a  con- 
nection between  M  and  N  is  observed,  it  often  turns 
out  that  we  recognise  M  as  made  up  of  Ay  C,  Ey  and  N 
of  By  Dy  Fy  \\\^  counection  of  which  was  before  a  fa- 
miliar fact  and  accordingly  possesses  with  us  a  higher 
authority.  This  explains  why  a  person  of  experience 
regards  a  new  event  with  different  eyes  than  the  nov- 
ice. The  new  experience  is  illuminated  by  the  mass 
of  old  experience.  As  a  fact,  then,  there  really  does 
exist  in  the  mind  an  **idea'*  under  which  fresh  experi- 
ences are  subsumed  ;  but  that  idea  has  itself  been  de- 


FORMAL  DEVELOPMENT.  485 

veloped  from  experience.  The  notion  of  the  necessity 
of  the  causal  connection  is  probably  created  by  our 
voluntary  movements  in  the  world  and  by  the  changes 
which  these  indirectly  produce,  as  Hume  supposed  but 
Schopenhauer  contested.  Much  of  the  authority  of 
the  ideas  of  cause  and  effect  is  due  to  the  fact  that  they 
are  developed  instinctively  and  involuntarily,  and  that 
we  are  distinctly  sensible  of  having  personally  con- 
tributed nothing  to  their  formation.  We  may,  indeed, 
say,  that  our  sense  of  causality  is  not  acquired  by  the 
individual,  but  has  been  perfected  in  the  develop- 
ment of  the  race.  Cause  and  effect,  therefore,  are 
things  of  thought,  having  an  economical  office.  It  can- 
not be  said  why  they  arise.  For  it  is  precisely  by  the 
abstraction  of  uniformities  that  we  know  the  question 
"why."     (See  Appendix,  V.) 

4.   In  the  details  of  science,  its  economical  character  Econom- 

,  ,  ical  fea* 

is  still  more  apparent.     The  so-called  descriptive  sci-  tures  of 

.  .  all  laws  of 

ences  must  chiefly  remain  content  with  reconstructing  nature, 
individual  facts.  Where  it  is  possible,  the  common  fea- 
tures of  many  facts  are  once  for  all  placed  in  relief.  But 
in  sciences  that  are  more  highly  developed,  rules  for  the 
reconstruction  of  great  numbers  of  facts  may  be  embod- 
ied in  a  single  expression.  Thus,  instead  of  noting  indi- 
vidual cases  of  light- refraction,  we  can  mentally  recon- 
struct all  present  and  future  cases,  if  we  know  that  the 
incident  ray,  the  refracted  ray,  and  the  perpendicular 
lie  in  the  same  plane  and  that  sin  or/sin  y^=  «.  Here, 
instead  of  the  numberless  cases  of  refraction  in  different 
combinations  of  matter  and  under  all  different  angles 
of  incidence,  we  have  simply  to  note  the  rule  above 
stated  and  the  values  of  «, — which  is  much  easier.  The 
economical  purpose  is  here  unmistakable.  In  nature 
there  is  no  law  of  refraction,  only  different  cases  of  re- 


486  THE  SCIEXCE  OF  MECI/AXICS. 

fraction.  The  law  of  refraction  is  a  concise  compen- 
dious rule,  devised  by  us  for  the  mental  reconstruction 
of  a  fact,  and  only  for  its  reconstruction  in  part,  that 
is,  on  its  geometrical  side. 
The  econ-  5.  The  sciences  most  highly  developed  economically 
mathemat-  are  those  whose  facts  are  reducible  to  a  few  numerable 

*       ■        * 
ICSl  SCI" 

ences.  elements  of  like  nature.  Such  is  the  science  of  mechan- 
ics, in  which  we  deal  exclusively  with  spaces,  times, 
and  masses.  The  whole  previously  established  econ- 
omy of  mathematics  stands  these  sciences  in  stead. 
Mathematics  may  be  defined  as  the  economy  of  count- 
ing. Numbers  are  arrangement-signs  which,  for  the 
sake  of  perspicuity  and  economy,  are  themselves  ar- 
ranged in  a  simple  system.  Numerical  operations,  it 
is  found,  are  independent  of  the  kind  of  objects  operated 
on,  and  are  consequently  mastered  once  for  all.  When, 
for  the  first  time,  I  have  occasion  to  add  five  objects  to 
seven  others,  I  count  the  whole  collection  through,  at 
once ;  but  when  I  afterwards  discover  that  I  can  start 
counting  from  5,  I  save  myself  part  of  the  trouble ; 
and  still  later,  remembering  that  5  and  7  always  count 
up  to  12,  I  dispense  with  the  numeration  entirely. 
Arithmetic  The  objcct  of  all  arithmetical  operations  is  to  save 
andaiRc-  ^j^^^.^  numeration,  by  utilising  the  results  of  our  old 
operations  of  counting.  Our  endeavor  is,  having  done 
a  sum  once,  to  preserve  the  answer  for  future  use.  The 
first  four  rules  of  arithmetic  well  illustrate  this  view. 
Such,  too,  is  the  purpose  of  algebra,  which,  substitut- 
ing relations  for  values,  symbolises  and  definitively 
fixes  all  numerical  operations  that  follow  the  same  rule. 
For  example,  we  learn  from  the  equation 


FORMAL  DEVELOPMENT.  487 

that  the  more  complicated  numerical  operation  at  the 
left  may  always  be  replaced  by  the  simpler  one  at  the 
right,  whatever  numbers  x  and  y  stand  for.  We  thus 
save  ourselves  the  labor  of  performing  in  future  cases 
the  more  complicated  operation.  Mathematics  is  the 
method  of  replacing  in  the  most  comprehensive  and 
economical  manner  possible,  new  numerical  operations 
by  old  ones  done  already  with  known  results.  It  may 
happen  in  this  procedure  that  the  results  of  operations 
are  employed  which  were  originally  performed  centu- 
ries ago. 

Often   operations  involving  intense  mental  effort  The  theory 
may  be   replaced  by  the  action  of  semi-mechanical  minams. 
routine,  with  great  saving  of  time  and  avoidance  of 
fatigue.      For  example,   the   theory  of  determinants 
owes  its  origin  to  the  remark,  that  it  is  not  necessary 
to  solve  each  time  anew  equations  of  the  form 


from  which  result 


^1  •^  +  ^1  ^^4-  ^1 

—  0 

«2   •^+  ^2>'+^2 
if 

=  0, 

It 

_  ^1    ^2           ^2  ^X 
a,    ^2—^2^1 

P 

N 

a^    ^2          ^2  ^1 
^1^2           ^2^^! 

Q 

but  that  the  solution  may  be  effected  by  means  of  the 
coefficients,  by  writing  down  the  coefficients  according 
to  a  prescribed  scheme  and  operating  with  them  me- 
chanically.     Thus, 


a,b, 
^3  ^2 

—  «i  ^2  —  ^2  ^ 

and  similarly 

^1  ^1 
i^2  ^2! 

—  P,  and  ^^  ^' 
''2  ^2 

1 


=  N 


Q- 


488  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

Calculating       Even  a  ioial  disburdening  of  the  mind  can  be  ef- 

machines. 

fected  in  mathematical  operations.  This  happens  where 
operations  of  counting  hitherto  performed  are  symbol- 
ised by  mechanical  operations  with  signs,  and  our  brain 
energy,  instead  of  being  wasted  on  the  repetition  of 
old  operations,  is  spared  for  more  important  tasks. 
The  merchant  pursues  a  like  economy,  when,  instead 
of  directly  handling  his  bales  of  goods,  he  operates 
with  bills  of  lading  or  assignments  of  them.  The 
drudgery  of  computation  may  even  be  relegated  to  a 
machine.  Several  different  types  of  calculating  ma- 
chines are  actually  in  practical  use.  The  earliest  of 
these  (of  any  complexity)  was  the  difference-engine  of 
Babbage,  who  was  familiar  with  the  ideas  here  pre- 
sented. 
Other  ab-  A  numerical  result  is  not  always  reached  by  the 

methods  of  actual  solution  of  the  problem ;  it  may  also  be  reached 
results.  indirectly.  It  is  easy  to  ascertain,  for  example,  that  a 
curve  whose  quadrature  for  the  abscissa  x  has  the  value 
x*"y  gives  an  increment  mx"'~^dx  of  the  quadrature  for 
the  increment  dx  of  the  abscissa.*  But  we  then  also  know 
that  rmx*^''^dx  =  jr*";  that  is,  we  recognise  the  quan- 
tity x^  from  the  increment  mx*^~'dx  diS  unmistakably 
as  we  recognise  a  fruit  by  its  rind.  Results  of  this 
kind,  accidentally  found  by  simple  inversion,  or  by 
processes  more  or  less  analogous,  are  very  extensively 
employed  in  mathematics. 

That  scientific  work  should  be  more  useful  the  more 
it  has  been  used,  while  mechanical  work  is  expended  in 
use,  may  seem  strange  to  us.  When  a  person  who 
daily  takes  the  same  walk  accidentally  finds  a  shorter 
cut,  and  thereafter,  remembering  that  it  is  shorter,  al- 
ways goes  that  way,  he  undoubtedly  saves  himself  the 
difference  of  the  work.  But  memory  is  really  not  work. 


FORMAL  DEVELOPMENT,  489 

It  only  places  at  our  disposal  energy  within  our  present 
or  future  possession,  which  the  circumstance  of  igno- 
rance prevented  us  from  availing  ourselves  of.  This 
is  precisely  the  case  with  the  application  of  scientific 
ideas. 

The  mathematician  who  pursues  his  studies  with-  Nocewity 

of  clear 

out  clear  views  of  this  matter,  must  often  have  the  views  on 

this  sub- 
uncomfortable  feeling  that  his  paper  and  pencil  sur-  ject. 

pass  him  in  intelligence.  Mathematics,  thus  pursued 
as  an  object  of  instruction,  is  scarcely  of  more  educa- 
tional value  than  busying  oneself  with  the  Cabala.  On 
the  contrary,  it  induces  a  tendency  toward  mystery, 
which  is  pretty  sure  to  bear  its  fruits. 

6.  The  science  of  physics  also  furnishes  examples  Examples 
of  this  economy  of  thought,  altogether  similar  to  those  omy  of  ° 
we  have  just  examined.  A  brief  reference  here  will  suf-  phyafcs. 
fice.  The  moment  of  inertia  saves  us  the  separate  con- 
sideration of  the  individual  particles  of  masses.  By 
the  force-function  we  dispense  with  the  separate  in- 
vestigation of  individual  force-components.  The  sim- 
plicity of  reasonings  involving  force-functions  springs 
from  the  fact  that  a  great  amount  of  mental  work  had 
tD  be  performed  before  the  discovery  of  the  properties 
of  the  force-functions  was  possible.  Gauss's  dioptrics 
dispenses  us  from  the  separate  consideration  of  the 
single  refracting  surfaces  of  a  dioptrical  system  and 
substitutes  for  it  the  principal  and  nodal  points.  But 
a  careful  consideration  of  the  single  surfaces  had  to 
precede  the  discovery  of  the  principal  and  nodal  points. 
Gauss's  dioptrics  simply  saves  us  the  necessity  of  often 
repeating  this  consideration. 

We  must  admit,  therefore,  that  there  is  no  result  of 
science  which  in  point  of  principle  could  not  have  been 
arrived  at  wholly  without  methods.     But,  as  a  matter 


490  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

Science  a  of  fact,  withiti  the  short  span  of  a  human  life  and  with 
problem,  man's  limited  powers  of  memory,  any  stock  of  knowl- 
edge worthy  of  the  name  is  unattainable  except  by  the 
greatest  mental  economy.  Science  itself,  therefore, 
may  be  regarded  as  a  minimal  problem,  consisting  of 
the  completest  possible  presentment  of  facts  with  the 
least  possible  expenditure  of  thought. 

7.  The  function  of  science,  as  we  take  it,  is  to  re- 
place experience.  Thus,  on  the  one  hand,  science 
must  remain  in  the  province  of  experience,  but,  on  the 
other,  must  hasten  beyond  it,  constantly  expecting  con- 
firmation, constantly  expecting  the  reverse.  Where 
neither  confirmation  nor  refutation  is  possible,  science 
is  not  concerned.  Science  acts  and  only  acts  in  the 
domain  of  uncompleted  experience.  Exemplars  of  such 
branches  of  science  are  the  theories  of  elasticity  and 
of  the  conduction  of  heat,  both  of  which  ascribe  to  the 
smallest  particles  of  matter  only  such  properties  as  ob- 
servation supplies  in  the  study  of  the  larger  portions. 
The  comparison  of  theory  and  experience  may  be  far- 
ther and  farther  extended,  as  our  means  of  observation 
increase  in  refinement. 

The  princi-       Experience  alone,  without  the  ideas  that  are  asso- 

ple  of  con-       .....  1  1    r 

tinuity.  the  ciated  With  it,  would  torever  remain  strange  to  us. 

entific  Those  ideas  that  hold  good  throughout  the  widest  do- 
mains of  research  and  that  supplement  the  greatest 
amount  of  experience,  are  the  most  scientific.  The  prin- 
ciple of  continuity,  the  use  of  which  everywhere  per- 
vades modern  inquiry,  simply  prescribes  a  mode  of 
conception  which  conduces  in  the  highest  degree  to  the 
economy  of  thought. 

8.  If  a  long  elastic  rod  be  fastened  in  a  vise,  the 
rod  may  be  made  to  execute  slow  vibrations.  These 
are  directly  observable,   can  be  seen,   touched,    and 


method. 


FORMAL  DEVELOPMENT.  491 

graphically  recorded.  If  the  rod  be  shortened,  the  Example  n< 
vibrations  will  increase  in  rapidity  and  cannot  be  di-  of  the 
rectly  seen  ;  the  rod  will  present  to  the  sight  a  blurred  science, 
image.  This  is  a  new  phenomenon.  But  the  sensa- 
tion of  touch  is  still  like  that  of  the  previous  case ;  we 
can  still  make  the  rod  record  its  movements ;  and  if 
we  mentally  retain  the  conception  of  vibrations,  we  can 
still  anticipate  the  results  of  experiments.  On  further 
shortening  the  rod  the  sensation  of  touch  is  altered  ; 
the  rod  begins  to  sound  ;  again  a  new  phenomenon  is 
presented.  But  the  phenomena  do  not  all  change  at 
once;  only  this  or  that  phenomenon  changes;  conse- 
quently the  accompanying  notion  of  vibration,  which 
is  not  confined  to  any  single  one,  is  still  serviceable, 
still  economical.  Even  when  the  sound  has  reached 
so  high  a  pitch  and  the  vibrations  have  become  so 
small  that  the  previous  means  of  observation  are  not 
of  avail,  we  still  advantageously  imagine  the  sounding 
rod  to  perform  vibrations,  and  can  predict  the  vibra- 
tions of  the  dark  lines  in  the  spectrum  of  the  polarised 
light  of  a  rod  of  glass.  If  on  the  rod  being  further 
shortened  aii  the  phenomena  suddenly  passed  into  new 
phenomena,  the  conception  of  vibration  would  no 
longer  be  serviceable  because  it  would  no  longer  afford 
us  a  means  of  supplementing  the  new  experiences  by 
the  previous  ones. 

When  we  mentally  add  to  those  actions  of  a  human 
being  which  we  can  perceive,  sensations  and  ideas  like 
our  own  which  we  cannot  perceive,  the  object  of  the 
idea  we  so  form  is  economical.  The  idea  makes  ex- 
perience intelligible  to  us ;  it  supplements  and  sup- 
plants experience.  This  idea  is  not  regarded  as  a  great 
scientific  discovery,  only  because  its  formation  is  so 
natural  that  every  child  conceives  it.     Now,  this  is 


492  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

exactly  what  we  do  when  we  imagine  a  moving  body 
which  has  just  disappeared  behind  a  pillar,  or  a  comet 
at  the  moment  invisible,  as  continuing  its  motion  and 
retaining  its  previously  observed  properties.  We  do 
this  that  we  may  not  be  surprised  by  its  reappearance. 
We  fill  out  the  gaps  in  experience  by  the  ideas  that 
experience  suggests. 
All  scien-  9-  Yet  not  all  the  prevalent  scientific  theories  origi- 

ories  not  nated  so  naturally  and  artlessly.  Thus,  chemical,  elec- 
the'princ?"  trical,  and  optical  phenomena  are  explained  by  atoms. 
8nu?ty?°°  But  the  mental  artifice  atom  was  not  formed  by  the 
principle  of  continuity ;  on  the  contrary,  it  is  a  pro- 
duct especially  devised  for  the  purpose  in  view.  Atoms 
cannot  be  perceived  by  the  senses  ;  like  all  substances, 
they  are  things  of  thought.  Furthermore,  the  atoms 
are  invested  with  properties  that  absolutely  contradict 
the  attributes  hitherto  observed  in  bodies.  However 
well  fitted  atomic  theories  may  be  to  reproduce  certain 
groups  of  facts,  the  physical  inquirer  who  has  laid  to 
heart  Newton's  rules  will  only  admit  those  theories  as 
provisional  helps,  and  will  strive  to  attain,  in  some  more 
natural  way,  a  satisfactory  substitute. 
Atoms  and  The  atomic  theory  plays  a  part  in  physics  similar 
tai artifices,  to  that  of  Certain  auxiliary  concepts  in  mathematics  ; 
it  is  a  mathematical  model  for  facilitating  the  mental 
reproduction  of  facts.  Although  we  represent  vibra- 
tions by  the  harmonic  formula,  the  phenomena  of  cool- 
ing by  exponentis^ls,  falls  by  squares  of  times,  etc. ,  no ' 
one  will  fancy  that  vibrations  in  themselves  have  any- 
thing to  do  with  the  circular  functions,  or  the  motion 
of  falling  bodies  with  squares.  It  has  simply  been  ob- 
served that  the  relations  between  the  quantities  inves- 
tigated were  similar  to  certain  relations  obtaining  be- 
tween familiar  mathematical  functions,  and  these  more 


FORMAL  DEVELOPMENT.  493 

familiar  ideas  are  employed  as  an  easy  means  of  sup- 
plementing experience.  Natural  phenomena  whose  re- 
lations are  not  similar  to  those  of  functions  with  which 
we  are  familiar,  are  at  present  very  difiBcult  to  recon- 
struct. But  the  progress  of  mathematics  may  facilitate 
the  matter. 

As  mathematical  helps  of  this  kind,  spaces  of  more  Nfaia- 
than  three  dimensions  may  be  used,  as  I  have  else-  sioned 

,  ,  ^        .     .  ,    ,  spaces. 

where  shown.  But  it  is  not  necessary  to  regard  these, 
on  this  account,  as  anything  more  than  mental  arti- 
fices. * 

*  As  the  outcome  of  the  labors  of  Lobatschewsky,  Bolyai,  Gauss,  and  Rie- 
mann,  the  view  has  gradually  obtained  currency  in  the  mathematical  world, 
that  that  which  we  call  s^ct  is  a  particular^  actual  case  of  a  more  general^ 
conceivable  case  of  multiple  quantitative  manifoldness.  The  space  of  sight 
and  touch  is  a  threefold  manifoldness;  it  possesses  three  dimensions ;  and 
every  point  in  it  can  be  defined  by  three  distinct  and  independent  data.  But 
it  is  possible  to  conceive  of  a  quadruple  or  even  multiple  space-like  manifold- 
ness. And  the  character  of  the  manifoldness  may  also  be  differently  conceived 
from  the  manifoldness  of  actual  space.  We  regard  this  discovery,  which  is 
chiefly  due  to  the  labors  of  Riemann,  as  a  very  important  one.  The  properties 
of  actual  space  are  here  directly  exhibited  as  objects  of  experience^  and  the 
pseudo-theories  of  geometry  that  seek  to  excogitate  these  properties  by  meta- 
physical arguments  are  overthrown. 

A  thinking  being  is  supposed  to  live  in  the  surface  of  a  sphere,  with  no 
other  kind  of  space  to  institute  comparisons  with.  His  space  will  appear  to 
him  similarly  constituted  throughout.  He  might  regard  ^t  as  infinite,  and 
could  only  be  convinced  of  the  contrary  by  experience.  Starting  from  any  two 
points  of  a  great  circle  of  the  sphere  and  proceeding  at  right  angles  thereto  on 
other  great  circles,  he  could  hardly  expect  that  the  circles  last  mentioned 
would  intersect.  So,  also,  with  respect  to  the  space  in  which  we  live,  only  ex- 
perience can  decide  whether  it  is  finite,  whether  parallel  lines  intersect  in  it, 
or  the  like.  The  significance  of  this  elucidation  can  scarcely  be  overrated. 
An  enlightenment  similar  to  that  which  Riemann  inaugurated  in  science  was 
produced  in  the  mind  of  humanity  at  large,  as  regards  the  surface  of  the  earth, 
by  the  discoveries  of  the  first  circumnavigators. 

The  theoretical  investigation  of  the  mathematical  possibilities  above  re- 
ferred to,  has,  primarily,  nothing  to  do  with  the  question  whether  things  really 
exist  which  correspond  to  these  possibilities ;  and  we  must  not  hold  mathe- 
maticians responsible  for  the  popular  absurdities  which  their  investigations 
have  given  rise  to.  The  space  of  sight  and  touch  is  /ArM-dimensional ;  that, 
no  one  ever  yet  doubted.  If,  now,  it  should  be  found  that  bodies  vanish  from 
this  space,  or  new  bodies  get  into  it,  the  question  might  scientifically  be  dis- 
cussed whether  it  would  facilitate  and  promote  our  insight  into  things  to  con- 
ceive experiential  space  as  part  of  a  four-dimensional  or  multi-dimensional 


494  THE  SCIE.VCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

Hypotheses  This  is  the  case,  too,  with  ail  hypothesis  formed 
for  the  explanation  of  new  phenomena.  Our  concep- 
tions of  electricity  fit  in  at  once  with  the  electrical  phe- 
nomena, and  take  almost  spontaneously  the  familiar 
course,  the  moment  we  note  that  things  take  place  as 
if  attracting  and  repelling  fluids  moved  on  the  surface 
of  the  conductors.  But  these  mental  expedients  have 
nothing  whatever  to  do  with  the  phenomenon  itself, 

space.  Yet  in  such  a  case,  this  fourth  dimension  would,  none  the  less,  remain 
a  pure  thing  of  thought,  a  mental  fiction. 

But  this  is  not  the  way  matters  stand.  The  phenomena  mentioned  were 
not  forthcoming  until  a/ter  the  new  views  were  published,  and  were  then  ex- 
hibited in  the  presence  of  certain  persons  at  spiritualistic  stances.  The  fourth 
dimension  was  a  very  opportune  discover*-  for  the  spiritualists  and  for  theo- 
logians who  were  in  a  quandary  about  the  location  of  hell.  The  use  the  spiri- 
tualist, makes  of  the  fourth  dimension  is  this.  It  is  possible  to  move  out  of  a 
finite  straight  line,  without  passing  the  extremities,  through  the  second  dimen- 
sion ;  out  of  a  finite  closed  surface  through  the  third  ;  and,  analogously,  oat 
of  a  finite  closed  space,  without  passing  through  the  enclosing  boundaries, 
through  the  fourth  dimension.  Even  the  tricks  that  prestidigitateurs,  in  the 
old  days,  harmlessly  executed  in  three  dimensions,  are  now  invested  with  a 
new  halo  by  the  fourth.  But  the  tricks  of  the  spiritualists,  the  tying  or  untying 
of  knots  in  endless  strings,  the  removing  of  bodies  from  closed  spaces,  are  all 
performed  in  cases  where  there  is  absolutely  nothing  at  stake.  AH  is  purpose- 
less jugglery.  We  nave  not  yet  found  an  a<-a?M<:Arwr  who  has  accomplished 
parturition  through  the  fourth  dimension.  If  we  should,  the  question  would 
at  once  become  a  serious  one.  Professor  Simony's  beautiful  tricks  in  rope- 
tying,  which,  as  the  performance  of  a  prestidigitateur,  are  very  admirable, 
speak  against,  not  for,  the  spiritualists. 

Everyone  is  free  to  set  up  an  opinion  and  to  adduce  proofs  in  support  of 
it.  Whether,  though,  a  scientist  !:ha11  find  it  worth  his  while  to  enter  into 
serious  investigations  of  opinions  so  advanced,  is  a  question  which  his  reason 
and  instinct  alone  can  decide.  If  these  things,  in  the  end,  should  turn  out  to 
be  true,  I  shall  not  be  ashamed  of  being  the  last  to  believe  them.  What  I  have 
seen  of  them  was  not  calculated  to  make  me  less  sceptical. 

I  myself  regarded  multi-dimensioned   space  as  a  mathematico-physical 

help  even  prior  to  the  appearance  of  Riemann's  memoir.     Hut  I  trust  that 

no  one  will  employ  what  I  have  thought,  said,  and  written  on  this  subject  as  a 

basis  for  the  fabrication  of  ghost  stories.  (Compare  Mach,  Die  Ctsckickte  und 

die  Wurzel  dee  Satzee  von  der  ErkaUung  der  Arbeit.) 


CHAPTER  V. 


THE  RELATIONS  OF  MECHANICS  TO  OTHER  DE-  ! 

PARTMENTS  OF  KNOWLEDGE. 


THE  RELATIONS  OF  MECHANICS  TO  PHYSICS. 

1 .  Purely  mechanical  phenomena  do  not  exist.   The  Tj^e  events 

•'  *  ^  ^  ^  of  nature 

production  of  mutual  accelerations  in  masses  is,  to  all<*ono*"- 

*  '  cUistvely 

appearances,  a  purely  dynamical  phenomenon.  But  belong  to 
with  these  dynamical  results  are  always  associated  cn<=«- 
thermal,  magnetic,  electrical,  and  chemical  phenom- 
ena, and  the  former  are  always  modified  in  proportion 
as  the  latter  are  asserted.  On  the  other  hand,  thermal, 
magnetic,  electrical,  and  chemical  conditions  also  can 
produce  motions.  Purely  mechanical  phenomena,  ac- 
cordingly, are  abstractions,  made,  either  intentionally 
or  from  necessity,  for  facilitating  our  comprehension  of 
things.  The  same  thing  is  true  of  the  other  classes  of 
physical  phenomena.  Every  event  belongs,  in  a  strict 
sense,  to  all  the  departments  of  physics,  the  latter  be- 
ing separated  only  by  an  artificial  classification,  which 
is  partly  conventional,  partly  physiological,  and  partly 
historical. 

2.  The  view  that  makes  mechanics  the  basis  of  the 
remaining  branches  of  physics,  and  explains  all  physical 
phenomena  by  mechanical  ideas,  is  in  our  judgment  a 
prejudice.  Knowledge  which  is  historically  first,  is 
not  necessarily  the  foundation  of  all  that  is  subsequently 


world. 


496  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

The  me-      gained.     As  more  and  more  facts  are  discovered  and 
aspects  of   classified,  entirely  new  ideas  of  general  scope   can  be 

nature  not 

necessarily  formed.    We  have  no  means  of  knowmg,  as  yet,  w^hich 

its  funda- 
mental       of  the  physical  phenomena  go  deepest^   whether   the 

mechanical  phenomena  are  perhaps  not  the  most  super- 
ficial of  ^all,  or  whether  all  do  not  go  equally  deep.  Even 
in  mechanics  we  no  longer  regard  the  oldest  laiv,  the 
law  of  the  lever,  as  the  foundation  of  all  the  other 
principles. 
Artificiality       The  mechanical  theory  of  nature,  is,  undoubtedly, 

of  the  me-  .  . 

chanicai     in  an  historical  view,  both  intelligible  and  pardonable ; 

conception  .  i.  ,  , 

of  the  and  it  may  also,  for  a  time,  have  been  of  much  value. 
But,  upon  the  whole,  it  is  an  artificial  conception. 
Faithful  adherence  to  the  method  that  led  the  greatest 
investigators  of  nature,  Galileo,  Newton,  Sadi  Carnot, 
Faraday,  and  J.  R.  Mayer,  to  their  great  results,  re- 
stricts physics  to  the  expression  of  actual  facts^  and 
forbids  the  construction  of  hypotheses  behind  the  facts, 
where  nothing  tangible  and  verifiable  is  found.  If  this 
is  done,  only  the  simple  connection  of  the  motions  of 
masses,  of  changes  of  temperature,  of  changes  in  the 
values  of  the  potential  function,  of  chemical  changes, 
and  so  forth  is  to  be  ascertained,  and  nothing  is  to  be 
imagined  along  with  these  elements  except  the  physical 
attributes  or  characteristics  directly  or  indirectly  given 
by  observation. 

This  idea  was  elsewhere  *  developed  by  the  author 
with  respect  to  the  phenomena  of  heat,  and  indicated, 
in  the  same  place,  with  respect  to  electricity.  All  hy- 
potheses of  fluids  or  media  are  eliminated  from  the 
theory  of  electricity  as  entirely  superfluous,  when  we 
reflect  that  electrical  conditions  are  all  given  by  the 

*  Mach,  Die  Gesckiehte  und  dU  Wnrul  d€t  S»tzes  von  der  Erhaitun^  dtr 
Arbeit. 


/ 


ITS  RELATIONS  TO  OTHER  SCIENCES.  497 

values  of  the  potential  function  V  and  the  dielectric  Science 
constants.     If  we  assume  the  differences  of  the  values  based  on 

facts,  not 

of  VX,o  be  measured  (on  the  electrometer)  by  the  forces,  on  hypoth- 
and  regard  V  and  not  the  quantity  of  electricity  Q  as 
the  primary  notion,  or  measurable  physical  attribute, 
we  shall  have,  for  any  simple  insulator,  for  our  quan- 
tity of  electricity 

<?=  4;rJ   \dx-+-dy-+-d^r^ 

(where  x,  y,  z  denote  the  coordinates  and  dv  the  ele- 
ment of  volume,)  and  for  our  potential* 

%7t  J      \dx'^^  dy"^^  dz^ 

Here  Q  and  ^appear  as  derived  notions,  in  which  no 
conception  of  fluid  or  medium  is  contained.  If  we 
work  over  in  a  similar  manner  the  entire  domain  of 
physics,  we  shall  restrict  ourselves  wholly  to  the  quan- 
titative conceptual  expression  of  actual  facts.  All  su- 
perfluous and  futile  notions  are  eliminated,  and  the 
imaginary  problems  to  which  they  have  given  rise  fore- 
stalled. 

The  removal  of  notions  whose  foundations  are  his- 
torical, conventional,  or  accidental,  can  best  be  fur- 
thered by  a  comparison  of  the  conceptions  obtaining 
in  the  different  departments,  and  by  finding  for  the 
conceptions  of  every  department  the  corresponding 
conceptions  of  others.  We  discover,  thus,  that  tem- 
peratures and  potential  functions  correspond  to  the 
velocities  of  mass-motions.  A  single  velocity-value,  a 
single  temperature-value,  or  a  single  value  of  potential 
function,  never  changes  alone.  But  whilst  in  the  case 
of  velocities  and  potential  functions,  so  far  as  we  yet 

*  Using  the  terminology  of  Clausius. 


498 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHAXICS. 


Desirabil- 
ity of  a 
compara- 
tive phys- 
ics. 


Circum- 
stances 
which  fa- 
vored the 
develop- 
ment of  the 
mechanical 
view. 


know,  only  differences  come  into  consideration,  the 
significance  of  temperature  is  not  only  contained  in  its 
difference  with  respect  to  other  temperatures.  Thermal 
capacities  correspond  to  masses,  the  potential  of  an 
electric  charge  to  quantity  of  heat,  quantity  of  elec- 
tricity to  entropy,  and  so  on.  The  pursuit  of  such  re- 
semblances and  differences  lays  the  foundation  of  a 
comparative  physics^  which  shall  ultimately  render  pos- 
sible the  concise  expression  of  extensive  groups  of  facts, 
without  arbitrary  additions.  We  shall  then  possess  a 
homogeneous  physics,  unmingled  with  artificial  atomic 
theories. 

It  will  also  be  perceived,  that  a  real  economy  of 
scientific  thought  cannot  be  attained  by  mechanical 
hypotheses.  Even  if  an  hypothesis  were  fully  com- 
petent to  reproduce  a  given  department  of  natural  phe- 
nomena, say,  the  phenomena  of  heat,  we  should,  by 
accepting  it,  only  substitute  for  the  actual  relations  be- 
tween the  mechanical  and  thermal  processes,  the  hy- 
pothesis. '  The  real  fundamental  facts  are  replaced  by 
an  equally  large  number  of  hypotheses,  which  is  cer- 
tainly no  gain.  Once  an  hypothesis  has  facilitated, 
as  best  it  can,  our  view  of  new  facts,  by  the  substitu- 
tion of  more  familiar  ideas,  its  powers  are  exhausted. 
We  err  when  we  expect  more  enlightenment  from-  an 
hypothesis  than  from  the  facts  themselves. 

^3.  The  development  of  the  mechanical  view  was 
favored  by  many  circumstances.  In  the  first  place,  a 
connection  of  all  natural  events  with  mechanical  pro- 
cesses is  unmistakable,  and  it  is  natural,  therefore,  that 
we  should  be  led  to  explain  less  known  phenomena  by 
better  known  mechanical  events.  Then  again,  it  was 
first  in  the  department  of  mechanics  that  laws  of  gen- 
eral and  extensive  scope  were  discovered^   A  law  of 


ITS  RELATIONS  TO  OTHER  SCIENCES.  499 

this  kind  is  the  principle  of  vis  znva  2 (U"^  —  C/q)  = 
2^pt  (?'2  —  p2^^  which  states  that  the  increase  of  the 
vis  vi7'a  of  a  system  in  its  passage  from  one  position  to 
another  is  equal  to  the  increment  of  the  force-function, 
or  work,  which  is  expressed  as  a  function  of  the  final 
and  initial  positions.  If  we  fix  our  attention  on  the 
work  a  system  can  perform  and  call  it  with  Helmholtz 
the  Spannkraft^  S,*  then  the  work  actually  performed^ 
U,  will  appear  as  a  diminution  of  the  Spannkra/t,  Ky 
initially  present;  accordingly,  S=K — Uy  and  the 
principle  of  vis  viva  takes  the  form 

2S  -\-  ^2mv^  =  const y 

that  is  to  say,  every  diminution  of  the  Spannkraft,  is  The  cpn- 
compensated  for  by  an  increase  of  the  vis  tnva.   In  this  Energy, 
form  the  principle  is  also  called  the  law  of  the  Conser- 
vation of  Energy y  in  that  the  sum  of  the  Spannkra/t  (the 
potential  energy)  and  the  vis  viva  (the  kinetic  energy) 
remains  constant  in  the  system.    But  since,  in  nature, 
it  is  possible  that  not  only  vis  viva  should  appear  as  the 
consequence  of  work  performed,  but  also  quantities  of 
heat,  or  the  potential  of  an  electric  charge,  and  so  forth, 
scientists  saw  in  this  law  the  expression  of  a  mechanical 
action  as  the  basis  of  all  natural  actions.     However, 
nothing  is  contained  in  the  expression  but  the  fact  of 
an  invariable  quantitative  connection  between  mechani- 
cal and  other  kinds  of  phenomena. 

4.  It  would  be  a  mistake  to  suppose  that  a  wide 
and  extensive  view  of  things  was  first  introduced  into 
physical  science  by  mechanics.     On  the  contrary,  this 

*  Helmholts  used  this  term  in  1847;  but  it  is  not  found  in  his  subsequent 
papers;  and  in  1882  {WUsentcka/tlichg  Abkandlungen,  II,  965)  he  expressly 
discards  it  in  favor  of  the  English  "  potential  energy."  He  even  (p.  968)  pre- 
fers Clausius's  word  Ergal  to  S^nnkraft^  which  is  quite  out  of  agreement 
with  modern  terminology.— TVaffj. 


500  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

Compre-     insight  was  possessed  at  all  times  by  the  foremost 

hensive-        .  .  ,  ,    •  ,  .  ^ 

nessof  inquirers  and  even  entered  into  the  construction  of 
condition,  mechanics  itself,  and  was,  accordingly,  not  first  created 
suit,  of  me-  by  the  latter.     Galileo  and  Huygens  constantly  alter- 

chfiinics.  . 

nated  the  consideration  of  particular  details  with  the 
consideration  of  universal  aspects,  and  reached  their 
results  only  by  a  persistent  effort  after  a  simple  and 
consistent  view.  The  fact  that  the  velocities  of  indi- 
vidual bodies  and  systems  are  dependent  on  the  spaces 
descended  through,  was  perceived  by  Galileo  and 
Huygens  only  by  a  very  detailed  investigation  of  the 
motion  of  descent  in  particular  cases,  combined  with 
the  consideration  of  the  circumstance  that  bodies  gen- 
erally, of  their  own  accord,  only  sink.  Huygens 
especially  speaks,  on  the  occasion  of  this  inquiry,  of 
the  impossibility  of  a  mechanical  perpetual  motion  ; 
he  possessed,  therefore,  the  modern  point  of  view.  He 
felt  the  incompatibility  of  the  idea  of  a  perpetual  motion 
with  the  notions  of  the  natural  mechanical  processes 
with  which  he  was  familiar. 
Exempiifi-  Take  the  fictions  of  Stevinus — say,  that  of  the  end- 
this  in  ste-  less  chaiu  on  the  prism.  Here,  too,  a  deep,  broad 
searches,  insight  is  displayed.  We  have  here  a  mind,  disciplined 
by  a  multitude  of  experiences,  brought  to  bear  on  an 
individual  case.  The  moving  endless  chain  is  to  Ste- 
vinus a  motion  of  descent  that  is  not  a  descent,  a  mo- 
tion without  a  purpose,  an  intentional  act  that  does 
not  answer  to  the  intention,  an  endeavor  for  a  change 
which  does  not  produce  the  change.  If  motion,  gener- 
ally, is  the  result  of  descent,  then  in  the  particular  case 
descent  is  the  result  of  motion.  It  is  a  sense  of  the 
mutual  interdependence  of  v  and  h  in  the  equation 
V  =  \/  2g/i  that  is  here  displayed,  though  of  course  in 
not  so  definite  a  form.     A  contradiction  exists  in  this 


ITS  RELATIONS  TO  OTHER  SCIENCES.  501 

fiction  for  Stevinus's  exquisite  investigative  sense  that 
would  escape  less  profound  thinkers. 

This  same  breadth  of  view,  which  alternates  the  Also,  in  the 
individual  with  the  universal,  is  also  displayed,  only  in  of  carnot 
this  instance  not  restricted  to  mechanics,  in  the  per-  Mayer, 
formances  of  Sadi  Carnot.  When  Carnot  finds  that 
the  quantity  of  heat  Q  which,  for  a  given  amount  of 
work  Z,  has  flgwed  from  a  higher  temperature  /  to  a 
lower  temperature  /*,  can  only  depend  on  the  tempera- 
tures and  not  on  the  material  constitution  of  the  bodies, 
he  reasons  in  exact  conformity  with  the  method  of 
Galileo.  Similarly  does  J.  R.  Mayer  proceed  in  the 
enunciation  of  the  principle  of  the  equivalence  of  heat 
and  work.  In  this  achievement  the  mechanical  view 
was  quite  remote  from  Mayer's  mind  ;  nor  had  he  need 
of  it.  They  who  require  the  crutch  of  the  mechanical 
philosophy  to  understand  the  doctrine  of  the  equiva- 
lence of  heat  and  work,  have  only  half  comprehended 
the  progress  which  it  signalises.  Yet,  high  as  we  may 
place  Mayer's  original  achievement,  it  is  not  on  that 
account  necessary  to  depreciate  the  merits  of  the  pro- 
fessional physicists  Joule,  Helmholtz,  Clausius,  and 
Thomson,  who  have  done  very  much,  perhaps  all,  to- 
wards the  detailed  establishment  and  perfection  of  the 
new  view.  The  assumption  of  a  plagiarism  of  Mayer's 
ideas  is  in  our  opinion  gratuitous.  They  who  advance 
it,  are  under  the  obligation  Xo  prove  it.  The  repeated 
appearance  of  the  same  idea  is  not  new  in  history.  We 
shall  not  take  up  here  the  discussion  of  purely  personal 
questions,  which  thirty  years  from  now  will  no  longer 
interest  students.  But  it  is  unfair,  from  a  pretense  of 
justice,  to  insult  men,  who  if  they  had  accomplished 
but  a  third  of  their  actual  services  to  science,  would 
have  lived  highly  honored  and  unmolested  lives. 


502  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

The  inter-  5.  We  shall  now  attempt  to  show  that  the  broad 

enceofthe  vicw  expressed  in  the  principle  of  the  conservation 

faicts  of  nsi- 

ture.  of  energy,  is  not  peculiar  to  mechanics,  but  is  a  condi- 

tion of  logical  and  sound  scientific  thought  generally. 
The  business  of  physical  science  is  the  reconstruction 
of  facts  in  thought,  or  the  abstract  quantitative  expres- 
sion of  facts.  The  rules  which  we  form  for  these  recon- 
structions are  the  laws  of  nature.  In  the  conviction  that 
such  rules  are  possible  lies  the  law  of  causality.  The 
law  of  causality  simply  asserts  that  the  phenomena  of 
nature  are  dependent  on  one  another.  The  special  em- 
phasis put  on  space  and  time  in  the  expression  of  the 
law  of  causality  is  unnecessary,  since  the  relations  of 
space  and  time  themselves  implicitly  express  that  phe- 
nomena are  dependent  on  one  another. 

The  laws  of  nature  are  equations  between  the  meas> 
urable  elements  afiyd ,  .  .  .  a?  of  phenomena.  As  na- 
ture is  variable,  the  number  of  these  equations  is  al- 
ways less  than  the  number  of  the  elements. 

If  we  know  all  the  values  ol  afiyd ,  .  .yhy  which, 
for  example,  the  values  of  X/iv .  . .  are  given,  we  may- 
call  the  group  afiyd.  .  .  the  cause  and  the  group 
XjjLV ,  .  .  the  effect.  In  this  sense  we  may  say  that  the 
effect  is  uniquely  determined  by  the  cause.  The  prin- 
ciple of  sufficient  reason,  in  the  form,  for  instance,  in 
which  Archimedes  employed  it  in  the  development  of 
the  laws  of  the  lever,  consequently  asserts  nothing 
more  than  that  the  effect  cannot  by  any  given  set  of 
circumstances  be  at  once  determined  and  undetermined. 

If  two  circumstances  a  and  X  are  connected,  then, 
supposing  all  others  are  constant,  a  change  of  X  will 
be  accompanied  by  a  change  of  a,  and  as  a  general 
rule  a  change  of  or  by  a  change  of  X,  The  constant 
observance  of  this  mutual  interdependence  is  met  with 


ITS  RELATIONS  TO  OTHER  SCIENCES.  503 

in  Stevinus,  Galileo,  Huygens,  and  other  great  inquir- Sense  of 

.  , .  ,  this  inter- 

ers.     The  idea  is  also  at  the  basis  of  the  discovery  of  depend- 

ence  at  the 

r^i/w/^T- phenomena.     Thus,  a  chan^^e  in  the  volume  of  basis  of  aii 

.  .  J  great  dis- 

a  gas  due  to  a  change  of  temperature  is  supplemented  coveries. 
by  the  counter-phenomenon  of  a  change  of  tempera- 
ture on  an  alteration  of  volume  ;  Seebeck's  phenome- 
non by  Peltier's  effect,  and  so  forth. 
Care  must,  of  course,  be  exercised,  in 
such  inversions,  respecting  the  form 
of  the  dependence.     Figure  235  will 
render  clear  how  a  perceptible  altera- 
tion of  a  may  always  be  produced  by 
an  alteration  of  A,  but  a  change  of  A 
not  necessarily  by  a  change  of  or.     The  relations  be- 
tween electromagnetic  and  induction  phenomena,  dis- 
covered by  Faraday,  are  a  good  instance  of  this  truth. 

If  a  set  of  circumstances  aByd ,  .  .,  by  which  ay»"oa« 

'    /  ■'  forms  of  ex- 

second  set  Xuv .  .  ,   is  determined,  be  made  to  pass  pj"?*"**"  <>' 

,    ,    '^  \  *^       ^  this  truth. 

from  its  initial  values  to  the  terminal  values  a' ^'y 
d\  .  .,  then  Xjjlv,  .  .  also  will  pass  intoA'/iV.  .  . 
If  the  first  set  be  brought  back  to  its  initial  state,  also 
the  second  set  will  be  brought  back  to  its  initial  state. 
This  is  the  meaning  of  the  **  equivalence  of  cause  and 
effect,"  which  Mayer  again  and  again  emphasizes. 

If  the  first  group  suffer  only  periodical  changes,  the 
second  group  also  can  suffer  only  periodical  changes, 
not  continuous  permanent  ones.  The  fertile  methods 
of  thought  of  Galileo,  Huygens,  S.  Carnot,  Mayer, 
and  their  peers,  are  all  reducible  to  the  simple  but  sig- 
nificant perception,  thai  purely  periodical  alterations  of 
one  set  of  circumstances  can  only  constitute  the  source  of 
similarly  periodical  alterations  of  a  second  set  of  circum- 
stances,  not  of  continuous  and  permanent  alterations.  Such 
maxims,  as  "the  effect  is  equivalent  to  the  cause," 


504  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

"work  cannot  be  created  out  of  nothing,"  '*a  per- 
petual motion  is  impossible,"  are  particular,  less  defi- 
nite, and  less  evident  forms  of  this  perception,  which 
in  itself  is  not  especially  concerned  with  mechanics,  but 
is  a  constituent  of  scientific  thought  generally.  With 
the  perception  of  this  truths  any  metaphysical  mystic- 
ism that  may  still  adhere  to  the  principle  of  the  con- 
servation of  energy*  is  dissipated.  (See  Appendix,  VI. ) 
Purpose  of         AH  ideas  of  conservation,  like  the  notion  of  sub- 

the  ideas  of  ... 

conserva-    Stance,   have  a  solid   foundation  in  the  economy  of 

tion.  •' 

'  thought.  A  mere  unrelated  change,  without  fixed  point 
of  support,  or  reference,  is  not  comprehensible,  not 
mentally  reconstructible.  We  always  inquire,  accord- 
ingly, what  idea  can  be  retained  amid  all  variations  as 
permanenty  what  law  prevails,  what  equation  remains 
fulfilled,  what  quantitative  values  remain  constant  ? 
When  we  say  the  refractive  index  remains  constant  in 
all  cases  of  refraction,  ^remains  =  9-810 w  in  all  cases 
of  the  motion  of  heavy  bodies,  the  energy  remains  con- 
stant in  every  isolated  system,  all  our  assertions  have 
one  and  the  same  economical  function,  namely  that  of 
facilitating  our  mental  reconstruction  of  facts. 

II. 

THE  RELATIONS  OF  MECHANICS  TO  PHYSIOLOGY. 

Conditions         !•   All  scicnce  has  its  origin  in  the  needs  of  life. 

deleTop"*  However  minutely  it  may  be  subdivided  by  particular 
vocations  or  by  the  restricted  tempers  and  capacities  of 
those  who  foster  it,  each  branch  can  attain  its  full  and 
best  development  only  by  a  living  connection  with  the 
whole.     Through  such  a  union  alone  can  it  approach 

♦  When  we  reflect  that  the  principles  of  science  are  all  abstractions  that 
presuppose  ref*etitions  of  similar  cases,  the  absurd  applications  of  the  law  of 
the  conservation  of  forces  to  the  universe  as  a  whole  fall  to  the  ground. 


ment  of 
science. 


ITS  RELATIONS  TO  OTHER  SCIENCES,  505 

its  true  maturity,  and  be  insured  against  lop-sided  and 
monstrous  growths. 

The  division  of  labor,  the  restriction  of  individual  Confusion 

of  the 

inquirers  to   limited    provinces,   the   investigation   of  means  and 

aims  of 

those  provinces  as  a  life-work,  are  the  fundamental  science, 
conditions  of  a  fruitful  development  of  science.  Only 
by  such  specialisation  and  restriction  of  work  can  the 
economical  instruments  of  thought  requisite  for  the 
mastery  of  a  special  field  be  perfected.  But  just  here 
lies  a  danger — the  danger  of  our  overestimating  the  in- 
struments, with  which  we  are  so  constantly  employed, 
or  even  of  regarding  them  as  the  objective  point  of 
science. 

2.  Now,  such  a  state  of  affairs  has,  in  our  opinion,  physics 
actually  been  produced  by  the  disproportionate  formal  mad?tL 
development  of  physics.  The  majority  of  natural  in-  pSySoiogy. 
quirers  ascribe  to  the  intellectual  implements  of  physics, 
to  the  concepts  mass,  force,  atom,  and  so  forth,  whose 
sole  office  is  to  revive  economically  arranged  expe- 
riences, a  reality  beyond  and  independent  of  thought. 
Not  only  so,  but  it  has  even  been  held  that  these  forces 
and  masses  are  the  real  objects  of  inquiry,  and,  if  once 
they  were  fully  explored,  all  the  rest  would  follow  from 
the  equilibrium  and  motion  of  these  masses.  A  person 
who  knew  the  world  only  through  the  theatre,  if  brought 
behind  the  scenes  and  permitted  to  view  the  mechan- 
ism of  the  stage's  action,  might  possibly  believe  that 
the  real  world  also  was  in  need  of  a  machine-room,  and 
that  if  this  were  once  thoroughly  explored,  we  should 
know  all.  Similarly,  we,  too,  should  beware  lest  the 
intellectual  machinery,  employed  in  the  representation 
of  the  world  on  the  stage  of  thought,  be  regarded  as  the 
basis  of  the  real  world. 

.3.  A  philosophy  is  involved  in  any  correct  view  of 


5o6  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

The  at-       the  relations  of  special  knowledge  to  the  great  body  of 

tempt  to  ex-  ^^  t»  -f 

plain  feel-   knowledge  at  large, — a  philosophy  that  must  be  de- 

inf{s  by 

motions,  manded  of  every  special  investigator.  The  lack  of  it 
is  asserted  in  the  formulation  of  imaginary  problems, 
in  the  very  enunciation  of  which,  whether  regarded  as 
soluble  or  insoluble,  flagrant  absurdity  is  involved. 
Such  an  overestimation  of  physics,  in  contrast  to  physi- 
ology, such  a  mistaken  conception  of  the  true  relations 
of  the  two  sciences,  is  displayed  in  the  inquiry  whether 
it  is  possible  to  explain  feelings  by  the  motions  of 
atoms? 

Explication        Let  US  Seek  the  conditions  that  could  have  impelled 

of  this  .  .  ^ 

anomaly,  the  mind  to  formulate  so  curious  a  question.  We  find 
in  the  first  place  that  greater  confidence  is  placed  in  our 
experiences  concerning  relations  of  time  and  space ; 
that  we  attribute  to  them  a  more  objective,  a  more  real 
character  than  to  our  experiences  of  colors,  sounds, 
temperatures,  and  so  forth.  Yet,  if  we  investigate  the 
matter  accurately,  we  must  surely  admit  that  our  sen- 
sations of  time  and  space  are  just  as  much  sensations 
as  are  our  sensations  of  colors,  sotinds,  and  odors,  only 
that  in  our  knowledge  of  the  former  we  are  surer  and 
clearer  than  in  that  of  the  latter.  Space  and  time  are 
well-ordered  systems  of  sets  of  sensations.  The  quan- 
tities stated  in  mechanical  equations  are  simply  ordinal 
symbols,  representing  those  members  of  these  sets 
that  are  to  be  mentally  isolated  and  emphasised.  The 
equations  express  the  form  of  interdependence  of  these 
ordinal  symbols. 

A  body  is  a  relatively  constant  sum  of  touch  and 
sight  sensations  associated  with  the  same  space  and 
time  sensations.  Mechanical  principles,  like  that,  for 
instance,  of  the  mutually  induced  accelerations  of  two 
masses,  give,  either  directly  or  indirectly,  only  some 


ITS  RELATIONS  TO    OTHER  SCIENCES.  507 


* 


combination  of  touch,  sight,  light,  and  time  sensations. 
They  possess  intelligible  meaning  only  by  virtue  of 
the  sensations  they  involve,  the  contents  of  which  may 
of  course  be  very  complicated. 

It  would  be  equivalent,  accordingly,  to  explaining  Mode  of 

-     .  .  ,  ,.    avoiding 

the  more  simple  and  immediate  by  the  more  compli-  such  er- 

.  rors. 

cated  and  remote,  if  we  were  to  attempt  to  derive  sen- 
sations from  the  motions  of  masses,  wholly  aside  from 
the  consideration  that  the  notions  of  mechanics  are 
economical  implements  or  expedients  perfected  to 
represent  mechanical  and  not  physiological  or  psycho- 
logical facts.  If  the  means  and  aims  of  research  were 
properly  distinguished,  and  our  expositions  were  re- 
stricted to  the  presentation  of  actual  fads,  false  prob- 
lems of  this  kind  could  not  arise. 

4.  All  physical  knowledge  can  only  mentally  repre-  The  princi- 
sent  and  anticipate  compounds  of  those  elements  we ch?n?csn^t 
call  sensations.    It  is  concerned  with  the  connection  of  don  but 
these  elements.  Such  an  element,  say  the  heat  of  a  body  ll^ect  o" 
A,  is  connected,  not  only  with  other  elements,  say  with 
such  whose  aggregate  makes  up  the  flame  B,  but  also 
with  the  aggregate  of  certain  elements  of  our  body,  say 
with  the  aggregate  of  the  elements  of  a  nerve  N.     As 
simple  object  and  element  Nis  not  essentially,  but  only 
conventionally,  different  from  A  and  B.  The  connection 
of  A  and  ^  is  a  problem  of  physics,  that  of  A  and  N  a 
problem  oi physiology.    Neither  is  alone  existent;  both 
exist  at  once.      Only  provisionally   can   we    neglect 
either.     Processes,  thus,  that  in  appearance  are  purely 
mechanical,  are,  in  addition  to  their  evident  mechani- 
cal features,  always  physiological,  and,  consequently, 
also  electrical,  chemical,  and  so  forth.    The  science  of 
mechanics  does  not  comprise  the  foundations,  no,  nor 
even  a  part  of  the  world,  but  only  an  aspect  of  it. 


APPENDIX. 

I. 

(See  page  140.} 

In  an  exhaustive  study  in  the  Zeitschrift  fiir  Volker- 
psychologies  1884,  Vol.  XIV,  pp.  365-410,  and  Vol.  XV, 
pp.  70-135,  337-387,  entitled  Die  Entdeckung  des  Be- 
harrungsgesetzeSy  E.  Wohlwill  has  shown  that  the  prede- 
cessors and  contemporaries  of  Galileo,  nay,  even  Gali- 
leo himself,  only  t^ery  gradually  abandoned  the  Aristo- 
telian conceptions  for  the  acceptance  of  the  law  of  in- 
ertia. Even  in  Galileo's  mind  uniform  circular  motion 
and  uniform  horizontal  motion  occupy  distinct  places. 
Wohlwill's  researches  are  very  acceptable  and  show 
that  Galileo  had  not  attained  perfect  clearness  in  his 
own  new  ideas  and  was  liable  to  frequent  reversion  to 
the  old  views,  as  might  have  been  expected. 

Indeed,  from  my  own  exposition  the  reader  will 
have  inferred  that  the  law  of  inertia  did  not  possess 
in  Galileo's  mind  the  degree  of  clearness  and  univer- 
sality that  it  subsequently  acquired.  (See  pp.  140 
and  143.)  With  regard  to  my  exposition  at  pages 
1 40-141,  however,  I  still  believef  in  spite  of  the  opin- 
ions of  Wohlwill  and  Poske,  that  I  have  indicated  the 
point  which  both  for  Galileo  and  his  successors  must 
have  placed  in  the  most  favorable  light  the  transition  B 
from  the  old  conception  to  the  new. 


5IO  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 

II. 
(See  page  218.} 

H.  Streintz*s  objection  {Die  physikalischen  Grund- 
lagen  der  Mechaniky  Leipsic,  1883,  p.  117),  that^  com- 
parison of  masses  satisfying  my  definition  can  be  ef- 
fected only  by  astronomical  means,  I  am  unable  to  ad- 
mit. The  expositions  on  pages  202,  218-221  amply 
refute  this.  Masses  mutually  produce  in  each  other 
accelerations  in  impact,  when  subject  to  electric  and 
magnetic  forces,  and  when  connected  by  a  string  on 
Atwood's  machine. 

My  definition  is,  the  outcome  of  an  endeavor  to 
establish  the  interdependence  of  phenomena  and  to  re- 
move all  metaphj'sical  obscurity,  without  accomplish- 
ing on  this  account  less  than  other  definitions  have 
done.  I  have  pursued  exactly  the  same  course  with 
respect  to  ideas  **  quantity  of  electricity "( ^^/-^^r ///V 
Grundbegriffe  der  Eiektrostatiky  Vortrag  gehaltcn  auf  der 
inter nationalen  eiektrischen  Ausstellung,  Vienna,  Septem- 
ber 4,  1883),  '*  temperature,"  ''quantity  of  heat"  {Zett- 
schrift  fiir  den  physikalischen  und  chemischen  Unterricht^ 
Berlin,  1888,  No.  I),  and  so  forth. 

III. 

(See  page  226.) 

My  views  concerning  physiological  time,  the  sensa- 
tion of  time,  and  partly  also  concerning  physical  time, 
I  have  expressed  elsewhere  (see  Beit  rage  zur  Analyse 
der  Empfindungeny  Jena,  Fischer,  1886,  pp.  103-in, 
166-168).  As  in  the*study  of  thermal  phenomena  we 
select  as  our  measure  of  temperature  an  arbitrarily 
chosen  volume,  which  varies  in  almost  parallel  correspon- 
dence with  our  sensation  of  heat,  and  which  is  not  liable 
to  the  uncontrollable  disturbances  of  our  organs  of  sen- 


APPENDIX,  511 

sation,  so,  for  similar  reasons^  we  select,  in  this  instance, 
as  our  measure  of  time,  an  arbitrarily  chosen  mot  ion  j  (the 
wangle  of  the  earth*s  rotation,  or  path  of  a  free  body,) 
which^jroceeds  in  almost  parallel  correspondence  with 
our  sensation  of  time.  Once  we  have  made  clear  to  our- 
selves that  we  are  concerned  only  with  the  ascertain- 
ment of  the  interdependence  of  phenomena,  as  I  pointed 
out  as  early  as  1 865  (  Ueber  den  Zeitsinn  des  Ohres,  Sitzungs- 
berichte  der  Wiener  Akademie)  and  1866  (Fichte's  Zeit- 
schrift  fUr  Philosophic^  all  metaphysical  obscurities  dis- 
appear. (Compare  J.  Epstein,  Die  logischen  Principien 
der  Zeiimessungy  Berlin,  1887.) 

IV. 
(See  page  238.) 

Of  the  treatises  which  have  appeared  since  1883  on 
the  law  of  inertia,  all  of  which  furnish  welcome  evidence 
of  a  heightened  interest  in  this  question,  I  can  here 
only  briefly  mention  that  of  Streintz  {Physikalische 
Grundlagen  der  Mechanik,  Leipsic,  1883)  and  that  of  L. 
Lange  {Die  gcschichtliche  Entwicklung  des  Bewegungs- 
begriffesy  Leipsic,  1886). 

The  expression  ** absolute  motion  of  translation" 
Streintz  correctly  pronounces  as  devoid  of  meaning  and 
consequently  declares  certain  analytical  deductions, 
to  which  he  refers,  superfluous.  On  the  other  hand, 
with  respect  to  rotation^  Streintz  accepts  Newton's  po- 
sition, that  absolute  rotation  can  be  distinguished  from 
relative  rotation.  In  this  point  of  view,  therefore,  one 
can  select  every  body  not  affected  with  absolute  rota- 
tion as  a  body  of  reference  for  the  expression  of  the 
law  of  inertia. 

I  cannot  share  this  view.  For  me,  only  relative 
motions  exist  {Er/ialtung  der  Arbeit^  p.  48 ;  Science  of 


512  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

Mechanics,  p.  229),  and  I  can  see,  in  this  regard,  no 
distinction  between  rotation  and  translation.    When  a 
body  moves  relatively  to  the  fixed  stars,  centrifugal 
forces  are  produced  ;  when  it  moves  relatively  to  some 
different  body,  and  not  relatively  to  the  fixed  stars,  no 
centrifugal  forces  are  produced.     I  have  no  objection 
to  calling  the  first  rotation   **  absolute"  rotation,  if  it 
be  remembered  that  nothing  is  meant  by  such  a  desig- 
nation except  relative  rotation  with  respect  to  the  fixed 
stars.  Can  we  fix  Newton's  bucket  of  water,  rotate  the 
fixed  stars,  and  then  prove  the  absence  of  centrifugal 
forces  ? 

The  experiment  is  impossible,  the  idea  is  meaning- 
less, for  the  two  cases  are  not,  in  sense-perception, 
distinguishable  from  each  other.  I  accordingly  regard 
these  two  cases  as  thexaw^  case  and  Newton's  dis- 
tinction as  an  illusion  {Science  of  Mechanics,  p.  232). 

But  the  statement  is  correct  that  it  is  possible  to 
find  one's  bearings  in  a  balloon  shrouded  in  fog,  by 
means  of  a  body  which  does  not  rotate  with  respect  to 
the  fixed  stars.  But  this  is  nothing  more  than  an  in- 
direct orientation  with  respect  to  the  fixed  stars ;  it  is 
a  mechanical,  substituted  for  an  optical,  orientation. 

I  wish  to  add  the  following  remarks  in  answer  to 
Streintz's  criticism  of  my  view.  My  opinion  is  not  to 
be  confounded  with  that  of  Euler  (Streintz,  pp.  7,  50), 
who,  as  Lange  has  clearly  shown,  never  arrived  at 
any  settled  and  intelligible  opinion  on  the  subject. 
Again,  I  never  assumed  that  remote  masses  only\  and  not 
near  ones,  determine  the  velocity  of  a  body  (Streintz,  p. 
7);  I  simply  spoke  of  an  influence  independent  of  dis- 
tance. In  the  light  of  my  expositions  at  pages  222- 
245,  the  unprejudiced  and  careful  reader  will  scarcely 
maintain  with  Streintz  (p.  50),  that  after  so  long  a  pe- 


APPENDIX,  513 

riod  of  time,  without  a  knowledge  of  Newton  and 
Euler,  I  have  only  been  led  to  views  which  these  in- 
quirers long  ago  held,  but  were  afterwards,  partly  by 
them  and  partly  by  others,  rejected.  Even  my  re- 
marks of  1872,  which  were  all  that  Streintz  knew,  can- 
not justify  this  criticism.  These  were,  for  good  rea- 
sons, concisely  stated,  but  they  are  by  no  means  so 
meagre  as  they  must  appear  to  one  who  knows  them 
only  from  Streintz's  criticism.  The  point  of  view 
which  Streintz  occupies,  I  at  that  time  expressly  re- 
jected. 

Lange's  treatise  is,  in  my  opinion,  one  of  the  best 
that  have  been  written  on  this  subject.  Its  methodical 
movement  wins  at  once  the  reader's  sympathy.  Its 
careful  analysis,  and  study,  from  historical  and  critical 
points  of  view,  of  the  concept  of  motion,  have  pro- 
duced, it  seems  to  me,  results  of  permanent  value.  I 
also  regard  its  clear  emphasis  and  apt  designation  of 
the  principle  of  ''particular  determination  "  as  a  point 
of  much  merit,  although  the  principle  itself,  as  well  as 
its  application,  is  not  new.  The  principle  is  really  at 
the  basis  of  all  measurement.  The  choice  of  the  unit 
of  measurement  is  convention  ;  the  number  of  measure- 
ment is  a  result  of  inquiry.  Every  natural  inquirer  who 
is  clearly  conscious  that  his  business  is  simply  the  in- 
vestigation of  the  interdependence  of  phenomena,  as  I 
formulated  the  point  at  issue  a  long  time  ago  (1865- 
1866),  employs  this  principle.  When,  for  example, 
{Mechanics,  p.  218  et  seqq.),  the  negative  inverse  ratio 
of  the  mutually  induced  accelerations  of  two  bodies  is 
called  the  mass-ratio  of  these  bodies,  this  is  a  conven- 
tion, e3?J)ressly  acknowledged  as  arbitrary ;  but  that 
these  ratios  are  independent  of  the  kind  and  of  the 
order  of  combination  of  the  bodies  is  2l  result  of  inquiry. 


514  THE  SCIENCE  OF  AfECHANICS. 

I  might  adduce  numerous  similar  instances  from  the 
theories  of  heat  and  electricity  as  well  as  from  other 
provinces.     Compare  Appendix,  II. 

Taking  it  in  its  simplest  and  most  perspicuous  form, 
the  law  of  inertia,  in  Lange's  view,  would  read  as  fol* 
lows: 

''Three  material  points  P^^  P^j  P^y  are  simulta- 
"neously  hurled  from  the  same  point  in  space  and 
**  then  left  to  themselves.  The  moment  we  are  certain 
''that  the  points  are  not  situated  in  the  same  straight 
"line,  we  join  each  separately  with  any  fourth  point  in 
"space,  Q.  These  lines  of  junction,  which  we  may 
"respectively  call  G^,  G^y  G^,  form,  at  their  point  of 
"  meeting,  a  three-faced  solid  angle.  If  now  we  make 
"this  solid  angle  preserve,  with  unaltered  rigidity, 
"  its  form,  and  constantly  determine  in  such  a  manner 
"its  position,  that  P^   shall  always  move  on  the  line 

'*  G^,  P^on  the  line  6^2 »  -^s  ^^  *^^  ^^^®  ^3»  these  lines 
"  may  be  regarded  as  the  axis  of  a  coordinate  or  iner- 
"  tial  system,  with  respect  to  which  every  other  ma- 
"terial  point,  left  to  itself,  will  move  in  a  straight  line. 
"The  spaces  described  by  the  free  points  in  the  paths 
"so  determined  will  be  proportional  to  one  another." 

A  system  of  coordinates  with  respect  to  which  three 
material  points  move  in  a  straight  line  is,  according  to 
Lange,  under  the  assumed  limitations,  a  simple  con- 
vention.  That  with  respect  to  such  a  system  also  a 
fourth  or  other  free  material  point  will  move  in  a 
straight  line,  and  that  the  paths  of  the  different  points 
will  all  be  proportional  to  one  another,  are  results  of 
inquiry. 

In  the  first  place,  we  shall  not  dispute  the  fact  that 
the  law  of  inertia  can  be  referred  to  such  a  system  of 
time  and  space  coordinates  and  expressed  in  this  form. 


APPENDIX,  515 

Such  an  expression  is  less  fit  than  Streintz's  for  prac- 
tical purposes,  but  on  the  other  hand,  is,  for  its  method- 
ical advantages,  more  attractive.  It  especially  appeals 
to  my  mind,  as  a  number  of  years  ago  I  was  engaged 
with  similar  attempts,  of  which  not  the  beginnings  but 
only  a  few  remnants  {Mechanics,  pp.  234-235)  are  left. 
I  abandoned  these  attempts  because  I  was  convinced 
that  we  only  apparently  evade  by  such  expressions  ref- 
erences to  the  fixed  stars  and  the  angular  rotation  of 
the  earth.  This,  in  my  opinion,  is  also  true  of  the 
forms  in  which  Streintz  and  Lange  express  the  law. 

In  point  of  fact,  it  was  precisely  by  the  considera- 
tion of  the  fixed  stars  and  the  rotation  of  the  earth 
that  we  arrived  at  a  knowledge  of  the  law  of  inertia  as 
it  at  present  stands,  and  without  these  foundations  we 
should  never  have  thought  of  the  explanations  here 
discussed  {Mechanics,  232-233).  The  consideration  of 
a  small  number  of  isolated  points,  to  the  exclusion  of 
the  rest  of  the  world,  is  in  my  judgment  inadmissible 
{Mechanics,  pp.  229-235). 

It  is  quite  questionable,  whether  a  fourth  material 
point,  left  to  itself,  would,  with  respect  to  Lange*s 
'*inertial  system,'*  uniformly  describe  a  straight  line,  if 
the  fixed  stars  were  absent,  or  not  invariable,  or  could 
not  be  regarded  with  sufficient  approximation  as  in- 
variable. 

The  most  natural  point  of  view  for  the  candid  in- 
quirer must  still  be,  to  regard  the  law  of  inertia  pri- 
marily as  a  tolerably  accurate  approximation,  to  refer 
it,  with  respect  to  space,  to  the  fixed  stars,  and,  with 
respect  to  time,  to  the  rotation  of  the  earth,  and  to 
await  the  correction,  or  more  precise  definition,  of  our 
knowledge  from  future  experience,  as  I  have  explamed 
on  page  237  of  this  book. 


5i6  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS,  \ 

I 

Upon  the  whole,  the  treatises  that  have  appeared 
since  1883  convince  me  that  my  expositions  have  not 
j'et  been  fully  considered,  and  I  have  therefore  left  the 
text  of  this  subject  unaltered. 

v. 

(See  page  485.) 

In  the  text  I  have  employed  the  term  *' cause"  in 
the  sense  in  which  it  is  ordinarily  used.  I  may  add 
that  with  Dr.  Carus,*  following  the  practice  of  the 
German  philosophers,  I  distinguish  ''cause,"  or  ^^-a/- 
grund,  from  Erkenntnissgrund.  I  also  agree  with  Dr. 
Carus  in  the  statement  that  '*  the  signification  of  cause 
and  effect  is  to  a  great  extent  arbitrary  and  depends 
much  upon  the  proper  tact  of  the  observer."  \ 

The  notion  of  cause  possesses  significance  only  as 
a  means  of  provisional  knowledge  or  orientation.  In 
any  exact  and  profound  investigation  of  an  event  the 
inquirer  must  regard  the  phenomena  as  dependent  on 
one  another  in  the  same  way  that  the  geometer  regards 
the  sides  and  angles  of  a  triangle  as  dependent  on  one 
another.  He  will  constantly  keep  before  his  mind,  in 
this  way,  all  the  conditions  of  fact. 

VI. 
(See  page  504.) 

The  principle  of  energy  is  only  briefly  treated  in 
the  text,  and  I  should  like  to  add  here  a  few  remarks 
on  the  following  four  treatises,  discussing  this  subject, 
which  have  appeared  since  1883  :  Die  physikalischen 
Grundsatze  der  elektrischen  Kraftiibertragung,  by  J.  Pop- 

*  See  his  Grnnd,  Ursacke  unti  ZwecJi;  R.  v.  Grurobkow,  Dresden,  iS8x, 
and  his  Fundamrntal  ProbUmx,  pp.  79-91,  Chicago  :  The  Open  Court  Publish- 
ing Co.,  1891. 

t  Fundamental  Problems,  p.  84. 


APPENDIX.  517 

per,  Vienna,  1883  ;  Die  Lehre  von  der  Energie^  by  G. 
Helm,  Leipsic,  1887  ;  Das  Princip  der  Erhaltung  der 
Energie,  by  M.  Planck,  Leipsic,  1887  ;  and  Das  Pro- 
blem der  Continuitdt  in  der  Mathematik  und  Mechanik, 
by  F.  A.  MuUer,  Marburg,  1886. 

The  independent  works  of  Popper  and  Helm  are, 
in  the  aim  they  pursue,  in  perfect  accord,  and  they 
quite  agree  in  this  respect  with  my  own  researches,  so 
much  so  in  fact  that  I  have  seldom  read  anything  that, 
without  the  obliteration  of  individual  differences,  ap- 
pealed in  an  equal  degree  to  my  mind.  These  two 
authors  especially  meet  in  their  attempt  to  enunciate 
a  general  science  of  energetics  ;  and  a  suggestion  of  this 
kind  is  also  found  in  a  note  to  my  treatise,  Ueber  die 
Erhaltung  der  Arbeit,  page  54. 

In  1872,  in  this  same  treatise  (pp.  42  et  seqq.),  I 
showed  that  our  belief  in  the  principle  of  excluded  per- 
petual motion  is  founded  on  a  more  general  belief  in 
the  unique  determination  of  one  group  of  (mechanical) 
elements,  afty .  .  .,  by  a  group  of  different  elements, 
xyz .  .  .  Planck's  remarks  at  pages  99,  133,  and  139 
of  his  treatise,  essentially  agree  with  this ;  they  are 
different  only  in  form.  Again,  I  have  repeatedly  re- 
marked that  all  forms  of  the  law  of  causality  spring 
from  subjective  impulses,  which  nature  is  by  no  means 
compelled  to  satisfy.  In  this  respect  my  conception  is 
allied  to  that  of  Popper  and  Helm. 

Planck  (pp.  21  et  seqq.,  135)  and  Helm  (p.  25  et 
seqq.)  meiltion  the  "metaphysical"  points  of  view  by 
which  Mayer  was  controlled,  and  both  remark  (Planck, 
p.  25  et  seqq.,  and  Helm,  p.  28)  that  also  Joule,  though 
there  are  no  direct  expressions  to  justify  the  conclusion, 
must  have  been  guided  by  similar  ideas.  To  this  last 
I  fully  assent. 


5X8  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

With  respect  to  the  so-called  **  metaphysical'' 
points  of  view  of  Mayer,  which,  according  to  Helm- 
holtz,  are  extolled  by  the  devotees  of  metaphysical 
speculation  as  Mayer's  highest  achievement,  but  which 
appear  to  Helmholtz  as  the  weakest  feature  of  his  ex- 
positions, I  have  the  following  remarks  to  make.  With 
maxims,  such  as  "Out  of  nothing,  nothing  comes/' 
**The  effect  is  equivalent  to  the  cause,"  and  so  forth, 
one  can  never  convince  another  of  anything.  How  little 
such  empty  maxims,  which  until  recently  were  admit- 
ted in  science,  can  accomplish,  I  have  illustrated  by 
examples  in  my  treatise  Die  Erhaltung  der  Arbeit,  But 
in  Mayer's  case  these  maxims  are,  in  my  judgment, 
not  weaknesses.  On  the  contrary,  they  are  with  him 
the  expression  of  a  powerful  instinctive  yearning,  as  yet 
unsettled  and  unclarified,  after  a  sound,  substantial 
conception  of  what  is  now  called  energy.  This  desire  I 
should  not  exactly  call  metaphysical.  We  now  kno'w 
that  Mayer  was  not  wanting  in  the  conceptual  power 
to  give  to  this  desire  clearness.  Mayer's  attitude  in 
this  point  was  in  no  respect  different  from  that  of  Gali- 
leo, Black,  Faraday,  and  other  great  inquirers,  although 
perhaps  many  were  more  taciturn  and  cautious  than  he. 

I  have  touched  upon  this  point  before  in  the  Bet- 
trdge  zur  Analyse  der  Empfindungen^  Jena,  1886,  p.  161 
et  seqq.  Aside  from  the  fact  that  I  do  not  share  the 
Kantian  point  of  view,  in  fact,  occupy  no  metaphysical 
point  of  view,  not  even  that  of  Berkeley,  as  hasty 
readers  of  my  last-mentioned  treatise  have  assumed, 
I  agree  with  F.  A.  Muller's  remarks  on  this  question 
(p.  104  et  seqq). 


CHRONOLOGICAL  TABLE 

OF  A  FFW 

EMINENT  INQUIRERS 

AND  OF 

THEIR    MORE    IMPORTANT    MECHANICAL   WORKS. 

A.RCHIMBDBS  (287-212  B.  €.)•  A  Complete  edition  of  his  works  was 
published,  with  the  commentaries  of  Eutocius,  at  Oxford,  in 
1792 ;  a  French  translation  by  F.  Peyrard  (Paris,  1808):  a  Ger- 
man translation  by  Ernst  Nizze  (Stralsund,  1824). 

Leonardo  da  Vinci  (1452-1519).  Leonardo's  scientific  manuscripts 
are  substantially  embodied  in  H.  Grothe's  work,  "Leonardo 
da  Vinci  als  Ingenieur  und  Philosoph  "  (Berlin,  1874). 

GuiDO  Ubaldi(o)  e  Marchionibus  Montis  (1545-1607).  Mecham- 
corum  Liber  (Pesaro,  1577). 

S.  Stbvinus  (1548-1620).  Begkinsehn  der  Weegkonst  (Leyden, 
1585);  Hypomnemata  Matkematica  (Leyden,  1608). 

Galilbo  (1564-1642).  Discorsi  e  dimostrazioni  matematicke  (Ley- 
den, 1638).  The  first  complete  edition  of  Galileo's  writings 
was  published  at  Florence  (i 842-1 856),  in  fifteen  volumes  8vo. 

Kbplbr  (1571-1630).  Astronomia  Nova  (Prague,  1609);  Harmo- 
nice  Mundi  (Linz,  1619);  SUreometria  Dolioriim  (L.\m,  161 5). 
Complete  edition  by  Frisch  (Frankfort,  1858). 

Marcus  Marci  (1595-1667).  De  Proportiotu  Afo/ us  (Prsigue,  1639). 

Dbscartes  (1596-1650).  Principia  PAi/(?s0p/n\r  (Xmsierdaim,  1644). 

RoBBRVAL  (1602-1675).  Sur  la  composition  des  mouvements.  Anc, 
Mint,  de  rAcad.  de  Paris.     T.  VI. 

Gubrickb  (1602- 1686).  Experimenta  Nova,  ut  Vocantur  Magde- 
burgica  (Amsterdam.  1672). 


1 


520  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS, 

Fbrmat  (1601-1665).     Varia  Opera  (Toulouse.  1679). 

ToRRicBixi  (1608-1647).     Opera  Geonietrica  (Florence,  1644). 

Wazxis  (16x6-1703).     Mechanica  Sive  de  Motu  (London,  1670). 

Mariottb  (1620-1684).     (Euvres  (Leyden,  1717). 

Pascal  (1623-1662).  R^cit  de  In  grande  experience  de  riquilibre 
dts  liqueurs  (Paris,  1648);  Traiti  de  riquilibre  des  liqueurs  et 
de  la  pesanteur  de  la  masse  de  Vair.     (Paris,  1662). 

BoYLX  (1627-1691).  Experimenta  Pkvsico  Mechanica  (London, 
1660). 

HUYGBNS  (1629- 1695).  A  Summary  Account  of  the  Laws  of  Men 
Hon.  Philos.  Trans.  1669;  Horologium  Oscillatorium  (Paris, 
1673);  Opuscula  Posthuma  (Leyden,  1703). 

Wrbn  (1632- 1 723).  Lex  Naturce  de  Collisione  Corporum,  Philos. 
Trans.  1669. 

Lami  (1640-17 1 5).  Nouvelle  manikre  de  dimontrer  les  principaux 
thioremes  des  iUmens  des  micaniques  (Paris,  1687). 

Nbwton  (1642  -1726).  Philosophic  Naturalis  Principia  Mathema- 
tica  (London,  1686). 

Lbibnitz  (1646-1716).  Acta  Eruditorum^  1686.  1695 ;  Leibnitzii 
et  Joh,  Bernoullii  Comer cium  Epistolicum  (Lausanne  and  Ge- 
neva, 1745)- 

Jambs  Bbrnoulli  (1654-1705).     Opera  Omnia  ^Geneva,  1744). 

Varignon  (1654-Z722).  Projet  d^une  nouvelle  mecanique  (Paris. 
1687). 

John  Bbrnoulli  (1667 -1748).  Acta  Erudit.  1693;  Opera  Omnia 
(Lausanne,  1742). 

Maupbrtuis  (1698-1759).  M^m.  de  VAcad.  de  Paris^  1740 ;  M^m. 
de  VAcad.  de  Berlin^  1745.  i747  \   (Euvres  (Paris,  1752). 

Maclaurin  (1698-1746).  A  Complete  System  of  Fluxions  (Edin- 
burgh, 1742). 

Daniel  Bbrnoulli  (1700-1782).  Comment.  Acad.  Petrop.,  T,  I. 
Hydrodynamica  (Strassburg,  1738). 

EuLER  (1707-1783).  Mechanica  siz'e  Mot  us  Scientia  (Petersburg:, 
1736) ;  Methodus  Inveniendi  Lineas  Curvas  (Lausanne.  1744). 


CHRONOLOGICAL   TABLE,  521 

Numerous  articles  in  the  volumes  of  the  Berlin  and  St.  Peters- 
burg academies. 

Clairaut  (1713-1765).      Thiorie  de  la  figure  de  la  terre  (Paris, 

1743). 
D'Alembbrt  (1717-1783).      TraiU  de  dynamique  (Paris,  1743). 

Lagrange  (1736-1813).  Essai  d^une  nouifelle  methode  pour  diter- 
miner  les  maxima  et  minima.  Misc.  Taurin.  1762  ;  Micanique 
analytique  (Paris,  1788). 

Laplace  (1749-1827).     Mecanique  cileste  (Paris,  1799). 

Fourier  (1768-1830).  Thiorie  analytique  de-la  chaleur  (Paris, 
1822). 

Gauss  (1777-1855).  De  Figura  Fluidorum  in  Statu  y^qui/ihrii. 
Comment.  Societ.  Gottin;^.,  1828;  Neues  Princip  det  Mechanik 
(Crelle's  Journal,  IV,  1829);  Intensitas  Vis  Magnetica  Terrestris 
ad  Mensuram  Absolutam  Revocata  (1833).  Complete  works 
(G5ttingen,  1863). 

PoiNSOT  (1777-1859).     Elements  de  statique  (Paris,  1804). 

PoNCELBT  (1788-1867).      Cours  de  mecanique  {Meiz,  1826). 

Belanger  (1790-1874).     Cours  de  micanique  (Paris,  1847). 

MoBi us  (179a  1867).     5/tf/i>&  (Leipsic.  1837). 

CoRiOLis  (1792- 1843).     Traiti  de  nUcanique  (Paris,  1829). 

C.  G.  J.  Jacobi  (1804-1851).  Vorlesungen  Uber  Dynamik,  heraus- 
gegeben  von  Clebsch  (Berlin,  1866). 

W.  R.  Hamilton  (1805-1865).  Lectures  on  Quaternions,  1853. — 
Essays. 

Grassmann  (1809- 1 877).     Ausdehnungslehre  (Leipsic,  1844). 


INDEX. 


Absolate,  space,  time.  etc.    (See  the 

nouns.) 
Absolate  units,  278,  284. 
Abstractions,  economical  character 

of,  483. 
Acceleration, Galileo  on,  i3iiet  seqq.; 

Newton  on,  238 ;   also  218,  230,  236, 

243.  H5' 
Action  and  reaction,  Newton  on,  198- 

201,  242. 

Action,  least,  principle  of,  364-380, 
454 ;  sphere  of,  383. 

Adaptation,  in  nature,4S2;  of  thoughts 
to  facts,  6. 

Adhesion  plates,  1x5. 

Aerostatics.     (See  air.) 

Affined,  166. 

Air,  expansive  force  of  isolated  por- 
tions of,  127 ;  quantitative  data  of, 
124;  weight  of,  113;  pressure  of, 
114  et  seqq. 

Air-pump,  experiments,  122  et  seqq.; 
the  mercurial,  123. 

Alcohol  and  water,  mixture  of,  384  et 
seq. 

Algebra,  economy  of,  486. 

Algebraical  mechanics,  4G6. 

All,  The,  necessity  of  its  considera- 
tion in  research,  23S1  461. 

Analytical  mechanics,  465-480. 

Analytic  method,  466. 

Animal  free  in  space,  290. 

Animistic  points  of  view  in  mechan- 
ics, 461  et  seq. 

Archimedes,  on  the  lever  and  the 
centre  of  gravity,  8-1 1 ;  critique  of 
his  deduction,  13-14 ;  illustration 
of  its  value,  10;  on  hydrostatics, 
86-88 ;  various  modes  of  deduction 


of  his  hydrostatic  principle,  104; 
illustration  of  his  principle,  106. 

Areas,  the  law  of  the  conservation  of, 
293-305. 

Areometer,  effect  of  particles  sus- 
pended in  liquids  on,  208. 

Artifices,  mental,  492  et  seqq. 

Assyrian  monuments,  i. 

Atmosphere.     (See  Air.) 

Atoms,  mental  artifices,  492. 

Attraction,  246. 

Atwood'  s  machine,  149. 

Avenarius,  R.,  ix. 

Babbage,  on  calculating  machines. 
488. 

Babo,  von,  apparatus  of,  150. 

Ballistic  pendulum,  328. 

Balls,  elastic,  symbolising  pressures 
in  liquids,  419. 

Bandbox,  rotation  of,  301. 

Barometer,  height  of  mountains  de- 
termined by,  XI 5,  X17. 

Base,  pressure  of  liquids  on,  90,  99. 

Belanger,  on  impulse,  271. 

Berkeley,  518. 

Bernoulli,  Daniel,  his  geometrical 
demonstration  of  the  parallelo- 
gram of  forces,  40-42 ;  criticism  of 
Bernoulli's  demonstration,  42-46; 
on  the  law  of  areas,  293 ;  on  the 
principle  of  vis  viva,  343,  348 ;  on 
the  velocity  of  liquid  efflux,  403;  his 
hydrodynamic  principle,4o8;  on  the 
parallelism  of  strata,  409;  his  dis- 
tinction of  hydrostatic  and  hydro- 
dynamic  pressure,  413. 

Bernoulli,  James,  on  the  catenary, 
74 ;  on  the  centre  of  oscillation,  33X 


524 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 


e(  seq.;  on  the  brachistochrone, 
426;  on  the  isoperiinetrical  prob- 
lems,  428  et  seq.;  his  character,  428 ; 
his  quarrel  with  John,  431 ;  his  Pro- 
gramma,  430. 

Bernoulli,  John,  his  generalisation  of 
the  principle  of  virtual  velocities. 
56;  on  the  catenary,  74;  on  centre 
of  oscillation,  333  335;  on  the  prin- 
ciple of  vit  viva,  343 ;  on  the  anal- 
ogies between  motions  of  masses 
and  light, 372;  his  liquid  pendulum, 
410 ;  on  the  brachistochrone,  425  et 
seqq.;  his  character,  427 ;  his  quar- 
rel with  James,  431 ;  his  solution  of 
the  isoperimetrical  problem,  431. 

Black,  his  discovery  of  carbonic  acid 
gas,  124. 

Boat  in  motion,  Huygens's  fiction  of 

a,  315.  325- 
Body,  definition  of,  506. 
Bolyai,  493. 
Bomb,  a  bursting,  293. 
Bouguer,  on  the  figure  of  the  earth, 

395- 

Boyle,  his  law,  125  et  seq.;  his  inves- 
tigations in  aerostatics,  123. 

Brachistochrone,  problem  of  the,  423 
et  seqq. 

Brahe,  Tycho,  on  planetary  motion, 
187. 

Bruno.Giordano,  his  martyrdom,  446. 

Bubbles,  392. 

Bucket  of  water,  Newton's  rotating, 
227,  232,  512. 

Cabala,  489. 

Calculating  machines,  488. 

Calculus,  difterential,  424 ;  of  varia- 
tions, 436  et  seqq. 

Canal,  fluid,  equilibrium  of,  396  et 
seqq. 

Cannon  and  projectile,  motion  of, 291. 

Canton,on  compressibility  of  liquids, 
92. 

Carnot.  his  performances,  501 ;  his 
formula,  327. 

Carus,  P.,  on  cause,  516. 

Catenary,  The,  74,  379,  425. 

Cauchy,  47. 

Causality,  483  et  seqq.;  502. 


Cause  and  effect,  economical  char- 
acter of  the  ideas,  483 :  equivalence 
off  502,  503;  Mach  on,  516;  Cams 
on,  516. 

Causes,  efficient  and  final,  368. 

Cavendish,  his  discovery  of  hydro- 
gen, 124. 

Cells  of  the  honeycomb,  453. 

Centimetre-gramme-second  system. 
2B5. 

Central,  centrifugal,  and  centripetal 
force.    (See  Force.) 

Centre  of  gravity,  14  et  seqq.;  descent 
of,  32 ;  descent  and  ascent  of,  174 
et  seqq.,  408;  the  law  of  the  con* 
servation  of  the,  287-303. 

Centre  of  gyration,  334. 

Centre  of  oscillation,  173  et  seqq.,  331 
-335 ;  Mersenne,  Descartes,  and 
Huygens  on,  174  et  seqq.;  relations 
of,  to  centre  of  gravity,  180-185; 
convertibility  of,  with  point  of  sus- 
pension, 186. 

Centre  of  percussion,  327. 

Chain,  Stevin's  endless,  25  et  seqq., 
500 ;  motion  of,  on  inclined  plane. 

347. 

Change,  unrelated,  504. 

Character,  an  ideal  universal,  481. 

Chinese  language,  482. 

Church,  conflict  of  science  and,  446. 

Circular  motion,  law  of,  x6o,  161. 

Clairaut,  on  vis  viva,  work,  etc.,  348 ; 
on  the  figure  of  the  earth,  395  ;  on 
liquid  equilibrium,  396  et  seq.;  on 
level  surfaces,  etc.,  398. 

Classes  and  trades,  the  function  of  in 
the  development  of  science,  4. 

Clausius,  497,  499,  301. 

Coefficients,  indeterminate,  La- 
grange' s,  471  et  seq. 

Collision  of  bodies.    (See  Impact 

Colors,  analysis  of.  481. 

Column,  rest  of  a  heavy,  258. 

Commandinus,  87. 

Communication,  the  economy  of,  78. 

Comparative  physics,   necessity    of. 

498. 
Component  of  force,  34. 
Composition  of  forces,  see  Forces  * 

Gauss's  principle  and  the,  364. 


INDEX. 


525 


Compression  of  liquids  and  |{a8cs,407. 

Conrad  us,  Balthasar,  308. 

Conservation,  of  energy,  499  et  seq., 
516  et  seqq.;  of  quantity  of  motion, 
Descartes  and  Leibnits  on,  372,  274; 
purpose  of  the  ideas  of.  504. 

Conservation  of  momentum,  of  the 
centre  of  gravity,  and  of  areas, laws 
of  the,  287-305 ;  these  laws,  the  ex- 
pression of  the  laws  of  action  and 
reaction  and  inertia,  303. 

Conservation  of  momentum  and  vis 
viva  interpreted,  326  et  seq. 

Constancy  of  quantity  of  matter,  mo- 
tion, and  energy,  theological  basis 
of,  456. 

Constraint.  333,  352 ;  least,  principle 

of.  350-364. 
Continuity,  the  principle  of,  140,  490 

et  seqq. 
Continuum,  physico-mechanical,  109. 
Coordinates,  forces  a  function  of,  397 

see  Force-function. 
Copernicus,  457,  232. 
Coriolis,  on  vis  viva  and  work,  272. 
Counter-phenomena,  303. 
Counter-work,  363,  366. 
Counting,  economy  of,  486. 
Courtivron,  his  law  of  equilibrium, 

73. 
Ctesibtus,  his  air-gun,  iia 

Currents,  oceanic,  302. 

Curtius  Rufus,  210. 

Curve-eleuients,  variation  of,  432. 

Curves,  roixima  and  minima  of,  429. 

Cycloids,  X43,  186,  379,  427. 

Cylinder,  double,  on  a  horizontal  sur- 
face, 60;  rolling  on  an  inclined 
plane.  345. 

Cylinders,  axal,  symbolising  the  rela- 
tions of  the  centres  of  gravity  and 
oscillation,  183. 

D'Alembert,  his  settlement  of  the 
dispute  concerning  the  measure  of 
force,  149,  276;  bis  principle,  331- 

343- 
D'Arcy,  on  the  law  of  areas,  293. 
Darwin,  his  theories,  452,  459. 
Declination  from  free  motion,  352- 

356. 


Deductive  development  of  science, 
421. 

Demonstration,  the  mania  for,  18, 82 ; 
artificial,  82. 

Departure  from  free  motion,  355. 

Derived  units,  278. 

Descartes,  on  the  measure  of  force, 
148,  250,  270,  272-276 ;  on  quantity  of 
motion,  conservation  of  momen- 
tum, etc.,  272  et  seqq.;  character  of 
his  physical  inquiries,  273 ;  his  me- 
chanical ideas,  25a 

Descent,  on  inclined  planes,  134  et 
seqq.,  law  of,  137 ;  in  chords  of  cir- 
cles, 138;  vertical,  motion  of,  treated 
by  Hamilton's  principle,383;  quick- 
est, curve  of.  426;  ofcentre  of  grav- 
ity. 52,  174  et  seqq.,  408. 

Description, a  fundamental  feature  of 
science,  5. 

Design  evidences  of,  in  nature,  452. 

Determinants  economy  of,  487. 

Determinative  factor*  of  physical 
processes  76. 

Differences,  of  quantities  their  rOle 
in  nature,  236 ;  of  velocities,  325. 

Differential  calculus,  424. 

Differential  laws,  255,  461. 

Dimensions,  theory  of,  279. 

Dioptrics,  Gauss's,  economy  of,  489. 

Disillusionment,  due  to  insight,  77. 

DQhring,  iz,  352. 

Dynamics,  the  development  of  the 
principles  of,  128-235  '•  retrospect  of 
the  development  of,  245-255;  found- 
ed by  Galileo,  128 ;  proposed  new 
foundations  for,  243 ;  chief  results 
of  the  development  of,  245,  246; 
analytical,  founded  by  Lagrange  on 
the  principle  of  virtual  velocities, 
467. 

Earth,  figure  of,  395  et  seqq. 

Economical  character  of  analytical 
mechanics,  48a 

Economy  of  description,  5. 

Economy  in  nature,  459. 

Economy  of  science,  481  -494. 

Economy  of  thought,  the  basts  and 
essence  of  science,  viii,  6,  481 ;  of 
language,  481 ;  of  all  ideas,  482;  of 


526 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 


the  ideas  cause  and  etfect,  484  ;  of 
the  laws  of  nature,  485 ;  of  the  law 
of  refraction,  485 ;  of  mathematics, 
486;  of  determinants,  487 ;  of  cal- 
culatinf(  machines,  488 ;  of  Gauss's 
dioptrics,  moment  of  inertia,  force- 
function.  489. 

Efflux,  velocity  of  liquid,  402  et  seq. 

Egyptian  monuments,  i. 

Eighteenth  century,  character  of, 
458. 

Elastic  bodies,  3x5,  317,  320. 

Elastic  rod,  vibrations  of.  490. 

Elasticity,  theory  of,  258,  259,  490. 

Electricity,  revision  of  the  theory  of, 
496. 

Electromotor,  Page's,  292 ;  motion  of 
a  free,  296  et  seq. 

Elementary  laws,  see  Differential 
laws. 

Ellipsoid,  trtaxal,  73 ;  of  inertia,  186; 
central,  186. 

Encyclopaedists,  French,  463. 

Energetics,  the  science  of,  5x7. 

Energy,  Galileo's  use  of  the  word, 
271 ;  conservation  of,  499  et  seq., 
potential  and  kinetic,  272,  499;  prin- 
ciple of,  516  et  seqq. 

Enlightenment,  the  age  of,  458. 

Epstein,  511. 

Equations,  of  motion,  34a;  of  me- 
chanics, fundamental,  270. 

Equilibrium,  the  decisive  conditions 
of,  S3 ;  dependence  of,  on  a  maxi- 
mum or  minimum  of  work,  69 ;  sta- 
ble, unstable,  mixed,  and  neutral 
equilibrium,  70-71 ;  treated  by 
Gauss's  principle,  355;  figures  of. 
393;  liquid,  conditions  of,  386  et 
seqq. 

Equipotential  surfaces,  see  Level 
surfaces. 

Ergal,  499. 

Error,  our  liability  to  in  the  recon- 
struction of  facts,  79. 

Euler,  on  the  "  loi  de  repos,"  68 ;  on 
moment  of  inertia,  179,  182, 186 ;  on 
the  law  of  areas,  293 ;  his  form  of 
D'Alembert's  principle,  337 ;  on  vis 
viva,  348 :  on  the  principle  of  least 
action,  3G8 ;  on  the  isoperimetrical 


problems  and  the  calculus  of  vajia- 
tions,  433  et  seqq.;  bis  theological 
proclivities,  449,  455 ;  his  contribu- 
tions to  analytical  mechanics,  466^ 

Exchange  of  velocities  in  impact,  315. 

Experience,  i  et  seq.,  481,  49a 

Explanation,  6. 

Extravagance  in  nature,  4591 

Facts  and  hypotheses,  494,  496,  498. 

Fall  of  bodies,  early  views  of,  xaS; 
investigation  of  the  laws  of.  130  et 
seq.;  see  Descent. 

Falling,  sensation  of,  906. 

Falling  bodies,  laws  of,  accident  of 
their  form,  247  et  seq ;  see  Descent. 

Faraday,  503 ;  his  lecture-experiment 
on  gases,  124. 

Feelings,  the  attempt  to  explain  them 
by  motions,  506. 

Fermat,  on  the  method  of  tai^ents, 
423. 

Fetishism,  in  modem  ideas,  463. 

Fiction  of  a  boat  in  motion,  Huy- 
gens's.  315,  325. 

Figure  of  the  earth,  395  et  seqq. 

Films,  liquid,  386,  392  et  seq. 

Flow,  lines  of,  400;  of  liquids,  4x6  et 
seq. 

Fluids,  the  principles  of  statics  ap- 
plied to,  86-110;  see  Liquids. 

Fluid  hypotheses,  496. 

Force,  moment  of,  37 ;  the  experien- 
tial nature  of,  42-44 ;  conception  of, 
in  statics,  84 ;  general  attributes  of, 
8s ;  the  Galilean  notion  of,  142 ;  dis- 
pute concerning  the  measure  of, 
148,  250,  270,  274-276;  centrifugal 
and  centripetal,  is8  et  seqq.;  New- 
ton on,  192,  197,  238,  239;  moving, 
203,  243 ;  resident,  impressed,  cen- 
tripetal, accelerative,  moving.  338, 
239 ;  the  Newtonian  measure  of,  acq, 
239t  276 ;  lines  of,  40a 

Force-function,  398  et  seqq.,  479, 489; 
Hamilton  on,  3SO. 

Force-relations,  character  of,  237. 

Forces,  the  parallelogram  of  3a,  33-48, 
243;  principle  of  the  composition 
and  resolution  of,  33-48, 197  et  seq  ; 
triangle  of,  108 ;  mutual  independ- 


INDEX. 


527 


ence  of,  154 ;  livinKt  see  Vis  viva  ; 
Newton  on  the  paralleloKrain  of, 
X93i  197;  impressed,  equilibrated.ef- 
fective,  gained  and  lost,  336;  mole- 
cular, 384  et  seqq.;  functions  of  co- 
ordinates, 397,  4C2 ;  central,  397. 

Formal  development  of  science,  421. 

Formulas,  mechanical,  269-186. 

Foucault  and  Toepler.optical  method 
of,  125. 

Foucault' s  pendulum,  302. 

Fourier,  on  dimensions,  279. 

Free  rigid  body,  rotation  of,  295. 

Free  systems,  mutual  action  of,  287. 

Friction,  of  minute  bodies  in  liquids, 
208 ;  motion  of  liquids  under,  4x6  et 
seq. 

Functions,  mathematical,  their  office 
in  science,  492. 

Fundamental  equations  of  mechan- 
ics, 27a 

Funicular  machine,  32. 

Funnel,  plunged  in  water,  412 ;  rotat- 
ing liquid  in,  303. 

"Galileo,"  name  for  unit  of  accel- 
eration, 285. 

Galileo,  his  dynamical  achievements, 
128-155;  his  deduction  of  the  law 
of  the  lever,  12;  his  explanation  of 
the  inclined  plane  by  the  lever,  23  ; 
his  recognition  of  the  principle  of 
virtual  velocities,  51;  his  researches 
in  hydrostatics,  90;  his  theory  of 
the  vacuum,  112  et  seq.;  his  discov- 
ery of  the  laws  of  falling  bodies, 
130  et  seqq.;  his  clock^  133;  char- 
acter of  his  inquiries,  140 ;  his  foun- 
dation of  the  law  of  inertia,  143 ; 
on  the  notion  of  acceleration,  145 ; 
tabular  presentment  of  his  discov- 
eries, 147 ;  on  the  pendulum  and  the 
motion  of  projectiles,  152  et  seqq.; 
founds  dynamics,  128;  his  pendu- 
lum, 162 ;  his  reasoning  on  the  laws 
of  falling  bodies,  230,  131, 247 ;  his 
favorite  concepts,  250 ;  on  impact, 
308-312;  his  struggle  with  the 
church,  446 ;  on  the  strength  of  ma- 
terials, 451;  does  not  mingle  science 
with  theology,  457 ;  on  inertia,  509. 


Gaseous  bodies,  the  principles  of 
statics  applied  to,  1 10-127. 

Gases,  flow  of,  405 ;  compression  of, 
407. 

Gauss,  his  view  of  the  principle  of 
virtual  velocities,  76 ;  on  absolute 
units,  278;  his  principle  of  least 
constraint,  350-364;  on  the  statics 
of  liquids,  J90;  his  dioptrics,  489. 

Gilbert,  462. 

Grassi,  94. 

Grassmann,  480. 

Gravitation,  universal,  190. 

Gravitational  system  of  measures, 
284-286U 

Gravity,  centre  of.    See  Centre  of 
gravity. 

Green' s  Theorem,  109. 

Guericke,  his  theological  specula- 
tions, 448 ;  his  experiments  in  aero- 
statics, 117  et  seqq.;  his  notion  of 
air,  1x8;  his  air-pump,  x2o;  his  air- 
gun,  123. 

Gyration,  centre  of,  334. 

Halley,  448. 

Hamilton,  on  force-function,  350. 

Hamilton's  principle,  380-384,  48a 

Heat,  revision  of  the  theory  of,  496. 

Helm,  517. 

Hehnholts,  viii;  on  the  conservation 
of  energy,  499,  501,  518. 

Hemispheres,  the  Magdeburg,  122. 

Hermann,  emplojrs  a  form  of  D'  Alem- 
bert's  principle,  337;  on  motion  in 
a  resisting  medium,  435. 

Hero,  his  fountain,  4x1 ;  on  the  mo- 
tion of  light,  422 ;  on  maxima  and 
minima,  451. 

Hiero,  86. 

Hipp,  chronoscope  of,  151. 

Hollow  space,  liquids  enclosing,  392. 

Homogenous,  279. 

Hopital,  L*,  on  the  centre  of  oscilla- 
tion, 33X ;  on  the  brachistochrone, 
4^6. 

Horror  vaeui^  xi2. 

Hume,  on  causality,  484. 

Huygens,dynamical  achievements  of, 
155- X87;  his  deduction  of  the  law 
of  the  lever,  X5-16;  criticism  of  his 


528 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 


deduction,  17-18;  his  rank  aa  an 
inquirer,  155 ;  character  of  hta  re- 
aearchea,  156  et  seq.;  on  centrifugal 
and  ceniripetal  force,  158  et  seqq.; 
his  experiment  with  light  balls  in 
rotating  fluids,  162;  on  the  pendu- 
lum and  oscillatory  motion,  i6a  et 
seqq.;  on  the  centre  of  oscillation, 
173  et  seq.;  his  principle  of  the  de- 
scent and  rise  of  the  centre  of  grav- 
ity, 274 ;  his  lesser  investigations, 
x86;  his  crowning  achievement,  187; 
his  favorite  concepts,  aji ;  on  im- 
pact, 313-327;  on  the  principle  of 
visviva^  343,  348;  on  the  figure  of 
the  earth,  395 ;  his  optical  re- 
searches, 423 ;  does  not  mingle  sci- 
ence and  theology,  457. 

Hydraulic  ram,  Montgolfier's,  41X. 

Hydrodynamic  pressure,  413. 

Hydrodynamics,  402-420. 

Hydrostatic  pressure,  413. 

Hydrostatics,  384-402. 

Hypotheses  and  facts,  494. 

Inclined  plane,  the  principle  of  the, 
24-33;  Galileo's  deduction  of  its 
laws,  131 ;  descent  on,  354 ;  movable 
on  rollers,  357  et  seq. 

Indeterminate   coefficients,  La- 
grange's, 471  et  seq. 

Inelastic  bodies,  317,  318. 

Inertia,  history  of  the  law  of,  141, 143, 
509,  SIX  et  seqq.;  moment  of,  X79, 
182,  x86,  489 ;  bodies  with  variable 
moments  of,  302 ;  law  of,  critically 
elucidated,  232,  238;  Newton  on, 
238,  243. 

Inertial  system,  515. 

Impact,  the  laws  of,  305-330;  force  of. 
compared  with  pressure,  3x2;  in 
the  Newtonian  view,  317  et  seqq.; 
oblique,  327;  Maupertuis's  treat- 
ment of,  365. 

Impetus,  275. 

Impulse,  27X. 

Inquirers,  the  great,  character  and 
value  of  their  performances,  7; 
their  different  tasks,  76 ;  their  atti- 
tude towards  religion,  457. 

Inquiry,  typical  modes  of,  3x7. 


Instinct,  mechanical,  importance  of, 
304. 

Instinctive  knowledge,  its  cogenqr. 
origin,  and  character,  x,  26-2&,  83. 

Instincts,  our  animal,  463. 

Instruction,  various  methods  of,  5. 

Integral  laws,  255,  46X. 

Intelligence,  conception  of, in  nature, 
461. 

Interdependence  of  the  facts  of  na- 
ture, 502  et  passim. 

Internal  forces,  action  of,  on  free  srs- 
leins,  289,  295. 

International  language,  48X. 

Isoperimetrical  problems,  42x1446; 
Euler's  classification  of,  433. 

Isothermal  surfaces,  400. 

Jacobi,  76,  38X,  459;  on  principle  of 

least  action,  371. 
Jellett,  on  the  calculus  of  variations, 

437  et  seq. 
Jolly,  iz. 
Joule,  50X. 
Judgments,  economical  character  of 

all,  483. 

Kant,  on  causality,  484. 

Kater,  186. 

Kepler,  his  laws  of  planetary  motion, 
X87 ;  possibility  of  his  discovery  of 
the  laws  of  falling  bodies,  248;  on 
maxima  and  minima,  423 ;  on  astrol- 
ogy, 463. 

Kilogramme,  28x. 

Kilogramme-metre,  272. 

Kinetic  energy,  272,  499. 

Kirchhoff,  viii,  38X. 

Knowledge,  instinctive,  x,  26-28,  85; 
the  communication  of,  the  founda- 
tion of  science,  4  ;  the  nature  of,  S  \ 
the  necessary  and  sufficient  condi- 
tions of,  10. 

KOnig,  on  the  cells  of  the  honeycomb, 

453- 

Laborde,  apparatus  of,  xja 

Lagrange,  his  deduction  of  the  law  of 
the  lever,  13;  his  deduction  of  the 
principle  of  virtual  velocities,  65- 
67 ;  criticism  of  this  last  deductioHi 


INDEX. 


529 


67-68;  his  form  of  D'Alembert's 
principle,  337 ;  on  vis  viva,  349 ;  on 
the  principle  of  least  action,  371 ; 
on  the  calculus  of  variations,  436  et 
seq.;  emancipates  physics  from  the- 
ology,  457;  his  analytical  mechan- 
ics, ix,  466;  his  indeterminate  co- 
efficients. 471  et  seq. 
Lami,  on  the  composition  of  forces, 

36. 

Lange  51X  et  seq. 

Language,  economical  character  of, 
481 ;  possibility  of  a  universal,  48a ; 
the  Chinese,  482. 

Laplace,  463. 

Lateral  pressure,  103. 

Laws  of  nature,  502. 

Laws,  rules  for  the  mental  recon- 
struction of  facts,  83-84,  485. 

Least  action,  principle  of,  364-380; 
its  theological  kernel,  454. 

Least  constraint,  principle  of,  350- 

364. 

Leibnitz,  on  the  measure  of  force, 
148.  ajo,  270.  274-276 ;  on  quantity  of 
motion,  274 ;  on  the  motion  of  light, 
425,  454;  on  the  brachistochrone, 
426 ;  as  a  theologian,  449. 

Level  surfaces,  98,  398  et  seqq. 

Lever,  the  principle  of  the,  8-25 ;  "  po- 
tential, '  20 ;  application  of  its  prin- 
ciples to  the  explanation  of  the 
other  machines,  22;  its  law  deduced 
by  Newton's  principles,  263-^267; 
conditions  of  its  rigidity,  96;  Mau- 
pertuis's  treatment  of,  366. 

Libraries,  stored  up  experience,  481. 

Light,  motion  of,  422,  424,  426;  Mau- 
pertuis  on  motion  of,  367 ;  motion 
of,  in  refracting  media,  374-376,  377- 
379 ;  its  minimal  action  explained, 

459- 
LindelOf,  437. 

Lippich,  apparatus  of,  xja 

Liquid  efflux,  velocity  of,  402. 

Liquid-head,  403,  416. 

Liquid,  rotating  in  a  funnel,  303. 

Liquids,  the  statics  of,  86-izo;  the 
dynamics  of,  402-420 ;  fundamental 
properties  of,  91 ;  compressibility 
of,  92 ;  equilibrium  of,  subjected  to 


gravity,  96;  immersed  in  liquids, 
pressure  of,  105 ;  lateral  pressure  of, 
103 ;  weightless,  384  et  seqq.;  com- 
pression of,  407 ;  soniferous,  vibra- 
tions of,  407 ;  mobile,  407 ;  motion 
of  viscous,  416. 

Living  power,  272. 

Lobatschewsky,  493. 

Locomotive,  oscillations  of  the  body 
of,  292. 

Luther,  463. 

Machines,  the  simple,  8  et  seqq. 

Maclaurin  on  the  cells  of  the  honey- 
comb, 453;  his  contributions  to  ana- 
lytical mechanics,  466. 

Magnus,  Valerianus,  1x7. 

Manometer,  statical,  123. 

Maraldi,  on  the  honeycomb,  453. 

Marci,  Marcus,  305-308. 

Mariotte,  his  law,  X2S  ;  his  apparatus 
and  experiments,  126  et  seq.;  on  im- 
pact, 313. 

Mass-areas,  295. 

Mass,  criticism  of  the  concept  of,  216 
-222 ;  Newton  on,  192,  194,  217,  238, 
251 ;  John  Bernoulli  on,  251 ;  as  a 
physical  property,  194;  distin- 
guished from  weight,  195;  measura- 
ble by  weight,  195,  220;  scientific 
definition  of,  218  et  seq.,  243,  510; 
involves  principle  of  reaction,  220. 

Mass,  motion  of  a,  in  principle  of 
least  action,  372. 

Mathematics,  function  of,  77. 

Matter,  quantity  of,  216,  238. 

Maupertuis,  his  loi  dt  re^s,  68  et 
seq.;  on  the  principle  of  least  ac- 
tion, 364,  368;  his  theological  pro- 
clivities, 454. 

Maxima  and  minima,  368  et  seqq. 
problems  of,  422  et  seqq. 

Maximal    and    minimal  effects,  ex 
planation  of,  460. 

Maxims,  scholastic,  143. 

Maxwell,  271. 

Mayer,  J.  R.,  on  work,  249,  503,  518; 
his  physical  achievements,  501. 

Measures,  see  Units. 

Mechanical,  experiences,  i ;  knowl- 
edge of  antiquity,  1-3;  phenomena. 


530 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 


purely,  493  et  seq.:  theory  of  na- 
ture, its  untenability,  49s  et  seq.; 
phenomena  not  fundamental,  496  ; 
conception  of  the  world,  artificiality 
of,  496. 

Mechanics,  the  science  of,  i;  earliest 
researches  in,  8 ;  extended  applica- 
tion of  the  principles  of,  and  de- 
ductivedevelopment  of  the  science, 
255-420;  the  formula  and  units  of. 
269-286;  character  of  the  principles 
of,  237;  form  of  its  principles 
mainly  of  historical  and  accidental 
origin,  247  et  seq.;  tfieological,  ani- 
mistic, and  mystical  points  of  view 
in,  446-465 ;  fundamental  equations 
of,  270-276 ;  new  transformation  of, 
4?o;  relations  of,  to  other  depart- 
ments of  knowledge,  495-307 ;  rela- 
tions of,  to  physics,  495-504;  rela- 
tions of,  to  physiology,  504-507;  an 
aspect,  not  the  foundation  of  the 
world,  496,  3'7 ;  analytical,  465-480; 
Newton's  geometrical,  465. 

Mcdiinn,  motion-determinative,  hy- 
pothesis of,  in  space,  230;  resisting, 
motion  in,  435. 

Memory,  481, 488. 

Mensbrugghe,  Van  der,  on  liquid 
films,  386. 

Mental  arti  fices,  492  et  seqq. 

Mercurial  air-pump,  125. 

Merscnne,  Z14,  174. 

Method  of  tangents,  423. 

Metre,  280. 

Mimicking,  of  facts  in  thought,  see 
Reproduction. 

Minima,  see  Maxima. 

Minimum  of  superficial  area,  387. 

Mixed  equilibrium,  70-71. 

Mobile  liquids,  407. 

MObius,  372,  480. 

Models,  mental,  492. 

Molecular  forces,  384  et  seqq. 

Moment,  statical,  14  ;  of  force,  37;  of 
inertia,  179,  182.  \^\ 

Moments,  virtual,  57. 

Momentum,  241,  244.  271 ;  law  of  the 
conservation  of,  288 ;  conservation 
of,  interpreted,  326. 

Monistic  philosophy,  the,  465. 


Montgolfier's  hydranlic  ram,  411. 

Moon,  its  acceleration  towards  the 
earth,  190;  length  of  its  day  in- 
creased to  a  month,  299. 

Morin,  apparatus  of,  150L 

Motion,  Newton's  laws  of,  227,241; 
quantity  of,  238,  271  et  seqq.;  equa- 
tions of.  342,  371 ;  circular,  laws  of, 
158  et  seqq.;  uniformly  accelerated, 
132;  relative  and  absolute,  %rj  et 
seqq..  511  et  seq. 

Motivation,  law  of,  484. 

MQller,  F.  A.,  517. 

Mystical  points  of  view  in  mechanics, 

456. 
Mysticism  in  science.  482. 
Mythology,  mechanical.  464. 

Napier,  his  theological  inclinations, 

447. 
Nature,  laws  of,  503. 

Necessity,  484,  485. 

Neumann,  C,  355. 

Neutral  equilibrium,  70-71. 

Newton,his  dynamical  achievements, 
187-201 ;  his  views  of  time,  space, 
and    motion,    222-238;    synoptical 
critique  of  his  enunciations,  2jS- 
245;  scope  of  his  principles,  256-269; 
enunciates  the  principle  of  the  par- 
allelogram of  forces,  36 ;  his  prin- 
ciple of  similitude,  165  et  seq.;  his 
discovery  of  universal  gravitation, 
its  character,  and  its  law,  x88  et 
seqq.;   effect  of  this  discovery  on 
mechanics,    191 ;    his    mechanical 
discoveries  192 ;   his  rtgultK  philo- 
tophandi^  193;    his  idea  of  force, 
193 ;    his  concept  of  mass,  194  et 
seqq.;  on  the  composition  of  forces, 
197;  on  action  and  reaction,  198; 
defects  and  merits  of  his  doctrines, 
20X,  244 ;  on  the  tides,  209  et  seq-; 
his  definitions,  laws,  and  corolla- 
ries, 238-242 ;  his  water-pendulum, 
409;  his  theological  speculations, 
448 ;  the  economy  and  wealth  of  bis 
ideas,  269 ;  his  laws  and  definitions, 
proposed  substitutes  for,  243;  his 
favorite  concepts,  251 ;  on  the  figure 
of  the  earth,  395 ;  does  not  mingle 


INDEX, 


531 


theology  with  science,  457 ;  on  the 
brachistochrone,  436. 
Numbers,  486. 

Observation,  82. 

Occasionalism,  the  doctrine  of,  449. 

Oersted,  93. 

Oil,  use  of,  in  Plateau's  experiments, 

384  et  seq. 
Oscillation,  centre  of,  331-335. 
Oscillatory  motion,  162  et  seqq. 

Pagan  ideas  in  modem  life,  462. 

Page' s  electromotor,  992. 

Pappus,  422 ;  on  maxima  ard  min- 
ima. 4SI. 

Parallelism  of  strata,  409. 

Parallelogram  of  forces,  see  Forces. 

Particular  determination,  principle 
of,  5x3- 

Pascal,  his  application  of  the  prin- 
ciple of  virtual  velocities  to  the 
statics  of  liquids,  54,  91,  96 ;  his  ex- 
periments in  liquid  pressure,  99; 
his  paradox,  ioz-102 ;  his  great  pi- 
ety, 447 ;  criticism  of  his  deduction 
of  the  hydrostatic  principle,  95-96 ; 
his  experiments  in  atmospheric 
pressure.  Z14  et  seqq. 

Peltier's  effect,  503. 

Pendulum,  motion  of,  153,  x<^,  x68; 
law  of  motion  of,  168 ;  experiments 
illustrative  of  motion  of,  168  et 
seqq.;  conical,  171;  determination 
of  ^  by,  172 ;  simple  and  compound, 
173*  'm\  cycloidal,  186;  a  falling, 
205;  ballistic,  328 ;  liquid,  409. 

Percussion,  see  Impact;   centre  of, 

327. 
Percussion-machine,  3x3. 
Perier,  115. 

Perpetual  motion,  25,  89,  500. 
Philosophy  of  the  specialist,  the,  506. 
Phoronomic  similarity,  166. 
Physics  and  theology,  separation  of, 

456. 

Physics,  arti6cial  division  of,  495 ; 
necessity  of  a  comparative,  498 ;  re- 
lations of  mechanics  to.  495-504 ; 
disproportionate  formal  develop- 
ment of,  505. 

Physiology,  relations  of  mechanics 


to,  504-507;  distinguished  from 
physics,  507. 

Pila  Heronis,  118,4x8. 

Place,  222,  226. 

Planck,  517. 

Planets,  motion  of,  187  et  seq. 

Plateau,  on  the  statics  of  liquids,  384 
'394*1  Plateau's  problem,  393. 

Poggendorfs  apparatus,  206  et  seq. 

Poinsot,  x86,  25X,  269, 480. 

Poisson,  42,  46. 

Polar  and  parallel  coordinates,  304. 

Poncelet,  251,  272. 

Popper,  J.,  5x6. 

Porta,  462. 

Poske,  on  the  law  of  inertia,  509. 

Potential,  xxo,  398  et  seqq.;  potential 
function,  497 ;  potential  energy,  499. 

Pound,  Imperial,  Troy,  Avoirdupois, 
283. 

Pre-established  harmony,  449. 

Pressure,  origin  of  the  notion  of,  84  \ 
liquid,  90,99  et  seqq.;  of  falling  bod- 
ies, 205 ;  hydrodynamic  and  hydro- 
static, 4x3;   of  liquids  in  motion, 

414. 
Pressure-bead,  403,  4x6. 

Principles,  their  general  character 
and  accidental  form,  79, 83, 431 ;  see 
Laws. 

Projectiles,  motion  of,  152  et  seqq.; 
treated  by  the  principle  of  least  ac- 
tion, 369. 

Projection,  obllqae,  153;   range  of, 

154. 
Proof,  the  natural  methods  of,  8a 
Ptolemy,  332, 
Pulleys,  81, 49-51* 
Pump,  1X3. 
Pythagoras,  433. 

Quantity,  of  matter,  2x6,  238 ;  of  mo- 
tion. 238,  37X  et  seqq. 
Quickest  descent,  curve  of,  436. 

Radii  vteiores^  394. 

Rationalism,  458. 

Reaction,  discussion  and  illoatration 
of  the  principle  of,  201-4x6;  criti- 
cism of  the  principle  of,  3x6-333; 
Newton  on,  196,  20X,  242. 

Reaction-tubes,  301. 


532 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MECHANICS. 


Reaction-wheels,  399  et  seqq. 

R^atimnr,  453. 

Reason,  sufficient,  principle  of,  9, 484, 

50a, 
Reconstruction  of  facts,  mental,  see 

Reproduction. 
RefiKurinK  of  facts  in  thought,  see 

Reproduction. 
Refraction,  economical  character  of 

law  of,  485. 
Regultt  Philoso^handi,  Newton's,  193. 
Regularity,  395. 
Religious  opinions,  Our,  464. 
Repos,  hide,  68. 
Representation,  see  Reproduction  of 

facts  in  thought. 
Reproduction  of  facts  in  thought,  5, 

84,  421.  481  494. 
Research,  means  and  aims  of,  distin- 
guished, 507. 
Resistance  head,  417. 
Rest,  Maupertuis's  law  of,  68,  259. 
Resultant  of  force,  34. 
Richer,  161,  251. 
Riemann,  493. 
Roberval,  his  balance,  60;  his  method 

of  maxima  and  minima.   423:   on 

momenta,  305  ;  on  the  composition 

of  forces,  197. 
Robins,  330. 
Routh,  352. 

Routine  methods,  181,  268,  287,  341, 
Rules,  83.  483;  the  testing  of,  81. 

Sail  filled  with  wind,  curve  of,  431. 

Scheffler,  353,  364. 

Schopenhauer,  on  causality,  484. 

Science,  the  nature  and  development 

■  of,  1-7 ;  the  origin  of,  4,  8,  78 ;  de- 
ductive and  formal  development  of, 
421  ;  physical,  its  pretensions  and 
attitude  464  et  seq.;  the  economy 
of,  481  494  ;  a  minimal  problem, 
490 ;  the  object  of,  496,  497,  502.  507; 
means  and  aims  of.  should  be  dis- 
tinguished, 504,  505 ;  condition  of 
the  true  development  of,  504  ;  divi- 
sion of  labor  in,  505 ;  tools  and  in- 
struments of,  505. 

Science  and  theology,  conflict  of,  446; 
their  points  of  identity,  460. 


Scientists,  struggle  of,  with  their  own 
preconceived  ideas,  447. 

Seebeck's  phenomenon,  503. 

Segner,  186;  Segncr's  wheel,  309. 

Sensations,  analysis  of,  464  ;  the  ele- 
ments of  nature,  482 ;  their  relative 
realness,  506. 

Shortest  line,  369,  371. 

Similarity,  phoronomic,  166. 

Similitude,  the  principle  of,  166,  177. 

Siphon,  114  et  seqq. 

Space,  Newton  on,  226;  absolute  and 
relative,  226,  232;  a  set  of  sensa- 
tions, 506;  multi-dimensioned,  an 
artifice  of  thought,  493. 

Spannkraft,  499. 

Specific  gravity,  87-88. 

Sphere,   rolling  on  inclined   plane, 

346. 

Spiritism,  or  spiritualism,  49 

Stable  equilibrium,  70-71. 

Stage  of  thought,  the,  505. 

Statical  manometer,  123. 

Statical  moment,  14  ;  possible  origin 
of  the  idea,  21. 

Statics,  deduction  of  its  principles 
from  hydrostatics,  107  et  seqq.;  the 
development  of  the  principles  of, 
8  127 ;  retrospect  of  the  develop- 
ment of,  77  85 ;  the  principles  of» 
applied  to  fluids,  86  no;  the  prin- 
ciples of,applied  to  gaseous  bodies, 
no  127;  Varignon's  dynamical,  38, 
368 ;  analytical,  founded  by  La- 
grange on  the  principle  of  virtual 
velocities,  467. 

Stevinus,  his  deduction  of  the  law  of 
the  inclined  plane,  24-31 ;  his  ex- 
planation of  the  other  machines  by 
thc  inclined  plane,  31-33;  the  par- 
allelogram of  forces  derived  from 
his  principle,  32-35  ;  his  discovery 
of  the  germ  of  the  principle  of  vir- 
tual velocities,49-5i;  his  researches 
in  hydrostatics,  88-90;  his  broad 
view  of  nature,  500. 

Strata,  parallelism  of,  409. 

Streintz,  510  et  seqq. 

String,  equilibrium  of  a,  372  et  seqq.; 
see  Catenary. 

Strings,   equilibrium  of  three>knotr 


\ 


INDEX. 


533 


ted,  6i ;  equilibrium  of  ramifying, 

33- 
Suction,  113. 
Sufficient  reason,  the  principle  of,  9, 

484,  502. 
Surface  of  liquids,  connection  of,  with 

equilibrium,  386-390. 
Surfaces,  isothermal,  400;  level,  98, 

398  et  seqq. 
Symmetry  of  liquid  films  explained, 

394. 
Synoptical  critique  of  the  Newtonian 

enunciations.  238-245. 
Synthetic  method,  466. 

Tangents,  method  of.  423. 

Taylor,  Brook,  on  the  centre  of  os- 
cillation, 335. 

Teleology,  or  evidences  of  design  in 
nature.  452. 

Theological  points  of  view  in  me- 
chanics, 446  et  seqq.;  inclinations 
of  great  physicists,  450. 

Theology  and  science,  conflict  of,  446; 
their  points  of  identity,  460. 

Theorems,  421. 

Theories.  491  et  seqq. 

Thermometers,  their  construction, 
282. 

Things,  their  nature,  482 ;  things  of 
thought,  492  et  seqq. 

Thomson  and  Tait.  their  opinion  of 
Newton's  laws,  245. 

Thought,  instruments  of,  505 ;  things 
of,  492  et  seqq.;  economy  of,  see 
Economy. 

Tides,  Newton  on,  209  et  seq.;  their 
effect  on  the  armyof  Alexander  the 
Great,  909;  explanation  of,  213  et 
seq.;  their  action  illustrated  by  an 
experiment,  215. 

Time,  511;  a  set  of  sensations,  506; 
Newton's  view  of,  222-^38;  abso- 
lute and  relative,  222;  nature  of, 
223-226,  234. 

Toeppler  and  Foucault,  optical 
method  of,  225. 

Torricclli,  his  modification  of  Gali- 
leo's deduction  of  the  law  of  the 
inclined  plane,  52;  his  measure- 
ment of  the  weight  of  the  atmos- 


phere, 113;  founds  dynamics,  402 ; 
his  vacuum  experiment,  113;  founds 
hydrodynamics,  402;  on  the  velo- 
city of  liquid  efflux,  402. 

Trade  winds,  302. 

Trades  and  classes,  function  of,  in  the 
development  of  science,  4. 

Tubes,  motion  of  liquids  in,  416  et 
seqq. 

Tylor,  462,  463. 

Ubaldi,  Guido,  his  statical  re- 
searches, 21. 
Uniquely  determined,  zo,  502. 
Unitary  conception  of  nature,  5. 
Units.  269-286. 
Unstable  equilibrium,  70-71. 

Vacuum,  112  et  seqq. 

Variation,  of  curve-elements,  433  et 
seqq. 

Variations,  calculus  of,  436  et  seqq. 

Varignon,  enunciates  the  principle  of 
the  parallelogram  of  forces,  36;  011 
the  simple  machines,  37 ;  his  statics 
a  dynamical  statics,  38;  on  velocity 
of  liquid  efflux,  403. 

Vas  tM^rficiaritiin  of  Stevinus,  89. 

Vehicle  on  wheels,  291. 

Velocity,  144;  angular,  396;  a  phys- 
ical level,  325. 

Velocity-head,  4x7. 

Vibration,  see  Oscillation. 

View,  breadth  of,  possessed  by  all 
great  inquirers.  500  et  seq. 

Vinci,  Leonardo  Da,  on  the  law  of 
the  lever,  30. 

Virtual  displacements,  definition  of, 
37 ;  see  also  Virtual  velocities. 

Virtual  moments,  57. 

Virtual  velocities,  origin  and  mean- 
ing of  the  term,  49;  the  principle 
of,  49-77. 

Viscosity  of  liquids,  416.         * 

Vii  mortua^  272,  275. 

Vii  viva,  272  et  seqq.,  315  ;  conserva- 
tion of,  317,  interpreted,  326;  in  im- 
pact, 323  et  seqq.;  principle  of,  343- 
350 ;  connection  of  Huygens' s  prin^ 
ciple  with,  178;  principle  of.  de- 
duced from  Lagrange's  fundamen- 
tal equations,  478,  4S)9. 


534 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  MEClfANICS. 


Vitnivius,  on  the  nature  of  sound,  3 ; 
his  accouut  of  Archimedes' s  dis- 
covery, 86;  on  ancient  air-instru- 
ments, xia 

Viviani,  113. 

Voltaire,  449,  454. 

Volume  of  liquids,  connection  of 
with  equilibrium,  387-390. 

Wallis,  on  impact,  313 ;  on  the  centre 

of  percussion,  327. 
Water,  compressibility  of,  93. 
Weightless  liquids,  384  et  seqq. 
Weights  and  measures,  see  Units. 
Weston,  differential  pulley  of,  59. 
Whcatstone,  chronoscope  of,  151. 
Wheel  and  axle,  with  non-circular 

wheel,  72 ;  motion  of,  22  et  seq.,  60, 

337.  344.  354.  381. 
Will,  conception  of,  in  nature,  461. 
Wire  frames,  Plateau's,  393. 


Wohlwill,  on  the  law  of  inertia,  306. 

509. 
Wood,  on  the  cells  of  the  honeycomb, 

453. 

Woodhouse,  on  isoperimetrical  prob- 
lems, 430. 

Work,  54,  67  et  seq.,  248  et  seq.,  363; 
definition  of,  272;  determinative  of 
vi»  viva^  178;  accidentally  not  the 
original  concept  of  mechanics,  54S: 
J.  R.  Mayer's  views  of,  249;  Hay- 
gens'  s  appreciation  of.  252,  27a ;  in 
impact,  322  et  seqq.;  of  molecular 
forces  in  liquids,  385  et  seqq.;  posi- 
tive and  negative,  386;  of  liquid 
forces  of  pressure,  415;  of  com- 
pression, 407. 

Wren,  on  impact,  313. 

Wright,  Chauncey,  453. 

Yard,  Imperial,  281;  American.  283. 


THE  OPEN  COURT 

A  WEEKLY  MAGAZINE 
DEVOTED  TO  THE  RELIGION  OF  SCIENCE 


THE  OPEN  COURT  does  Dot  understand  by  religion 
any  creed  or  dogmatic  belief,  but  man*8  world-conception  in 
so  far  as  it  regulates  his  conduct. 

The  old  dogmatic  conception  of  religion  is  based  u{)on  the 
science  of  past  ages;  to  base  religion  upon  the  maturest  and 
truest  thought  of  the  present  time  is  the  object  of  The  Open 
Court.  Thus,  the  religion  of  The  Open  Court  is  the  Religion 
of  Science,  that  is  the  religion  of  verified  and  verifiable  truth. 

Although  opposed  to  irrational  orthodoxy  and  narrow 
bigotry,  Tlie  Open  Court  does  not  attack  the  properly  religious 
element  of  the  various  religions.  It  criticises  their  errors  un- 
fiinchingly  but  without  animosity,  and  it  endeavors  to  preserve 
of  them  all  that  is  true  and  good. 

The  current  numbers  of  The  Open  Court  contain  valuable 
original  articles  from  the  pens  of  distinguished  thinkers. 
Accurate  and  authorized  translations  are  made  in  Philosophy, 
Science,  and  Criticism  from  the  periodical  literature  of  Conti- 
nental Europe,  and  reviews  of  noteworthy  recent  investigations 
are  prjBsented. 

Terms :  Two  dollars  a  year  throughout  the  Postal  Union. 
Single  Copies,  5  cents. 


THE  MONIST 

A  QUARTERLY  MAGAZINE  OF 
PHILOSOPHY    AND   SCIENCE 


THE  MONIST  discusses  the  fundamental  problems  of 
Philosophy  in  their  practical  bearings  upon  the  religious, 
ethical,  and  sociological  questions  of  the  day. 

Among  its  contributors  are :  Charles  S.  Peirce,  Prof. 
Joseph  Le  Conte,  Dr.  W.  T.  Harris,  Prof  E.  D.  Cope,  M.  D. 
Conwav,  Prof.  F.  Max  Mailer,  Prof.  0.  J.  Romanes,  Prof.  C. 
Lloyd  Morgan,  James  Sully,  B.  Bosanquet,  Dr.  A.  Binet,  Prof. 
C.  Lombroeo,  Prof.  E.  Mach,  Prof.  F. JckII,  Prof.  Ernst  Haeckel, 
Prof.  H.  Hoffding,  Dr.  F.  Oswald,  Dr.  Emil  Hirsch,  Prof.  J. 
Delboeuf,  E.  de  l5>berty. 

Per  Copy.  50  Cents ;  Yearly  $2.00.  In  England,  and  all 
countries  in  U.  P.  U.  Per  Copy  2s.  6d;  Yearly  98.  6d. 

CHICAGO  :  LONDON  : 

The  Open  Court  Pub.  Co.  Messrs.  Watts  &  Co. 

324  Dearborn  Street  17  Johnson's  Court,  Fleet  St.,  E.G.